F IL E D
United States Court of Appeals
Tenth Circuit
PUBLISH September 4, 2007
Elisabeth A. Shumaker
U N IT E D ST A T E S C O U R T O F A P PE A L S Clerk of Court
T E N T H C IR C U IT
LA W REN CE G O LA N ; ESTA TE OF
R ICHA RD K A PP; S.A . PU BLISHING
C O, IN C., d/b/a ESS.A .Y .
R ECOR DIN G S; SY M PH O N Y OF THE
CANYONS; RON HALL d/b/a
FESTIV AL FILM S; and JO H N
M cDONOUGH, d/b/a TIM ELESS
VIDEO ALTERN ATIVES
IN TERNATIO NAL,
Plaintiffs-Appellants,
v.
No. 05-1259
ALBERTO R. GONZALES, in his
official capacity as Attorney General of
the United States; and M AR YB ETH
PETERS, Register of Copyrights,
Copyright Office of the
United States,
Defendants-Appellees,
IN TER NATIO N A L C OA LITIO N FOR
COPYRIG HT PROTECTIO N,
Amicus Curiae.
A ppeal from the U nited States D istrict C ourt
for the D istrict of C olorado
(D .C . N o. 1:01-cv-01854 L T B -B N B )
Lawrence Lessig, Center for Internet and Society, Stanford Law School, Stanford,
California (Hugh Q. Gottschalk and Carolyn J. Fairless, W heeler Trigg Kennedy
LLP, Denver, Colorado, with him on the briefs), for Plaintiffs-Appellants.
John S. Koppel, Appellate Staff Civil Division (Peter D. Keisler, Assistant
Attorney General, W illiam J. Leone, United States A ttorney, and W illiam Kanter,
Appellate Staff Civil Division, W ashington, D.C., with him on the brief), for
Defendants-Appellees.
Eric M . Lieberman and David B. Goldstein, Rabinowitz, Boudin, Standard,
Krinsky & Lieberman, P.C., New York, New York, filed an Amicus Curiae brief
in support of Defendants-A ppellees.
Before H E N R Y , B R ISC O E , and L U C E R O , Circuit Judges.
H E N R Y , Circuit Judge.
Plaintiffs in this case range from orchestra conductors, educators,
performers, and publishers to film archivists and motion picture distributors. They
challenge two acts of Congress, the Copyright Term Extension Act (“CTEA”),
Pub. L. No. 105-298, §§ 102(b) and (d), 112 Stat. 2827-28 (1998) (amending 17
U.S.C. §§ 302, 304), and § 514 of the U ruguay Round Agreements Act (“URAA”),
Pub. L. No. 103-465, 108 Stat. 4809, 4976-80 (1994), codified at 17 U.S.C. §§
104A, 1 109.
1
Section 104A provides in the pertinent part:
(a) A utomatic protection and term.–
(continued...)
2
Also known as the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, the CTEA
increased the duration of existing and future copyrights from life-plus-50-years to
life-plus-70-years. Section 514 of the URAA implements Article 18 of the Berne
Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic works. Ushered into being
in 1886 at the behest of Association Littéraire et Artistique Internationale, an
organization founded by Victor Hugo and dedicated to obtaining protection for
literary and artistic w orks, the Berne Convention requires member countries to
afford the same copyright protection to foreign authors as they provide their own
authors. In this case, congressional compliance with the Berne Convention meant
1
(...continued)
(1) Term.
(A) Copyright subsists, in accordance with this section, in restored works, and
vests automatically on the date of restoration.
. . . .
(h) D efinitions. For purposes of this section and section 109(a):
. . . .
(6) The term “restored work” means an original work of authorship that–
(A) is protected under subsection (a);
(B) is not in the public domain in its source country through expiration of term
of protection;
(C) is in the public domain in the United States due to–
(I) noncompliance with formalities imposed at any time by United
States copyright law, including failure of renewal, lack of proper notice,
or failure to comply with any manufacturing requirements; (ii) lack of
subject m atter protection in the case of sound recordings fixed before
February 15, 1972; or (iii) lack of national eligibility; and
(D) has at least one author or rightholder who was, at the time the work was
created, a national or domiciliary of an eligible country, and if published was
first published in an eligible country and not published in the United States
during the 30-day period following publication in such eligible country.
3
copyrighting some foreign works in the public domain. 2
Plaintiffs argue the CTEA extends existing copyrights in violation of the
“limited Times” provision of the Constitution’s C opyright Clause. With regard to
the URAA, plaintiffs contend § 514 shrinks the public domain and thereby
violates the limitations on congressional power inherent in the Copyright Clause.
In addition, plaintiffs argue that § 514’s removal of works from the public domain
interferes with their First A mendment right to free expression.
The district court dismissed plaintiffs’ CTEA claim and granted summary
judgment for the government on plaintiffs’ URAA challenges. W e exercise
jurisdiction pursuant to 28 U.S.C. § 1291 and affirm the district court’s dismissal
of the CTEA claim as foreclosed by the Supreme Court’s decision in Eldred v.
Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003). W e also agree with the district court that § 514 of
the URAA has not exceeded the limitations inherent in the Copyright Clause.
Nevertheless, we hold that plaintiffs have shown sufficient free expression
interests in works removed from the public domain to require First Amendment
2
Article 18 of the Berne Convention provides in the pertinent part:
(1) T his Convention shall apply to all works which, at the mom ent of
its coming into force, have not yet fallen into the public domain in the
country of origin through the expiry of the term of protection.
(2) If, however, through the expiry of the term of protection which was
previously granted, a work has fallen into the public domain, of the
country where the protection is claimed, that work shall not be
protected anew [.]
4
scrutiny of § 514. On this limited basis, we remand for proceedings consistent
with this opinion.
I. B A C K G R O U N D
Each plaintiff in this case relies on artistic works in the public domain for
his or her livelihood. Lawrence Golan, for example, performs and teaches works
by foreign composers including Dmitri Shostakovich and Igor Stravinsky. Before
the CTEA, plaintiffs anticipated that certain works would soon outlive copyright
protection and enter the public domain. The CTEA delayed this moment by 20
years. Prior to the URAA, each plaintiff utilized or performed works by foreign
artists in the public domain, such as Sergei Prokofiev’s renowned “Peter and the
W olf.” Since the passage of the URAA, plaintiffs must pay higher performance
fees and sheet music rentals as well as other royalties. In many cases, these costs
are prohibitive.
Plaintiffs filed suit in the United States District Court for the District of
Colorado arguing that both the CTEA and the URAA are unconstitutional. The
court concluded the Supreme Court’s decision in Eldred precluded plaintiffs’
challenge to the CTEA and granted summary judgment to the government on
plaintiffs’ two URAA claims. Golan v. Ashcroft, 310 F. Supp. 2d 1215, 1218 (D .
Colo. 2004). Reasoning that “C ongress has historically demonstrated little
compunction about removing copyrightable materials from the public domain,” the
5
district court ruled that Congress had the power to enact § 514 of the URAA under
the Copyright Clause. Golan v. Gonzales, No. Civ. 01-B-1854(BNB), 2005 W L
914754, at *14 (D. Colo. Aug. 24, 2005). The court also granted summary
judgment on plaintiffs’ First Amendment claim, on the theory they had no
protected interest in the now-copyrighted works. This appeal followed.
II. ST A N D A R D O F R E V IE W
W e review de novo a district court’s grant of summary judgment. Steffy v.
Orman, 461 F.3d 1218, 1221 (10th Cir. 2006). Summary judgment is appropriate
only when “there is no genuine issue as to any material fact.” F ED . R. C IV . P.
56(c). W e also examine de novo the district court’s conclusions regarding the
Constitution. O’Connor v. Washburn Univ., 416 F.3d 1216, 1223 (10th Cir.
2005). “[I]t is also appropriate to bear in mind . . . that in the enactment of a
statute Congress is presumed to act with knowledge of controlling constitutional
limitations or proscriptions and with an intent and purpose to avoid their
contravention.” Wells, by Gillig, v. Att’y General of the United States, 201 F.2d
556, 560 (10th Cir. 1953); see also INS v. Chadha, 462 U.S. 919, 944 (1983) (“W e
begin . . . with the presumption that the challenged statute is valid.”).
III. D ISC USSIO N
Plaintiffs claim that the CTEA’s 20-year extension of existing copyrights
violates the Copyright Clause’s “limited Times” provision. In addition, they
6
contend that the URAA’s removal of works from the public domain exceeds the
authority granted to Congress under the Copyright Clause. Finally, plaintiffs
maintain that § 514 of the URAA must be subject to First Amendment review
because it has altered the traditional contours of copyright protection. Since
familiarity with the foundations of copyright law is crucial to understanding the
dispute, we begin with an outline of basic copyright principles.
Under the Copyright Clause, Congress may “promote the Progress of
Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors . . . the
exclusive Right to their W ritings.” U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 8. The Supreme
Court has explained that “[the Clause] is intended to motivate the creative activity
of authors and inventors by the provision of a special reward, and to allow the
public access to the products of their genius after the limited period of exclusive
control has expired.” Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S.
417, 429 (1984). By encouraging creative expression through limited monopolies,
the Copyright Clause “promot[es] broad public availability of literature, music,
and the other arts.” Twentieth Century M usic Corp. v. Aiken, 422 U.S. 151, 156
(1975). “[O]nce the . . . copyright monopoly has expired, the public may use the .
. . work at will and without attribution.” Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox
Film Corp., 539 U.S. 23, 33-34 (2003). These imaginative works inspire new
creations, which in turn inspire others, hopefully, ad infinitum. This cycle is what
7
makes copyright “the engine of free expression.” Harper & Row Publishers Inc.
v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 558 (1985).
Congress’s power to bestow copyrights is broad. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at
205 (“[I]t is Congress that has been assigned the task of defining the scope of the
limited monopoly that should be granted to authors . . . in order to give the public
appropriate access to their work product.”) (internal quotation marks omitted).
But it is not boundless. The Copyright Clause itself limits Congress’s power as to
what kinds of works can be copyrighted and for how long. For instance, in order
to be copyrightable, a work must be original. Feist Publ’ns, Inc. v. Rural Tel.
Serv. Co., 499 U.S. 340, 345 (1991) (“The sine qua non of copyright is originality
. . . . Originality is a constitutional requirement.”). In addition, a copyright must
be limited in duration. Dastar, 539 U.S. at 37 (noting that Congress cannot
“create[] a species of perpetual . . . copyright”). The rationale underlying this
limitation is that an infinite copyright would deprive the public of the benefit – the
right to use and enjoy the expression – that it is supposed to receive in exchange
for the grant of monopoly privileges to the author for a discrete period of time.
See id. at 33-34 (“The rights of a . . . copyright holder are part of a carefully
crafted bargain under which, once the . . . copyright monopoly has expired, the
public may use the . . . work at will and without attribution.”) (internal citation
and quotation marks omitted).
8
The Supreme Court has recognized that the First A mendment can limit
Congress’s power under the Copyright Clause. Eldred, 537 U.S. at 219-21
(indicating that copyright acts are not “categorically immune from challenges
under the First Amendment”) (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court has
emphasized, however, that “copyright’s built-in First Amendment
accommodations” – the idea/expression dichotomy and the fair use defense –
generally protect the public’s First Amendment interest in copyrighted works. Id.
at 219-20.
The first of these “built-in safeguards,” the idea/expression dichotomy,
denies copyright protection “to any idea, procedure, process, system, method of
operation, concept, principle, or discovery, regardless of the form in which it is
described, explained, illustrated, or embodied in [a copyrighted] work.” 17 U.S.C.
§ 102(b). It reserves to authors, however, the right to exploit their “expression,”
id., a term that refers to “the particular pattern of words, lines and colors, or
musical notes” that comprise a work. R OBERT A. G ORMAN , C OPYRIGHT L AW 23
(2d ed. 2006).
The second safeguard, the fair use defense, allows the public to utilize a
copyrighted work “for purposes such as criticism, comment, news reporting,
teaching (including multiple copies for classroom use), scholarship, or research.”
17 U.S.C. § 107. The defense protects the public’s First Amendment interest in an
9
author’s original expression by “afford[ing] considerable latitude for scholarship
and comment, and even for parody.” Eldred, 537 U.S. at 220 (internal citations
and quotation marks omitted).
Although these built-in free speech safeguards w ill ordinarily insulate
legislation from First Amendment review, the Eldred Court indicated that such
review is warranted w hen an act of Congress has “altered the traditional contours
of copyright protection.” Id. at 221. The Court did not define the “traditional
contours of copyright protection.” However, as we discuss in detail below, one of
these traditional contours is the principle that once a work enters the public
domain, no individual – not even the creator – may copyright it.
W ith these principles in mind, we turn to plaintiffs’ challenges to the CTEA
and URAA.
A. T HE CTEA
The Copyright Clause provides: “The Congress shall have Power . . . To
promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to
Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to their respective W ritings and
Discoveries[.]” U.S. Const., art. I, § 8, cl. 8. Plaintiffs contend the CTEA
violates the “limited Times” prescription by increasing the term from life-plus-50-
years to life-plus-70-years. M ore specifically, they argue that “the Framers w ould
have considered the [life-plus-70] term to be so long as to be effectively
10
perpetual.” Aplts’ Br. at 55.
Analyzing the CTEA in light of the Clause’s inherent limitations, the
Supreme Court upheld the Act in Eldred. 537 U.S. at 194 (“[W]e reject
petitioners’ challenges to the CTEA. . . . Congress acted within its authority and
did not transgress constitutional limitations.”). Nevertheless, plaintiffs attempt to
distinguish Eldred, invoking the Court’s acknowledgment that “[p]etitioners [did]
not challenge the ‘life-plus-70-years’ timespan itself.” Id. at 193. Plaintiffs
therefore contend that Eldred does not foreclose the argument that the CTEA’s
extension of all future copyrights to a life-plus-70-years timespan violates the
Copyright Clause. Though plaintiffs may be correct that the Eldred Court did not
technically address this term, the rationale underlying Eldred compels us to
conclude that the CTEA-imposed timespan passes constitutional muster.
The Ninth Circuit recently upheld the dismissal of a nearly-identical CTEA
challenge in Kahle v. Gonzales, 487 F.3d 697 (9th Cir. 2007). The plaintiffs in
Kahle, like plaintiffs here, argued that the CTEA’s life-plus-70-years copyright
term violated the “limited Times” prescription because the Framers would have
viewed it as “effectively perpetual.” Id. at 699 (internal quotation marks omitted).
As the Ninth Circuit observed, the Eldred Court “clearly grasped the role ‘limited
Times’ play in the copyright scheme and the Framers’ understanding of that
phrase.” Id. at 700. Indeed, the Eldred Court emphasized that our constitutional
11
scheme charges Congress, and not federal courts, with “the task of defining the
scope of the limited monopoly that should be granted to authors.” 537 U.S. at 205
(internal quotation marks omitted). As the Kahle court reasoned, “the outer
boundary of ‘limited Times’ is determined by weighing the impetus provided to
authors by longer terms against the benefit provided to the public by shorter terms.
That weighing is left to Congress, subject to rationality review.” Kahle, 487 F.3d
at 701. This rationale is clearly consistent with Eldred. See 537 U.S. at 204
(reviewing the CTEA merely to determine “whether it is a rational exercise of the
legislative authority conferred by the copyright clause”).
W e agree with the Kahle court’s holding that Eldred precludes a challenge
to the 20-year term extension. See Eldred, 537 U.S. at 208 (“W e cannot conclude
that the CTEA – which continues the unbroken congressional practice of treating
future and existing copyrights in parity for term extension purposes – is an
impermissible exercise of Congress’ power under the Copyright Clause.”).
Plaintiffs here, like the plaintiffs in Kahle, “provide no compelling reason why w e
should depart from a recent Supreme Court decision.” Kahle, 487 F.3d at 701.
B. T HE URAA
Plaintiffs present two arguments regarding the constitutionality of § 514 of
the U RAA. First, they claim that § 514 exceeds the authority granted to Congress
in the Copyright Clause. Second, they maintain § 514 has disrupted the traditional
12
contours of copyright protection and thus demands First Amendment scrutiny. W e
begin with the contention that Congress has overstepped its Article I authority.
1. Section 514 does not violate the C opyright Clause
Plaintiffs ground their argument that § 514 transgresses the bounds of
Congress’s Article I authority in the text of the Copyright Clause. They contend
that § 514’s extension of copyright protection to works in the public domain
eviscerates any limitations imposed by the “limited Times” prescription and the
Progress Clause. In essence, plaintiffs aver that unless we hold that the Progress
Clause and the “limited Times” prescription prevent Congress from copyrighting
works in the public domain, Congress could adopt a practice of copyrighting
works as they fall into public domain. This would prevent the public from ever
gaining unfettered access to the expressions.
W e agree it would be troubling if Congress adopted a consistent practice of
restoring works in the public domain in an effort to confer perpetual monopolies.
But this argument is similar to one the Eldred plaintiffs raised, and, like the
Eldred Court, we are mindful that “a regime of perpetual copyrights is clearly not
the situation before us.” Eldred, 537 U.S. at 209.
Plaintiffs cite Graham v. John Deere Co., 383 U.S. 1 (1966), in support of
their contentions. There, the Supreme Court concluded that Congress could not
issue a patent when the invention had resided in the public domain before the
13
inventor had applied for the patent. For both their Progress Clause and “limited
Times” arguments, plaintiffs rely heavily on the Graham Court’s statement that
“Congress may not authorize the issuance of patents whose effects are to remove
existent knowledge from the public domain, or to restrict free access to materials
already available.” Id. at 6. Plaintiffs contend there is no meaningful distinction
between copyrights and patents that would prevent this court from applying
Graham here.
The D.C. Circuit confronted and rejected an identical argument in Luck’s
M usic Library, Inc. v. Gonzales, 407 F.3d 1262 (D.C. Cir. 2005), a case in which
the plaintiffs maintained that § 514’s copyright of works in the public domain
violated the Copyright Clause. In rejecting the contention, the D.C. Circuit noted
that
[Graham] dealt with patents rather than copyright, and the ideas
applicable to one do [not] automatically apply to the other. For
example, the Eldred Court saw the ‘quid pro quo’ idea as having a
special force in patent law, where the patentee, in exchange for
exclusive rights must disclose his ‘discoveries’ against his presumed
will. In contrast, the author is eager to disclose her w ork.
407 F.3d at 1266.
In addition to these distinctions, the Eldred Court observed that while
patents “prevent full use by others of the inventor’s knowledge,” “copyright gives
the holder no monopoly on any knowledge.” 537 U.S. at 217. W e further note
that the language plaintiffs cite from Graham is taken from a discussion about the
14
Progress Clause in the context of conditions for patentability. The sentence
following the one plaintiffs emphasize reads: “Innovation, advancement, and
things which add to the sum of useful knowledge are inherent requisites in a
patent system which by constitutional command must ‘promote the Progress of . . .
the useful Arts.’” Graham, 383 U.S. at 6 (emphasis supplied). In fact, the
Graham Court only mentioned copyright in a footnote w hen it explained that it
had omitted the copyright portion of the Patent and Copyright Clause because it
was “not relevant” to the disposition of the case. Id. at 6 n.1. Thus, we conclude
that plaintiffs have thrust onto Graham a burden it w as never intended to bear.
W e decline to read Graham as standing for the proposition that, in the context of
copyright, the public domain is a threshold that Congress may not “traverse in
both directions.” Aplts’ Br. at 50.
Furthermore, the Graham Court emphasized that the Constitution assigns
Congress the task of “implement[ing] the stated purpose of the Framers by
selecting the policy which in its judgment best effectuates the constitutional aim.”
383 U.S. at 6. As discussed above, the Eldred Court echoed this refrain. See
Eldred, 537 U.S. at 205 (“[I]t is Congress that has been assigned the task of
defining the scope of the limited monopoly that should be granted to authors . . . in
order to give the public appropriate access to their work product.”) (internal
quotation marks omitted). The clear import of Eldred is that Congress has
15
expansive powers w hen it legislates under the Copyright Clause, and this court
may not interfere so long as Congress has rationally exercised its authority. See
Eldred, 237 U.S. at 213 (searching for a “rational basis for the conclusion that the
CTEA ‘Promotes the Progress of Science’”). Here, we do not believe that the
decision to comply with the Berne Convention, which secures copyright
protections for American works abroad, is so irrational or so unrelated to the aims
of the Copyright Clause that it exceeds the reach of congressional power. Id. at
208 (emphasizing that the Court was “not at liberty to second-guess congressional
determinations and policy judgments of this order, however debatable or arguably
unwise they may be”).
Nevertheless, legislation promulgated pursuant to the Copyright Clause
must still comport with other express limitations of the Constitution. Saenz v.
Roe, 526 U .S. 489, 508 (1999) (“Article I of the Constitution grants Congress
broad power to legislate in certain areas. Those legislative powers are, however,
limited not only by the scope of the Framers’ affirmative delegation, but also by
the principle that they may not be exercised in a way that violates other specific
provisions of the Constitution.”) (internal quotation marks omitted); Buckley v.
Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 132 (1976) (“Congress has plenary authority in all areas in
which it has substantive legislative jurisdiction so long as the exercise of that
authority does not offend some other constitutional restriction.”) (internal citation
16
omitted). Thus, even if Congress has not exceeded its Article I authority, § 514
may still be subject to First Amendment review.
2. C ongress’s R em oval of W orks from the Public D omain A lters the
T raditional C ontours of C opyright Protection and R equires First
A m en dment S cru tin y
W e begin our First Amendment analysis by examining the intersection of
the Copyright Clause and the First Amendment. In doing so, we address the
Eldred Court’s holding that the CTEA’s extension of existing copyrights did not
require First Amendment scrutiny and discuss the Court’s suggestion that an act of
Congress would only be subject to First Amendment review if it “altered the
traditional contours of copyright protection.” 537 U.S. at 221. Based on the
Eldred Court’s analysis, we examine the bedrock principle of copyright law that
works in the public domain remain there and conclude that § 514 alters the
traditional contours of copyright protection by deviating from this principle. W e
then explain how this deviation implicates plaintiffs’ First A mendment interest in
the works at issue and determine that copyright’s two built-in free speech
safeguards – the idea/expression dichotomy and the fair use defense – do not
adequately protect the First Amendment interests. Finally, we note that, unlike the
CTEA, the U RAA does not adopt supplemental free speech safeguards.
a. The Copyright Clause & the First Amendment
It is clear that the Copyright Clause is meant to foster values enshrined in
17
the First A mendment. See Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 558 (observing that “the
Framers intended copyright itself to be the engine of free expression”). The
Clause’s primary purpose is to provide authors with incentives to produce works
that w ill benefit the public. See id. at 546 (“The monopoly created by copyright
thus rew ards the individual author in order to benefit the public.”) (internal
quotation marks omitted) (emphasis supplied); Aiken, 422 U.S. at 156 (“The
immediate effect of our copyright law is to secure a fair return for an ‘author’s’
creative labor. But the ultim ate aim is, by this incentive, to stimulate artistic
creativity for the general public good.”) (emphasis supplied); M azer v. Stein, 347
U.S. 201, 219 (1954) (“The economic philosophy behind the clause empow ering
Congress to grant [] copyrights is the conviction that encouragement of individual
effort by personal gain is the best way to advance public welfare through the
talents of authors . . . in ‘. . . [the] useful Arts.’”); Fox Film Corp. v. Doyal, 286
U.S. 123, 127 (1932) (“The sole interest of the U nited States and the primary
object in conferring the monopoly lie in the general benefits derived by the public
from the labors of authors.”).
In Eldred, the connection between the First Amendment and copyright
prompted the Court to reject the proposition that “copyrights [are] categorically
immune from challenges under the First Amendment.” 537 U.S. at 221 (internal
quotation marks omitted). However, under the facts of Eldred, copyright’s
18
inherent free speech protections obviated any need for First Amendment review of
the C TEA. The Court based this holding on three factors. First, the C ourt
concluded that copyright law’s “built-in First Amendment accommodations” – the
idea/expression dichotomy and fair use defense – adequately protected the First
Amendment interests at stake. Id. at 219. Second, the Court reasoned that the
plaintiffs had only a trivial interest in the copyrighted w orks because “[t]he First
Amendment securely protects the freedom to make – or decline to make – one’s
own speech; it bears less heavily when speakers assert the right to make other
people’s speeches.” Id. at 221 (emphasis supplied). Finally, the Court noted that
the CTEA provided supplemental protections to ensure that the Act did not
diminish the public’s access to protected expression. Id. at 220. The Court
further indicated that legislation could be subject to First A mendment scrutiny if it
“altered the traditional contours of copyright protection.” Id. at 221.
b. The principle that works in the public domain remain there is a
traditional contour of copyright protection that § 514 alters
W e begin our analysis of § 514 by exploring the traditional contours of
copyright protection. The Eldred Court did not define the “traditional contours of
copyright protection,” and we do not find, nor do the parties suggest that the
phrase appears in any other federal authority that might shed light on its meaning.
Nevertheless, the term seems to refer to something broader than copyright’s built-
in free speech accommodations.
19
Our understanding of the traditional contours of copyright protection has
both a functional and a historical component. W ith regard to the functional
aspect, we note that a contour is “an outline” or “the general form or structure of
something.” W EBSTER ’ S N INTH N EW C OLLEGIATE D ICTIONARY 284 (1984).
Because the term copyright refers to a process as well as a form of intellectual
property rights, we assess whether removing a w ork from the public domain alters
the ordinary procedure of copyright protection. Relatedly, we explore the way in
which the public domain delimits the scope of copyright protection. In addition,
the Eldred Court’s use of the word “traditional” to modify “contours” suggests
that Congress’s historical practice with respect to copyright and the public domain
must inform our inquiry. Based on these criteria, we conclude that the traditional
contours of copyright protection include the principle that works in the public
domain remain there and that § 514 transgresses this critical boundary.
i. Copyright Sequence
Although the specific requirements for perfecting a copyright have changed
over the years, the process has always begun when an author generates an original
expression. The 1909 Copyright Act required an author seeking protection to
attach notice to any distributed copies of his or her work. M oreover, the author
could not initiate an infringement action or apply for a renewal unless he or she
had formally registered the work with the copyright office. The 1976 Act removed
20
many of the consequences for failure to register or attach notice, and, in 1989, the
United States effectively abandoned all formalities as a condition of compliance
with the Berne Convention. Thus, today, a limited copyright attaches at the
moment a work is created. 3 W hen the copyright expires at the end of the statutory
period, the w ork becomes part of the public domain. Until § 514, every statutory
scheme preserved the same sequence. A work progressed from 1) creation; 2) to
copyright; 3) to the public domain. Under § 514, the copyright sequence no longer
necessarily ends with the public domain: indeed, it may begin there. Thus, by
copyrighting works in the public domain, the U RAA has altered the ordinary
copyright sequence.
ii. Public Domain
The significance of the copyright sequence, combined with the principle
that no individual may copyright a w ork in the public domain, is that ordinarily
works in the public domain stay there. See Country Kids ‘N City Slicks, Inc. v.
Sheen, 77 F.3d 1280, 1287 (10th Cir. 1996) (holding that a doll design could not
be copyrighted because it was characterized by “typical paper doll features found
in the public domain”); Lipton v. Nature Co., 71 F.3d 464, 470 (2d Cir. 1995)
(“[F]acts are considered to be in the public domain and therefore not protectable
3
An author must still include notice in order to defend against “innocent
infringer[s].” G ORMAN , supra, at 91.
21
under copyright law . . . .”); Norm a Ribbon & Trim ming, Inc. v. Little, 51 F.3d 45,
48 (5th Cir. 1995) (holding that certain flowers could not be copyrighted “because
these same flowers already existed in the public domain”); United States v.
Hamilton, 583 F.2d 448, 450 (9th Cir. 1987) (noting that “a map which represents
a new combination of information already in the public domain lacks any element
worthy of copyright protection”); M .M . Bus. Forms Corp. v. Uarco, Inc., 472 F.2d
1137, 1140 (6th Cir. 1973) (“Elementary legal words and phrases are in the public
domain and no citizen may gain monopoly thereover to the exclusion of their use
by other citizens.”); Amsterdam v. Triangle Publ’ns, Inc., 189 F.2d 104, 106 (3d
Cir. 1951) (“The location of county lines, township lines and municipal lines is
information within the public domain, and is not copyrightable.”); Christianson v.
West Pub. Co., 149 F.2d 202, 203 (9th Cir. 1945) (“The outline map of the United
States with state boundaries is in the public domain and is not copyrightable.”)
(internal quotation marks omitted); M eade v. United States, 27 Fed. Cl. 367, 372
(1992) (holding that “defendant’s LOVE stamp” could not be copyrighted because
it “exist[ed] in the public domain”); see also Toro Co. v. R&R Prods. Co., 787
F.2d 1208, 1213 (8th Cir. 1908) (“If the disputed work is similar to a pre-existing
protected work or one in the public domain, the second work must contain some
variation recognizable as that of the second author.”).
In Sheldon v. M etro-Goldwyn Pictures Corp., 81 F.2d 49, 54 (2d Cir. 1936),
22
aff’d, 309 U.S. 390, 392 (1940), Judge Learned Hand, a luminary in the field of
copyright law, illustrated this principle when he stated that “if by some magic a
man who had never known it were to compose anew Keats’s Ode on a Grecian
Urn, he would be an ‘author,’ and, if he copyrighted it, others might not copy that
poem, though they might of course copy Keats.” Sheldon, 81 F.2d at 54. As
Judge Hand observed, Keats’s poems remained in the public domain – free for
anyone to copy – even if someone copyrighted the identical language. Section
514 contravenes this principle.
iii. The history of American copyright law reveals no tradition of
copyrighting works in the public domain
As we stated above, the fact that the Eldred Court used the w ord
“traditional” to modify “contours” suggests that the history of American copyright
law should inform our inquiry. Eldred, 537 U.S. at 221. Accordingly, we look for
evidence indicating that the Framers believed removal of works from the public
domain w as consistent with the copyright scheme they designed. Congress’s past
practices are also pertinent to determining whether extricating works from the
public domain is a tradition of our country’s copyright law.
a. T he Fram ers’ V iew s
Unfortunately, constitutional historians know little about the Framers’
views regarding copyright and the public domain. In part, this is because, when
the states ratified the Constitution, “the Common Law of the United States . . . was
23
in a highly uncertain state on the subject of copyrights.” 1 W illiam W . Crosskey,
P OLITICS AND THE C ONSTITUTION IN THE H ISTORY OF THE U NITED S TATES 477
(1953). Uncertainty also stems from the fact that none of the usual, reliable
sources – The Federalist Papers, M adison’s notes from the Constitutional
Convention, or accounts of the First Congress’s deliberations – take up the subject
in any detail.
Passed in 1790, the first Copyright Act granted fourteen years of protection
for books, maps, and charts already printed in the United States. See Eldred, 537
U.S. at 194 (discussing the 1790 A ct). The parties debate whether the First
Congress extended copyright protection to works already in the public domain.
W hile the Eldred Court recognized that “the First Congress clearly did confer
copyright protection on works that had already been created,” id. at 196 n.3,
plaintiffs argue convincingly that most, if not all, of these works were covered by
a state common-law copyright and therefore not in the public domain. In
response, the government observes that not all states enacted copyright statutes
during the period of the Articles of Confederation. See Feltner v. Columbia
Pictures Television, Inc., 523 U .S. 340, 350 (1998) (citing Copyright Enactments:
Laws Passed in the United States Since 1783 Relating to Copyright 21 (Copyright
Office ed., Bulletin No. 3, rev. 1963)); Thomas B. Nachbar, Intellectual Property
and Constitutional N orm s, 104 Colum. L. Rev. 272, 338 n.284 (2004) (“Of the
24
general copyright laws passed by the States during the years of the Articles of
Confederation, two of them (M aryland and Pennsylvania) never even came into
effect; they included reciprocity clauses that were never fulfilled because one
State, Delaware, never enacted a general copyright law . . . .”).
Although the history of the 1790 Act could be highly informative of the
Framers’ views, the answer to the question of whether Congress thought it was
removing works from the public domain is probably not just unclear but also
unknowable. Edward C. W alterscheid, Understanding the Copyright Act of 1790:
the Issue of Common Law Copyright in America and the M odern Interpretation of
the Copyright Power, 53 J. Copyright Soc’y U.S.A. 313, 332 (2006) (“There is
very little contemporaneous legislative history dealing with the 1790 Act.”); see
also id. at 340 (“[I]t is impossible to demonstrate w ith any reasonable certainty
from the language of the 1790 Copyright Act and the circumstances surrounding
its enactment that Congress believed that it was creating a property right in
authors rather than affirming and protecting an existing common-law right, albeit
for a limited time.”).
Given the scarcity of historical evidence, we cannot conclude that the
Framers viewed removal of works from the public domain as consistent with the
copyright scheme they created. Nor do we discern at the dawn of the Republic any
burgeoning tradition of removing works from the public domain.
25
b. C ongressional Practice Since the F irst C ongress
At oral argument, the government conceded that apart from the 1790 Act’s
purported grant of copyright protection to works in the public domain, there have
been few instances of such grants since. It does, however, point to a series of
private bills granting copyrights to individuals. But “[t]hese private bills do not
support the [government’s] historical gloss, but rather significantly undermine the
historical claim.” Eldred, 537 U.S. at 234 (Stevens, J., dissenting). Far from
providing evidence that copyrighting works in the public domain is within the
traditional contours of copyright protection, the fact that individuals were forced
to resort to the uncommon tactic of petitioning Congress demonstrates that this
practice w as outside the normal practice.
In addition, the government argues that the wartime acts of Dec 18, 1919,
Pub. L. No. 66-102, 41 Stat. 368, and the Emergency Copyright Act of 1941, Pub.
L. No. 77-258, 55 Stat. 732, removed w orks from the public domain by granting
the President authority to give foreign authors additional time to comply with
copyright requirements. However, a review of the historical record reveals that
these emergency wartime bills, passed in response to exigent circumstances,
merely altered the means by which authors could comply with the procedural rules
for copyright; these bills were not explicit attempts to remove w orks from the
public domain. The Emergency Copyright Act of 1941, for example, recognized
26
that authors “may have been tem porarily unable to comply with [copyright
formalities] because of the disruption or suspension of facilities essential for such
compliance.” 55 Stat. 732 (emphasis supplied).
The statutory context of these acts reveals that they were, at most, a brief
and limited departure from a practice of guarding the public domain. In previous
actions granting copyrights to foreign authors, Congress emphasized that it was
not attempting to interfere with the rights of Americans who had relied on the
foreign works. For example, the 1919 Act stated that “nothing herein contained
shall be construed to deprive any person of any right which he may have acquired
by the republication of such foreign work in the United States prior to approval of
this Act.” 41 Stat. 369. One of the Acts to which the 1919 Act referred was the
1909 Copyright Act. That Act made clear that “no copyright shall subsist in the
original text of any work which is in the public domain.” Copyright Act, Pub. L.
No. 60-349, 35 Stat. 1075, 1077 (1909) (emphasis supplied).
This context notwithstanding, the wartime acts may have had the effect of
removing a very small number of w orks from the public domain. Nevertheless,
this possibility is insufficient to establish a traditional contour of copyright law.
Indeed, world war is (hopefully) not traditional. The fact that the legislation was
passed in response to the exigencies of a world war suggests that Congress felt
compelled to depart from its normal practice of preserving the public domain.
27
M oreover, the mere passage of these discrete acts does not indicate that such
removal was consistent with any provision of the Constitution, including the First
Amendment. See 3 N IMMER ON C OPYRIGHT § 9A.07[A], 9A-79 to -80 (2007)
(stating that “although three [wartime] enactments granted very limited
resurrection, . . . the practice under those circumscribed enactments w as simply to
sweep the constitutional issues under the rug”).
Based on the foregoing, we see no tradition of removing works from the
public domain. Indeed, if anything, our examination of the history of American
copyright law reveals that removal was the exception rather than the rule. Thus, §
514 deviates from the time-honored tradition of allowing works in the public
domain to stay there.
iv. Conclusion
In sum, by extending a limited monopoly to expressions historically beyond
the pale of such privileges, the URAA transformed the ordinary process of
copyright protection and contravened a bedrock principle of copyright law that
works in the public domain remain in the public domain. Therefore, under both
the functional and historical components of our inquiry, § 514 has altered the
traditional contours of copyright protection.
c. The URAA’s removal of works from the public domain
implicates plaintiffs’ First Amendment interest
W e now explain how this alteration of traditional contours affects the First
28
Amendment interests of these plaintiffs. To begin, as discussed above, copyright
law bears out the rather obvious – but significant – point that works in the public
domain belong to the public. See Dastar, 539 U.S. at 33-34 (2003) (“[O]nce the . .
. copyright monopoly has expired, the public may use the . . . work at will and
without attribution.”); Am. Tobacco Co. v. Werckmeister, 207 U.S. 284, 299-300
(1907) (observing that widespread publication of a work without copyright
protection “render[s] such work common property”) (emphasis supplied). As
Judge Hand made clear in National Comics Publications, Inc. v. Fawcett
Publications, Inc., 171 F.2d 594, 603 (2d Cir. 1951), a case that involved
copyrights to “Superman” and “Captain M arvel” comic strips, “once [the strips
fell] into the public domain . . . anyone might copy them.” In other words, each
member of the public – “anyone” – has a non-exclusive right, subject to
constitutionally permissible legislation, to use material in the public domain. The
implication of this principle is that the plaintiffs here possessed a non-exclusive
right to use the works at issue.
Furthermore, the First Amendment protects plaintiffs’ right to unrestrained
artistic use of these works. The Supreme Court has emphasized that the right to
artistic expression is near the core of the First A mendment. Ward v. Rock Against
Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 790 (1989) (“M usic is one of the oldest forms of human
expression. From Plato’s discourse in the Republic to the totalitarian state in our
29
own times, rulers have known [music’s] capacity to appeal to the intellect and to
the emotions, and have censored musical compositions to serve the needs of the
state. . . . The Constitution prohibits any like attempts in our own legal order.
M usic, as a form of expression and communication, is protected under the First
Amendment.”); Schad v. Borough of M ount Ephraim, 452 U.S. 61, 65 (1981)
(“Entertainment, as well as political and ideological speech, is protected; motion
pictures, programs broadcast by radio and television, and live entertainment, such
as musical and dramatic w orks, fall within the First Amendment guarantee.”);
Kaplan v. California, 413 U .S. 115, 119-120 (1973) (“[P]ictures, films, paintings,
drawings, and engravings . . . have First A mendment protection . . . .”).
Together, the clear import of these principles is that the public in general
and these plaintiffs in particular have a First Amendment interest in using works
in the public domain. For example, at the moment that Dmitri Shostakovich’s
Symphony No. 5 entered the public domain, Plaintiff John Blackburn had a right to
create a derivative work for a high school band to perform at an event
comm emorating 9/11. The principle of copyright law that shields works in the
public domain from copyright ensured M r. Blackburn’s right to create the piece,
and the First A mendment protected his right to perform it.
Section 514 has interfered with M r. Blackburn’s right by making the cost of
performance or creation of new derivative w orks based on Shostakovich’s
30
Symphony No. 5 prohibitive. M oreover, as the example of M r. Blackburn’s
composition suggests, plaintiffs’ First A mendment interests in public domain
works are greater than the interests of the Eldred plaintiffs. The Eldred plaintiffs
did not – nor had they ever – possessed unfettered access to any of the works at
issue there. As the Eldred Court observed, the most the Eldred plaintiffs could
show was a weak interest in “making other people’s speeches.” 537 U.S. 221. By
contrast, the speech at issue here belonged to plaintiffs w hen it entered the public
domain. In reliance on their rights to these works, plaintiffs have already
performed or planned future performances and used these publically available
works to create their ow n artistic productions. 4
By removing works from the public domain, § 514 arguably hampers free
expression and undermines the values the public domain is designed to protect.
See Meade, 27 Fed. Cl. at 372 (“Extending copyright protection to a heart-shaped
picture of earth effectively would grant the copyright holder a monopoly over the
4
Interestingly, during the Eldred oral argument, Justice Souter asked then-
Solicitor General Olsen whether the Copyright Clause combined with the
Necessary and Proper Clause could justify the extension of monopoly privileges
to a “copyright that expired yesterday.” Aplts’ Supp. Auth. dated June 2, 2006,
Transcript of Oral Argument at 44, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (No. 01-
618). The Solicitor General replied that although such an act was not
inconceivable, the public domain likely presented a “bright line” because once
“[s]omething . . . has already gone into the public domain [] other individuals or
companies or entities may then have acquired an interest in, or rights to be
involved in disseminating [the w ork.]” Id.
31
innumerable w ays of expressing this picture. Allowing this picture to remain in
the public domain for all artists to interpret freely, however, will foster creativity
by ensuring that future mapmakers and artists have an ample store of ideas on
which to build their works.”). W e therefore conclude that once the works at issue
became free for anyone to copy, plaintiffs in this case had vested First Amendment
interests in the expressions, and § 514’s interference with plaintiffs’ rights is
subject to First Amendment scrutiny.
f. Copyright’s built-in free speech safeguards are not adequate to
protect the First Amendment interests at stake
In Eldred, the Court indicated that “copyright’s built-in free speech
safeguards are generally adequate to address [First Amendment concerns].” 537
U.S. at 221 (emphasis supplied). Below, we conclude that the idea/expression
dichotomy and the fair use defense are not designed to combat the threat to free
expression posed by § 514’s removal of works from the public domain.
i. Idea/Expression Dichotomy
The idea/expression dichotomy protects First Amendment interests by
ensuring that “no author may copyright facts or ideas. The copyright is limited to
those aspects of the work – termed ‘expression’ – that display the stamp of the
author’s originality.” Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 547 (citation omitted). The
Supreme Court has observed that the idea/expression dichotomy “strikes a
definitional balance between the First Amendment and the Copyright Act by
32
permitting free communication of facts while still protecting an author’s
expression.” Eldred, 537 U.S. at 219 (quoting Harper, 471 U.S. at 556). See 4
N IMMER ON C OPYRIGHT , supra, § 19E.03[A][2], at 19E-20 to -21 (“In general, the
democratic dialogue – a self-governing people’s participation in the marketplace
of ideas – is adequately served if the public has access to an author’s ideas, and
such loss to the dialogue as results from inaccessibility to an author’s ‘expression’
is counterbalanced by the greater public interest in the copyright system.”).
However, the idea/expression dichotomy’s utility as a definitional
mechanism is limited to determining whether a proposed work is an idea or
whether the work displays sufficient originality to constitute an expression. In the
typical case, the danger to free speech interests is that an individual might gain
monopoly privileges over an idea. Here, by contrast, there is no doubt that the
works at issue are expressions; the threat to free expression lies not in what is
being copyrighted, but in the fact that the works are being removed from the
public domain. The idea/expression dichotomy is simply not designed to
determine whether Congress’s grant of a limited monopoly over an expression in
the public domain runs afoul of the First Amendment.
ii. Fair Use Defense
“The [fair use] defense provides: the fair use of a copyrighted work,
including such use by reproduction in copies . . . , for purposes such as criticism,
33
comment, new s reporting, teaching (including multiple copies for classroom use),
scholarship, or research, is not an infringement of copyright.” 17 U.S.C. § 107
(internal quotation marks omitted). “[It] allows the public to use not only facts
and ideas contained in a copyrighted work, but also expression itself in certain
circumstances.” Eldred, 537 U.S. at 219. For example, although Ralph Ellison’s
estate may retain the copyright to his classic novel Invisible M an, the fair use
defense permits scholars and teachers to quote extensively from the book and even
reproduce entire sections for the purpose of commenting on (say) the parallels
between the narrator’s literal and figurative vision. Because the purpose of the
fair use defense is to “afford[] considerable ‘latitude for scholarship and
comm ent,’” Eldred, 537 U.S. at 220 (quoting Harper, 471 U.S. at 560), the C ourt
has described it as a “guarantee of breathing space within the confines of
copyright.” Campbell v. Acuff-Rose M usic, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 579 (1994).
In our view, the fair use doctrine is not a sufficient safeguard of plaintiffs’
First Amendment interests. Although the doctrine allows limited use of
copyrighted works, it does not address works that have entered the public domain
and are therefore available for unrestricted use. By withdrawing works from the
public domain, § 514 leaves scholars, artists, and the public w ith less access to
works than they had before the Act. The fact that the fair use doctrine permits
some access to those works may not be an adequate substitute for the unlimited
34
access enjoyed before the URAA was enacted. Thus, instead of providing
additional “breathing space” for free expression, the fair use defense suggests that
§ 514 infringes upon plaintiffs’ First A mendment rights.
In sum, “copyright’s built-in free speech safeguards,” Eldred, 537 U.S. at
221, are designed to govern the distribution of rights between authors and the
public from the moment a work is created and copyrighted until the copyright
expires. This design presumes that some rights are properly reserved for the
author who has never relinquished his right to exploitation. Once a work has
entered the public domain, however, neither the author nor the author’s estate
possesses any more right to the work than any member of the general public.
Because § 514 bestows copyrights upon works in the public domain, these built-in
safeguards are not adequate to protect plaintiffs’ First Amendment interests.
iii. The U RAA does not supplement the traditional First
Amendment safeguards
In concluding that the CTEA did not require First Amendment scrutiny, the
Eldred Court noted that “the CTEA [] supplements the[] traditional safeguards.”
Id. The Court described the additional protections as follows:
First, [the CTEA] allows libraries, archives, and similar institutions to
“reproduce” and “distribute, display, or perform in facsimile or digital
form” copies of certain published works “during the last 20 years of any
term of copyright . . . for purposes of preservation, scholarship, or
research” if the work is not already being exploited commercially and
further copies are unavailable at a reasonable price. 17 U.S.C. § 108(h).
Second, Title II of the CTEA, known as the Fairness in M usic Licensing
35
Act of 1998, exempts small businesses, restaurants, and like entities
from having to pay performance royalties on music played from licensed
radio, television, and similar facilities.
Id. at 220 (quoting 17 U.S.C. § 108(h)) (some internal citations omitted).
The URAA contains none of the CTEA’s supplemental First Amendment
protections. It neither provides exceptions for “libraries, archives and similar
institutions,” nor exemptions for “small businesses, restaurants and like entities
from having to pay performance royalties.” 17 U.S.C. § 108(h). Rather than
excepting parties, such as plaintiffs, who have relied upon works in the public
domain, the URAA provides only a safe harbor allowing a party to use a restored
work for one year after receiving notice of the restored copyright protection. 17
U.S.C. § 104A(d)(2). W e note, however, that it does permit a party to continue to
use a work if notice is not given. See Luck’s M usic, 467 F.3d at 1265 (discussing
§ 104A(d)(2)). W hen compared to the CTEA, this is hardly a “guarantee of
breathing space.” Campbell, 510 U.S. at 579.
IV . IN ST R U C TIO N S FO R R E M A N D
In conducting its First Amendment analysis on remand, the district court
should assess whether § 514 is content-based or content-neutral. Content-based
restrictions on speech are those which “suppress, disadvantage, or impose
differential burdens upon speech because of its content.” Grace U nited M ethodist
Church v. City of Cheyenne, 451 F.3d 643, 657 (10th Cir. 2006) (internal citations
36
and quotations omitted). These restrictions “are subject to the most exacting
scrutiny.” Id. If § 514 is a content-based restriction, then the district court will
need to consider whether the government’s interest in promulgating the legislation
is truly “compelling” and whether the government might achieve the same ends
through alternative means that have less of an effect on protected expression. 5
United States v. Playboy Entm’t Group, Inc., 529 U.S. 803, 813 (2000). By
contrast, “[a] regulation that serves purposes unrelated to the content of
expression is deemed neutral, even if it has an incidental effect on some speakers
or messages but not others.” Rock Against Racism, 491 U.S. at 791. A content-
5
Although not mentioned by the parties, Congress’s treaty, comm erce, and
takings powers may provide Congress with the authority to enact § 514. See 3
N IMMER ON C OPYRIGHT § 9A.07[B], 9A -79 to -80, 90A .07[C], 9A -85. W e also
note that at oral argument, Professor Lessig claimed that the experience of other
countries, such as the United Kingdom, suggests that the United States could
comply with the Berne Convention through less restrictive means. Indeed, the
United Kingdom Copyright Statute, as well as the statutes in Australia, Canada,
India, and New Zealand, define a reliance party as any person who “incurs or has
incurred any expenditure or liability in connection with, for the purpose of or with
a view to the doing of an act which at the time is not or was not an act restricted
by any copyright in the work.” Irwin Karp, Final Report, Berne Article 18 Study
on Retroactive United States Copyright Protection for Berne and Other Works, 20
C OLUM .-VLA J.L. & Arts 157, 178 (W inter 1996) (quoting “The Copyright
(A pplication to Other Countries) O rder in Council 988”; June 13, 1989, Article
7(2), reprinted in Copyright Laws and Treaties of the W orld, UK: Item 7c, at 2
(Unesco Supp. 1989-1990). Under the British, Canadian, Australian, and Indian
systems, “the reliance party is allow ed to continue making those uses of the w ork
it had made, or incurred commitments to make, before its copyright is restored.
But the reliance party can be ‘bought out’ by the owner of the restored copyright.
That is, the reliance party must cease exploiting the work if the owner pays
compensation, in an amount to be determined by negotiation or arbitration.” Id.
37
neutral restriction must be “narrowly tailored to serve a significant governmental
interest.” Id. (quoting Clark v. Cmty. for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U.S. 288,
293 (1984)).
V . C O N C L U SIO N
For the foregoing reasons, we affirm the district court’s dismissal of the
CTEA claim as foreclosed by Eldred. W e also affirm the district court’s holding
that § 514 of the URAA does not exceed the limitations inherent in the Copyright
Clause. Nevertheless, since § 514 has altered the traditional contours of copyright
protection in a manner that implicates plaintiffs’ right to free expression, it must
be subject to First Amendment review. W e therefore REM AND for proceedings
consistent w ith this opinion.
38