IN THE COURT OF CRIMINAL APPEALS
OF TEXAS
NO. PD-1123-19
Ex parte CHARLES BARTON, Appellant
ON STATE’S PETITION FOR DISCRETIONARY REVIEW
FROM THE SECOND COURT OF APPEALS
TARRANT COUNTY
KELLER, P.J., filed a dissenting opinion in which KEEL, J., joined.
Suppose a citizen, unhappy with an opinion from this Court, sent repeated emails to a group
of like-minded citizens, saying “Texas is in trouble” and “This is arguably the most devastating ruling
I have ever received from a court” and “It’s time to get serious and get on the phone, write letters, etc
to EVERYONE YOU KNOW to make them aware of what’s happening. Name names on this court!
If this stands we lose Texas. It’s do or die this time.” Has that citizen committed a crime? Under the
Court’s decision today, the answer is “Yes.” At the risk of being prosecuted myself for violating §
42.07(a)(7) of the Texas Penal Code, let me say here that the people of Texas should be alarmed by
this holding.
The Court holds today that the “electronic communications” subsection of the Texas
BARTON DISSENT— 2
harassment statute “does not implicate the First Amendment’s freedom of speech protections”
because the conduct that it regulates is non-speech conduct. I cannot agree. The term “electronic
communications” alone suggests that the regulated conduct is speech, but the statutory definition of
the term makes it clear that the regulated conduct is indeed speech. The statute defines “electronic
communications” broadly, and the mens rea of the statute includes intent to “annoy,” “alarm,” or
“embarrass” another. The statute encompasses a vast amount of speech that is protected by the First
Amendment. And although I have been critical of Scott v. State1 in the past, the statute in this case
is far broader than the telephone harassment statute, and we need not overrule Scott to find the statute
here to be unconstitutional.
Section 42.07(a)(7) provides that a person commits an offense if:
with intent to harass, annoy, alarm, abuse, torment, or embarrass another, he. . . sends
repeated electronic communications in a manner reasonably likely to harass, annoy,
alarm, abuse, torment, embarrass, or offend another.2
“Electronic communication” is defined expansively to mean:
a transfer of signs, signals, writing, images, sounds, data, or intelligence of any nature
transmitted in whole or in part by a wire, radio, electromagnetic, photoelectronic, or
photo-optical system.3
“Electronic communication” includes“a communication initiated by electronic mail, instant message,
network call, communication tool, or a facsimile machine”4 and “a communication made to a pager.”5
1
322 S.W.3d 662 (Tex. Crim. App. 2010).
2
TEX. PENAL CODE § 42.07(a)(7) (2011).
3
Id. § 42.07(b)(1).
4
Id. § 42.07(b)(1)(A).
5
Id. § 42.07(b)(2)(B).
BARTON DISSENT— 3
A transfer of signals, writing, images, sounds, or data by an “electromagnetic system” necessarily
includes use of the internet. While the telephone harassment statute was limited to communications
over the telephone, the electronic-communications statute is much more expansive, encompassing
anything that could be thought of as an electronic communication.
But the breadth of the electronic-communications statute does not derive solely from the
variety of electronic devices that may deliver communications or the variety of formats in which
communications may occur. It also derives from the scope of the intended audience. Telephone
conversations are, at least most of the time, limited to one individual communicating with another.
But the internet opens up very public avenues of communication. Message boards, blogs, and
internet news articles can be seen by the entire world. Depending on the privacy settings, Facebook
posts can be seen by a large assortment of people. Then there are Twitter, Instagram, Snapchat, Tik
Tok, and many other social networking platforms.
Since most communications over the phone are one-on-one, they are in some sense private,
and although there are ways to block at least some types of unwanted calls, in some sense a telephone
user might be considered a “captive audience” for harassing telephone communications. Privacy and
“captive audience” rationales might allow for greater leeway in regulating telephone
communications.6 But when those rationales are absent, we should be especially leery of punishing
speech. As the Supreme Court explained in Cohen v. California: “The ability of government,
consonant with the Constitution, to shut off discourse solely to protect others from hearing it is . . .
dependent upon a showing that substantial privacy interests are being invaded in an essentially
6
See Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 21-22 (1971) (referring to “substantial privacy
interests . . . being invaded in an essentially intolerable manner” and “the special plight of the captive
auditor”).
BARTON DISSENT— 4
intolerable manner. Any broader view of this authority would effectively empower a majority to
silence dissidents simply as a matter of personal predilections.”7
The Court suggests that we need not reach the issue of whether the statute can be upheld under
the Cohen privacy rationale because the electronic-communications statute is not aimed at speech.
I disagree. The Court begins with the fact that it is possible to find some kernel of expression in
almost every activity a person undertakes. But the electronic-communications statute is not
concerned with just any activity—it is concerned with communications. And the “electronic” methods
of delivering communications—including the internet and social media platforms—are mediums for
delivering speech. Given the inherently communicative aspect of electronic communications, at least
as a general matter, the Court errs to engage in an analysis of whether otherwise non-speech conduct
constitutes expression.8 The “intent to convey a particularized message” test for determining whether
conduct that is ordinarily non-speech is actually expressive has no application to something that is
ordinarily speech or expression.9
The Court makes much of the fact that the electronic-communications statute encompasses
the mere sending of data, and it concludes that the repeated sending of data could be meaningless to
an individual. Someone could send emails to flood another person’s inbox. The emails could contain
meaningless gibberish. But it is not enough to say that it is possible to violate a statute by conduct
7
Id. at 21.
8
See Ex parte Thompson, 442 S.W.3d 325, 334-36 (Tex. Crim. App. 2014) (no intent to
convey a particularized message required for inherently expressive conduct such as parades,
paintings, and photographs) (discussing Hurley v. Irish–American Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Group,
515 U.S. 557 (1995)).
9
Id.
BARTON DISSENT— 5
that does not implicate the First Amendment, if under an overbreadth analysis, the statute reaches a
substantial amount of First Amendment conduct in relation to its legitimate sweep.10
In Thornhill v. Alabama, for example, an anti-loitering statute made it an offense to loiter
around or picket a business with intent to influence or induce others not to patronize the business.11
Under the language of the Alabama statute, it appears that a criminal violation could occur if a person
physically blocked entry into a business. Physically blocking entry would not be speech protected
under the First Amendment. But the Supreme Court nevertheless found the statute to be overbroad
because its language “comprehend[ed] every practicable method whereby the facts of a labor dispute
may be publicized in the vicinity of the place of business of an employer.”12
And in State v. Johnson, we acknowledged that “intentionally or knowingly damaging a
United States flag is not inherently expressive” and that “a statute that proscribes such conduct will
10
See See Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U.S. 88, 91, 99-100 (1940) (loitering/picketing at a
business); State v. Johnson, 475 S.W.3d 860, 873 (Tex. Crim. App. 2015) (flag desecration).
11
Thornhill, supra at 91. Specifically, the Alabama statute provided that it was an offense
to:
go near to or loiter about the premises or place of business of any other person, firm,
corporation, or association of people, engaged in a lawful business, for the purpose,
or with intent of influencing, or inducing other persons not to trade with, buy from,
sell to, have business dealings with, or be employed by such persons, firm,
corporation, or association, or . . . [to] picket the works or place of business of such
other persons, firms, corporations, or associations of persons, for the purpose of
hindering, delaying, or interfering with or injuring any lawful business or enterprise
of another.
Id.
12
Id. at 100.
BARTON DISSENT— 6
at least theoretically apply to some circumstances that do not implicate the First Amendment.”13 But
we pointed out that “[m]ost conduct that falls within the provisions of the statute and that would come
to the attention of the authorities would constitute protected expression.”14 We concluded that the
flag desecration statute was unconstitutionally overbroad because it, “by its text and in actual fact,
prohibit[ed] a substantial amount of activity that is protected by the First Amendment, judged in
relation to its legitimate sweep.”15
If we look at the electronic-communications statute’s actual sweep, we can see that its
language encompasses a truly enormous amount of speech. This is so even accounting for the
requisite intent to harass, annoy, alarm, abuse, torment, or embarrass. As the examples at the
beginning of this opinion illustrate, alarming someone could be the point of the communication. And
so could annoying and embarrassing. One can look as far back as the parable of the unjust judge in
the Bible to see an example of a persistent woman who finally gets relief from an unjust judge so that
she will stop bothering him.16 As for intent to embarrass, one could look to Andrew Breitbart’s
disclosure of Anthony Weiner’s indiscretions and Breitbart’s subsequent follow-ups on that story.17
Often, the intent specified in the statute will be a legitimate purpose of the communication. The First
13
Johnson, 475 S.W.3d at 873.
14
Id. at 876.
15
Id. at 882.
16
Luke 18:1-5.
17
See https://www.npr.org/2011/06/07/137042268/looking-at-breitbarts-role-in-weiners-
scandal.
BARTON DISSENT— 7
Amendment protects a great deal of speech that is purposefully annoying, alarming, or embarrassing.18
What about the Scott case? First, Scott said that the harassing phone calls would be essentially
noncommunicative “in the usual case.”19 Scott did not hold that the harassing conduct at issue was
inherently nonspeech; it held that it was usually nonspeech.20 But the “usual case” in Scott was based
narrowly on the use of a telephone, which ordinarily involves a private one-on-one communication.
The electronic-communications statute is much broader, involving not only myriad different methods
of conveying electronic communications but also involving an expanded audience—in many cases
including everyone who has access to the internet or to a particular social media app.
Moreover, the Scott opinion explicitly contemplated that the recipient of the call would be the
18
See Coates v. City of Cincinnati, 402 U.S. 611, 615 (1971) (“The First and Fourteenth
Amendments do not permit a State to make criminal the exercise of the right of assembly simply
because its exercise may be ‘annoying’ to some people. If this were not the rule, the right of the
people to gather in public places for social or political purposes would be continually subject to
summary suspension through the good-faith enforcement of a prohibition against annoying
conduct.”); Long v. State, 931 S.W.2d 285, 290 n.4 (Tex. Crim. App. 1996) (“The First Amendment
does not permit the outlawing of conduct merely because the speaker intends to annoy the listener
and a reasonable person would in fact be annoyed. Many legitimate political protests, for example,
contain both of these elements.”).
19
322 S.W.3d at 669-70 (saying it twice).
20
Scott did not create an alternative holding when it held that harassing phone calls under
the statute were not protected by the First Amendment because the conduct invaded privacy interests
in an intolerable manner. Rather, it created a supplemental holding—that in the “not usual” case the
conduct was still not protected by the First Amendment because the conduct was an intolerable
intrusion on privacy. See id. at 670 (“To the extent that the statutory subsection is susceptible of
application to communicative conduct, it is susceptible of such application only when that
communicative conduct is not protected by the First Amendment because, under the circumstances
presented, that communicative conduct invades the substantial privacy interests of another (the
victim) in an essentially intolerable manner.”).
BARTON DISSENT— 8
target of the actor’s intent to harass, annoy, alarm, abuse, torment, or embarrass.21 But with many
forms of electronic communications—e.g. an internet news article, a blog post, a message board post,
or a social media post—there will usually be a great number of recipients of the communication who
are not targets of the actor’s harassing intent. In fact, it would often be unnecessary for the target of
the actor’s intent to even receive or read the electronic communication. When information about the
target is disclosed in such a public manner, and when that information is what causes the target to be
embarrassed or annoyed or alarmed, that information is speech.
And our later opinion in Wilson v. State22 retreated from Scott in two respects: (1) by rejecting
the notion that the term “repeated” was limited to situations that could be termed a single criminal
episode,23 and (2) by rejecting the notion that a facially legitimate purpose for a call negated having
the requisite intent to harass, annoy, alarm, abuse, torment, or embarrass.24 Even if the Wilson
opinion’s retreat in these two respects did not ultimately invalidate the conclusion in Scott, that retreat
undermines any extension of the reasoning in Scott to the broader electronic-communications statute.
I strongly disagree with the Court’s conclusion that the electronic-communications statute
does not implicate the First Amendment. It follows that I also disagree with the Court’s conclusion
that the rational basis test provides the appropriate framework for evaluating the constitutionality of
the statute. I would conduct an overbreadth analysis under the First Amendment and resolve whether
21
Id. at 669 (“First, the text requires that the actor have the specific intent to harass, annoy,
alarm, abuse, torment, or embarrass the recipient of the telephone call.”).
22
448 S.W.3d 418 (Tex. Crim. App. 2014).
23
Id. at 422-24.
24
Id. at 425-26.
BARTON DISSENT— 9
the statute punishes a substantial amount of protected speech in relation to its legitimate sweep.
Because the Court does not answer that question, I will say here only that the breadth of the statute
convinces me that the answer is “yes.”
I respectfully dissent.
Filed: April 6, 2022
Publish