Amatel, Joseph v. Hawk, Kathleen

United States Court of Appeals FOR THE DISTRICT OF COLUMBIA CIRCUIT Argued May 8, 1998 Decided September 15, 1998 No. 97-5293 Joseph Amatel, et al., Appellees v. Janet Reno, Attorney General of the United States, et al., Appellants Consolidated with Nos. 97-5294, 97-5295 Appeals from the United States District Court for the District of Columbia (No. 96cv02774) (No. 96cv02790) (No. 97cv00475) Edward Himmelfarb, Attorney, U.S. Department of Jus- tice, argued the cause for appellants. With him on the briefs were Frank W. Hunger, Assistant Attorney General, Wilma A. Lewis, U.S. Attorney, and Barbara L. Herwig, Assistant Director, U.S. Department of Justice. Jodie L. Kelley argued the cause for appellees. With her on the brief were Ann M. Kappler, Marjorie Rifkin and Margaret Winter. Bruce A. Taylor was on the brief for amici curiae National Coalition for the Protection of Children & Families, et al. Before: Wald, Williams and Tatel, Circuit Judges. Opinion for the Court filed by Circuit Judge Williams. Dissenting opinion filed by Circuit Judge Wald. Williams, Circuit Judge: A group of prisoners and publish- ers challenges the constitutionality of a statutory ban on the use of Bureau of Prisons funds to distribute sexually explicit material to prisoners. The statute is not enforced directly; instead, the Bureau has promulgated regulations defining the terms of the proscription and significantly narrowing its scope. The district court, analyzing the statute, ruled that it was facially invalid as a violation of the First Amendment and enjoined its enforcement. Finding that scrutiny should be directed to the substance of the regulations instead, and disagreeing with the district court's evaluation, we reverse and remand. * * * Before 1996, federal regulations authorized prison wardens to reject a publication "only if it [was] determined detrimental to the security, good order, or discipline of the institution or if it might facilitate criminal activity." 28 CFR s 540.71(b). Sexually explicit material fell into this category if it "by its nature or content pose[d] a threat to the security, good order, or discipline of the institution, or facilitate[d] criminal activi- ty." 28 CFR s 540.71(b)(7). Under this standard, explicit heterosexual material was ordinarily admitted. See Thorn- burgh v. Abbott, 490 U.S. 401, 405 n.6 (1989). In 1996 Congress passed the Ensign Amendment, which bars the use of Bureau of Prisons funds to pay for the distribution of commercial material that "is sexually explicit or features nudity." 1 See Omnibus Consolidated Appropria- tions Act of 1997, Pub. L. No. 104-208 s 614.2 Regulations later adopted by the Bureau assign rather narrow meanings to these terms: "nudity" means "a pictorial depiction where genitalia or female breasts are exposed"; "features" means that "the publication contains depictions of nudity or sexually explicit conduct on a routine or regular basis or promotes itself based upon such depictions in the case of individual one- time issues." Even material that otherwise would be said to "feature nudity" is excepted if it contains "nudity illustrative of medical, educational, or anthropological content." "Sexual- ly explicit" means "a pictorial depiction of actual or simulated sexual acts including sexual intercourse, oral sex, or mastur- bation." 28 CFR s 540.72(b). Under these regulations, then, there is no restriction whatever on non-pictorial sexually explicit material. In 1997, three inmates, each denied receipt of either Play- boy or Penthouse, filed separate suits alleging that the En- sign Amendment violated the First Amendment. Their suits were consolidated, along with similar suits filed by the pub- lishers of those magazines and a publishing trade organiza- tion; the consolidated plaintiffs moved for injunctive relief. The district court, purporting to apply the test set out in Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78 (1987), found the Ensign Amendment facially invalid--implicitly granting plaintiffs' __________ 1 By its terms, the statute therefore does not prohibit prisoners from obtaining such material at their own expense. Neither party has suggested that this is a realistic possibility, or discussed the rules governing gifts by visitors. Accordingly, our analysis will treat the spending restriction as a ban on distribution. Where the government absolutely monopolizes the means of speech or controls a bottleneck, as we are assuming vis-a-vis the prison distribution system, a refusal to fund functions the same as an outright ban. 2 Identical language appears in s 614 of Pub. L. No. 105-119, governing the fiscal year ending September 30, 1998, so no issue of mootness is currently posed. motion for summary judgment (which, in fact, they never made)--and permanently enjoined its enforcement. * * * Both sides agree that Safley sets out the appropriate framework for reviewing government regulation of prisons.3 But before beginning that analysis, we must note that our first difference with the district court is as to the proper object of judicial scrutiny. Plaintiffs ask for relief against both the Ensign Amend- ment and its implementing regulations. The district court seemed to assume that the statute itself has been and will be applied to these plaintiffs; accordingly, it directed its analysis primarily towards the statute. But there is no suggestion that any warden does or will apply the statute directly; so far as appears, all enforcement is mediated through the regula- tions. Insofar as plaintiffs attack the proscriptions of the statute not embodied in the regulations, they effectively pursue a pre-enforcement challenge. Even in the First Amendment context, such a challenge presents a justiciable controversy only if the probability of enforcement is "real and substan- tial." Salvation Army v. Dep't of Comm. Affairs, 919 F.2d 183, 192 (3d Cir. 1990); see also Steffel v. Thompson, 415 U.S. 452, 460 (1974). In the statutory borderland beyond the implementing regulations (i.e., the statute's apparent ban on some non-pictorial material, its vaguer language, and its lack of any exception for medical or educational material), the prospect of enforcement appears completely insubstantial. It is as if the government had waived certain provisions of the law. And with such a waiver, as Salvation Army explicitly holds, there is no standing to challenge the waived provisions. See 919 F.2d at 192-93 ("[T]he district court should decline to __________ 3 The claims of the publisher plaintiffs might seem to call for a different analysis, as they of course are not prisoners. Thornburgh makes clear, however, that Safley's reasonableness standard gov- erns "regulations that affect[ ] rights of prisoners and outsiders." 490 U.S. at 410 n.9. provide an advisory opinion regarding the constitutionality of these provisions."). See also Forsyth County, Georgia v. Nationalist Movement, 505 U.S. 123, 131 (1992) (evaluation of facial challenge to statute must take into account construction by enforcing body). We therefore limit our focus to the substantive prohibitions of the regulations.4 * * * Cases analyzing constitutional claims by those within gov- ernmental institutions such as prisons, public schools, the military, or the government workplace often open with the axiom that the boundaries of those institutions do not sepa- rate inhabitants from their constitutional rights. See, e.g., Safley, 482 U.S. at 84 ("Prison walls do not form a barrier separating prison inmates from the protections of the Consti- tution."); Connick v. Myers, 461 U.S. 138, 142 (1983) ("[I]t has been settled that a State cannot condition public employ- ment on a basis that infringes the employee's constitutionally protected interest in freedom of expression."); Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School Dist., 393 U.S. 503, 506 (1969) ("It can hardly be argued that either students or teachers shed their constitutional rights to freedom of speech or expression at the schoolhouse gate."); General Media Communications, Inc. v. Cohen, ("GMC ") 131 F.3d 273, 276 (2d Cir. 1997) ("The Constitution does not, of course, stop at the gates of a military base."). This observation is invariably followed by the complementary principle that by their nature such environments must allow regulation more intrusive than what may lawfully apply to the general public. See Safley, 482 U.S. at 84-85; Connick, 461 U.S. at 143; Tinker, 393 U.S. at 507; GMC, 131 F.3d at 276. In these environments, the government is permitted to balance constitutional rights __________ 4 Our dissenting colleague relies on two recent decisions invalidat- ing provisions that are more similar to the statute than to the regulatory intepretation established in this case. Mauro v. Arpaio, 1998 WL 550190 (9th Cir. Sept. 1, 1998); Waterman v. Verniero, 1998 WL 354932 (D.N.J. June 29, 1998). See Dissent at 1-2 n.1. Because we see the only ripe case before us as confined to the regulations, our case is plainly distinguishable. against institutional efficiency in ways it may not ordinarily do.5 See, e.g., Waters v. Churchill, 511 U.S. 661, 675 (1994) (describing governmental power to restrict speech in the name of efficiency); Safley, 482 U.S. at 88 (noting balancing between First Amendment rights and governmental inter- ests). For the prison context, Safley directs courts to uphold a regulation, even one circumscribing constitutionally protected interests, so long as it "is reasonably related to legitimate penological interests." 482 U.S. at 89. We are to assess the overall reasonableness of such restrictions with attention to four factors: first, whether the restriction bears a "valid, rational connection" to the "legitimate governmental interest put forward to justify it," such that the "asserted goal is [not] so remote as to render the policy arbitrary or irrational," id. at 89-90; second, whether inmates retain alternative means of exercising the circumscribed right, id. at 90; third, the costs that accommodating the right imposes on other inmates, guards, and prison resources generally, id.; and fourth, whether there are alternatives to the regulation that "fully accommodate[ ] the prisoner's rights at de minimis cost to valid penological interests," id. at 90-91. Although the fac- tors are intended as guides to a single reasonableness stan- dard, see id. at 89; see also Thornburgh, 490 U.S. at 414 ("The Court in [Safley] identified several factors that are relevant to, and that serve to channel, the reasonableness inquiry."), the first factor looms especially large. Its rational- ity inquiry tends to encompass the remaining factors, and some of its criteria are apparently necessary conditions. Nothing can save a regulation that promotes an illegitimate or non-neutral goal. See Safley, 482 U.S. at 90. __________ 5 This distinction is often phrased in terms of differential stan- dards of review applicable to the government when it acts in roles other than sovereign. See, e.g., Waters v. Churchill, 511 U.S. 661, 671 (1994). But it may be more apt to conceive of it as a distinction between government regulation of public discourse generally, and government regulation of speech within governmental institutions. See generally Robert Post, Constitutional Domains 199-268 (1995). In this case, both proponents in congressional debate, and the government in its briefs here, assert as the goal an interest in the rehabilitation of prisoners. See, e.g., 142 Cong. Rec. H8261 (daily ed. July 24, 1996) ("Congress should not be fueling the sexual appetites of offenders, espe- cially those who have been convicted of despicable sex of- fenses against women and children. Magazines that portray and exploit sex acts have no place in the rehabilitative envi- ronment of prisons, nor should we pay Bureau of Prison[s] staff to distribute them.") (statement of Rep. Ensign); id. at H8262 ("The infamous serial killer Ted Bundy ... stated before his death his belief that pornographic materials direct- ly contributed to his violent crimes. While a number of factors determine whether a prisoner will become a law- abiding citizen upon release from prison, cutting prisoners off from their sexually explicit magazines will certainly do no harm.") (statement of Rep. Ensign). The next question is whether rehabilitation is a legitimate and "neutral" govern- ment interest within the meaning of Safley. The legitimacy of the rehabilitative purpose appears indis- putable. Indeed, the Supreme Court has often characterized rehabilitation as one of the primary goals of penal institu- tions. See, e.g., O'Lone v. Estate of Shabazz, 482 U.S. 342, 348 (1987) (describing rehabilitation as "valid penological objective[ ]"); Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396, 413 (1974) (identifying "substantial government interests of security, order, and rehabilitation"). At least since the mid-19th cen- tury, it is hard to imagine a prison system that did not seek to reduce the likelihood that prisoners would again transgress society's norms. The inventors of the prison in New York and Pennsylvania framed its goals in these terms: The penitentiary, free of corruptions and dedicated to the proper training of the inmate, would inculcate the discipline that negligent parents, evil companions, tav- erns, houses of prostitution, theaters, and gambling halls had destroyed. Just as the criminal's environment had led him into crime, the institutional environment would lead him out of it. David J. Rothman, The Invention of the Asylum: Social Order and Disorder in the New Republic 82-83 (rev. ed. 1990). In turning to "neutrality," the district court looked at the statute itself, not the goal, and found it non-neutral. "[T]he Ensign Amendment is a content-based statute with a sole focus on the sexual nature of the publications it seeks to prohibit." The conclusion is correct--the Ensign Amendment is formulated in terms of content. But we do not understand that characteristic to run afoul of Safley's neutrality require- ment. Despite the apparent similarity in terms, "neutrality" in the Safley sense is quite different from the familiar First Amendment notion of "content-neutrality." The Court most recently explained in Thornburgh that "neutral" here means no more than that "the regulation or practice in question must further an important or substantial governmental inter- est unrelated to the suppression of expression." 490 U.S. at 415 (quoting Martinez). There the Court found neutrality simply because in application of the regulations the prison administrators were to "draw distinctions between publica- tions solely on the basis of their potential implications for prison security." Id. It pointed out that the regulations struck down in Martinez, in contrast, barred writings that "unduly complain[ed]" or "magnif[ied] grievances," or ex- pressed "inflammatory" views, thus inviting the prison au- thorities " 'to apply their own personal prejudices and opin- ions as standards for prisoner mail censorship.' " 490 U.S. at 416 n.14 (quoting Martinez); see also Martinez, 416 U.S. at 415 (striking down regulations because no legitimate interest at all was offered as justification). Thus the Martinez regula- tions were "decidedly not 'neutral' in the relevant sense." Thornburgh, 490 U.S. at 416 n.14. The rehabilitative interest offered by the government here meets this rather thin neutrality requirement. The Court cannot have meant to insist upon neutrality in its classic First Amendment sense, as embodied, for example, in the dictum of Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 339 (1974), that "[u]nder the First Amendment, there is no such thing as a false idea." In its role as an operator of prisons, the govern- ment surely does not lapse from the required neutrality if it bans "how-to" manuals on fraud and embezzlement ("Fraud for Dummies"). The idea that committing such crimes is not proper may not be "false" in the Gertz sense, but in the prison context the government may oppose it rather absolute- ly. This authority cannot be explained away on the theory that such a ban could withstand even the strictest scrutiny and that its validity therefore tells us nothing of the "neutrali- ty" requirement; as voiced by the Court, the "neutrality" requirement is an absolute prerequisite. Accordingly, we think the Court's actual application of the requirement, with its focus on the existence of some legitimate goal and on assuring that rules are in fact not framed so as to advance illegitimate or unvetted goals, must control our understanding of its meaning. That government power to inculcate values conflicts with the libertarian premises of the First Amendment is clear, but such power is well established. Even outside special govern- mental institutions, the state has some authority to become a player in the marketplace of ideas. It may commission advertising urging children to stay in school or off drugs; it can sponsor anti-violence campaigns. See Regan v. Taxation with Representation, 461 U.S. 540, 548-59 (1983); see gener- ally Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 193 (1991) ("The Govern- ment can, without violating the Constitution, selectively fund a program to encourage certain activities it believes to be in the public interest, without at the same time funding an alternate program which seeks to deal with the problem in another way."). And within its own institutions, government's power to pursue its legitimate goals is elevated: within reasonable limits, it may attach sanctions to or exclude speech that threatens its goals--even if those goals include promotion of particular values. That is the general lesson of cases such as Waters, 511 U.S. 661 (upholding dismissal of employee for speech that might have caused disruption); Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U.S. 675, 685 (1986) (upholding suspension of student who used indecent language in assem- bly speech); and Greer v. Spock, 424 U.S. 828 (1976) (uphold- ing exclusion from military base of civilians who wished to distribute political literature). Of course this does not mean by a long shot that every government institution can pursue any value. Our century has seen more than enough of governments trying to act as engineers of human souls. But inculcation of values cannot be characterized as a suppression of expression in every context. The Supreme Court has in fact taken the position that democratic society depends on inculcation of democratic values. See, e.g., Ambach v. Norwick, 441 U.S. 68, 76-77 (1979) (stating that public schools are important "in the preparation of individuals for participation as citizens, and in the preservation of the values on which our society rests"); Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483, 493, (1954) ("[Public education] is a principal instrument in awakening the child to cultural values, in preparing him for later profes- sional training, and in helping him to adjust normally to his environment."). The generality of Safley's reasonableness test, and common sense as well, suggest that the flexibility open to the political branches must be at its apogee in institutions for the care and custody of those who have already transgressed society's norms. If "promoting respect for authority and traditional values" among schoolchildren is a legitimate interest of government and not inherently a form of speech suppression, see Board of Education, Island Trees Union Free School Dist. No. 26 v. Pico, 457 U.S. 853, 864 (1982) (plurality opinion), surely the same is true of promot- ing such a goal among criminals. Prisoners of course differ from the other examples of individuals entangled with the government in that they have no recourse to a private sphere. For them, there is no outside. Judges plainly must bear in mind the total occupa- tion of prisoners' lives by the state. But prisoners find themselves in the maw of the state not because they have been drawn there by the promise of government wages, nor because a statute imposes a universal requirement of edu- cation, but because they have broken the law. Moreover, even government workers have suffered a similar eclipse of the private sphere; the government's ability to fire them for speech that threatens workplace disruption is not limited to speech within the workplace. See, e.g., Pickering v. Board of Education, 391 U.S. 563 (1968) (analyzing letter to the edi- tor). See generally Note, The Costs of Agencies: Waters v. Churchill and the First Amendment in the Administrative State, 106 Yale L.J. 1233, 1239-40 (1997) (discussing scope of governmental authority). Accordingly, we conclude that re- habilitation, and such character-moulding as may be implicit therein, constitute legitimate and neutral goals as those are understood in Safley. * * * We thus turn to whether there is a "valid rational connec- tion" between the interest and the regulations. Prison juris- prudence is not well enough developed to indicate precisely how demanding the requirement of rational means-end con- nection is. But the similarity between Safley's phrasing and the language of rational basis review suggests to us that, as far as the means-end fit is concerned, Safley's standard is, if not identical, something very similar. Compare, e.g., Nord- linger v. Hahn, 505 U.S. 1, 11 (1992) ("[T]he relationship of the classification to its goal is not so attenuated as to render the distinction arbitrary or irrational.") with Safley, 482 U.S. at 89-90 ("[T]he logical connection between the regulation and the asserted goal is so remote as to render the policy arbitrary or irrational."). The legislative judgment is that pornography adversely affects rehabilitation. It does not matter whether we agree with the legislature, only whether we find its judgment rational. The question for us is not whether the regulation in fact advances the government interest, only whether the legislature might reasonably have thought that it would. See, e.g., Nordlinger, 505 U.S. at 11. We think that the government could rationally have seen a connection between pornography and rehabilitative values. Congress might well perceive pornography as tending gener- ally to thwart the character growth of its consumers. One current exposition of this view sees pornography as treating women purely as objects of male sexual gratification. See, e.g., Catharine A. MacKinnon, Only Words 108-10; Mac- Kinnon, "Francis Biddle's Sister: Pornography, Civil Rights, and Speech," in Feminism Unmodified 163, 174 (1987); Mar- tha C. Nussbaum, "Objectification," 25 Phil. & Pub. Affairs 249, 283-86 (1995); Cass Sunstein, The Partial Constitution 257-90 (1993). But this viewpoint shares at least a core with ideas that have a lineage of a few centuries, perhaps millen- nia, stressing the desirability of deferring gratification, of sublimation of sexual impulses, of channeling sexual expres- sion into long-term relationships of caring and affection, of joining eros to agape. The supposition that exclusion of pornography from prisons will have much of an impact in this direction may be optimistic, but it is not irrational. There is, of course, no "record evidence," and certainly no sophisticated multiple regression analyses or other social science data, to support this belief--a fact our dissenting colleague finds fatal. See Dissent at 8-11. We do not think, however, that common sense must be the mere handmaiden of social science data or expert testimonials in evaluating congressional judgments. Quite the opposite: scientific stud- ies can have a corrective effect by establishing an apparently implausible connection or refuting an apparently obvious one, but, subject to such corrections, conformity to commonsensi- cal intuitive judgments is a standard element of both reason- ableness and rationality. Compare D.N. McCloskey, The Rhetoric of Economics 44 (1985) ("Not all regression analyses are more persuasive than all moral arguments; not all con- trolled experiments are more persuasive than all introspec- tions. People should not discriminate against propositions on the basis of epistemological origin. There are some subjec- tive, soft, vague propositions that are more persuasive than some objective, hard, precise propositions.") Nor do we think Safley requires more. In that case, the Court scoured the record for evidence of a rational link between the asserted security interests and the marriage ban because common sense does not suggest any. See Safley, 482 U.S. at 97-100. Here, the regulations restrict prison consumption of publica- tions that implicitly elevate the value of the viewer's immedi- ate sexual gratification over the values of respect and consid- eration for others. Common sense tells us that prisoners are more likely to develop the now-missing self-control and re- spect for others if prevented from poring over pictures that are themselves degrading and disrespectful. Nor can we find irrationality in a congressional fear that pornography may set back rehabilitation in the narrower sense, more directly related to recidivist activity. The briefs, particularly that of the amicus curiae, call our attention to studies purporting either to document or to demolish the causal link between pornography and sex crimes.6 Without attempting a comprehensive summary, we note a few. One concludes that exposing "already angered men" (probably not especially rare in prison) to nonviolent pornography can lead to short-term increases in their aggressiveness. Edward Donnerstein, et al., The Question of Pornography 40-48 (1987). Another finds that "pornography provides ideational support for rape...." Larry Baron & Murray A. Straus, Four Theories of Rape in American Society 185 (1989). Baron & Straus's primary evidence for this claim is an observed correlation between the circulation rates of sex magazines and reported rape rates. While they are hesitant to defend a "cause-effect" link between pornography and rape, they do see the correlation as explained by "the pres- ence of a hypermasculine or macho culture pattern." Id. at 186. This cultural pattern, Baron and Straus hypothesize, causes both higher incidence of rape and higher consumption of pornography. Of course, it seems quite likely that a culture and its manifestations have a mutually reinforcing relationship, so that a prohibition of pornography is a reason- able element of a struggle against machismo and its ill effects. Finally, there is a significant body of research showing that long-term exposure to pornography, particularly pornog- __________ 6 Congress did not cite these materials, an omission of no impor- tance. See Jones v. United States, 463 U.S. 354, 365 n.13 (1983). Our concern is not why Congress believed that pornography affect- ed rehabilitation, but whether it would have been rational so to believe. Cf. Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 117 S. Ct. 1174, 1197 (1997) ("Congress is not obligated, when enacting its statutes, to make a record of the type that an administrative agency or court does to accommodate judicial review."). raphy containing scenes of "aggressive sexuality," can make its (male) audience more aggressive, more tolerant of violence against women, and more susceptible to myths about rape, such as the notion that women can enjoy being raped. See Neil Malamuth, "Aggression against Women: Cultural and Individual Causes," in Malamuth & Donnerstein, 19, 32-39; see also Mike Allen et al., "Exposure to Pornography and Acceptance of Rape Myths," 45 J. Communication 5 (1995) ("Although the experimental studies demonstrate that violent pornography has more effect [inducing rape myth acceptance] than nonviolent pornography, nonviolent pornography still demonstrates an effect.") See also Richard A. Posner, Sex and Reason, 366-71 (1992) (noting inconclusiveness of social science findings on net effects of pornography on incidence of rape; pornography may tend to increase rape by its ideologi- cal and aphrodisiac effects, but may tend to decrease it by enhancing a substitute (masturbation), the balance of these effects being unknown). The point of this is not to suggest that a causal link has been shown. The array of academic authority on the other side is at least as substantial, and quite possibly more so. But even undertaking to weigh the competing scholarship would misconceive the judicial role. Dealing with legislative judgments about rehabilitation, the Supreme Court has said that "[w]hen Congress undertakes to act in areas fraught with medical and scientific uncertainties, legislative options must be especially broad and courts should be cautious not to rewrite legislation, even assuming, arguendo, that judges with more direct exposure to the problem might make wiser choices." Marshall v. United States, 414 U.S. 417, 427 (1974) (emphasis in original); see also Kansas v. Hendricks, 117 S. Ct. 2072, 2081 n.3 (1997). And in upholding a statute barring provision of sexually explicit material to minors, the Court noted that "while these studies all agree that a causal link [between exposure to explicit material and impaired ethical and moral development] has not been demonstrated, they are equally agreed that a causal link has not been disproved either." Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.S. 629, 642 (1968) (internal quotation omitted); see also American Booksellers Ass'n v. Hudnut, 771 F.2d 323, 329 n.3 (7th Cir. 1985). The same uncertainty prevails here, and suffices to place the legislative judgment within the realm of reason under the standards applicable to the political branches' management of prisons. The evidence is simply not conclusive on the efficacy of a ban on pornography in promoting prisoners' rehabilitation. For judges seeking only a reasonable connection between legislative goals and actions, scientific indeterminacy is deter- minative. * * * The remaining Safley factors further substantiate the over- all reasonableness of the regulations. The second involves the prisoners' alternative means of exercising the right at stake. Of course if the "right" at stake is defined in terms of the materials excluded by the ban, any regulation will come up short. The Court accordingly observed in Thornburgh that the relevant right "must be viewed sensibly and expan- sively," 490 U.S. at 417, though it stated no method for actually carrying out the definitional process. In Thorn- burgh, where the regulation barred all "sexually explicit material which by its nature or content poses a threat to the security, good order, or discipline of the institution, or facili- tates criminal activity," id. at 405 n.5, the Court found the second factor "clearly satisfied" because "the regulations [there at issue] permit a broad range of publications to be sent, received, and read," id. at 418. In so doing, it made no inquiry into the scope of sexually explicit material not covered by the ban. Thus, unless there is some minimum entitlement to smut in prison, the origins of which must be obscure, this factor can hardly be fatal.7 The third Safley factor concerns the adverse impact "on guards and other inmates, and on the allocation of prison __________ 7 Even if there were such a bizarre entitlement, the regulations would still satisfy this factor, as they leave the inmate free to enjoy all written forms of smut not barred by the regulations upheld in Thornburgh. resources" of accommodating the right claimed. 482 U.S. at 90. It thus seems in part a restatement of the deferential balancing called for under the first factor: if Congress may reasonably conclude that pornography increases the risk of prison rape, then the adverse impact is substantial. Accom- modating the right poses a threat to the safety of guards and other inmates. The issue of the allocation of prison resources we take up below; we think the third and fourth factors are strongly interrelated. The fourth Safley factor poses the question whether there are alternatives that can accommodate that right "at de minimis costs to valid penological interests." Safley, 482 U.S. at 91. This is not, the Court emphasized, a " 'least restrictive alternative' test." Id. at 90. The most obvious alternative is a detailed prisoner-by-prisoner (and presumably publication-by-publication) sifting to determine whether a particular publication will harm the rehabilitation of a particu- lar prisoner. The costs of this approach seem far from de minimis. Apart from the purely administrative burden of such a process, the exercise of such broad discretion seems highly conducive to just the sort of conflicting decisions that give bite to vagueness concerns. And the reality is that prisoners are likely to pass pornographic materials about, so that prisoner-by-prisoner determinations may run aground on the "ripple effect" that the Court mentioned in Safley, 482 U.S. at 90. Even if pornography could be directed only to those not likely to be adversely affected, it could find its way to others, interfering with their rehabilitation and increasing threats to safety. Of course the flip side of avoiding the costs and hazards of a grant of broad discretion to wardens is the possibility of preventing delivery of materials that, either generally or for a specific set of (effectively segregated) prisoners, pose little or no threat of the harm Congress sought to diminish. Outside prison walls this concern is addressed by the overbreadth doctrine. Here it seems to us captured in part by the demand for a rational relation between the regulation and the goal, and by consideration of alternatives under the fourth "factor." Thus, the objections to a more flexible standard-- such as one that would vest discretion in wardens to prevent delivery of materials in any case where in his judgment it would impair a specific prisoner's rehabilitation--go a long way to rebut the claim. The dissent, nonetheless, seems to regard only such a case- by-case approach as constitutional, and makes much of vari- ous hypothetical situations in which the categorical ban could unneccessarily exclude certain publications. See Dissent at 15-21. To the extent that these hypotheticals assume direct enforcement of the Ensign Amendment, the likelihood of such enforcement is, as we have noted, quite remote and not before us in this case. Further, the actions of the Bureau of Prisons also suggest that the likelihood of this sort of exclu- sion under the actual regulatory scheme is remote. The Bureau's Program Statement, for example, listing examples of permissible publications, cites National Geographic; Our Bod[ies], Our Selves; Sports Illustrated (Swimsuit Edition); and the Victoria's Secret Catalog. P.S. 5266.07, at 7. We find it all but impossible to believe that the Swimsuit Edition and Victoria's Secret pass muster while Michelangelo's David or concentration camp pictures fail; nor has there been any suggestion that any prison official has attempted to imple- ment such a bizarre interpretation. As there is no allegation that women in segregated women's prisons are demanding Playboy, neither the possibility of such demand nor the Bureau's possible response assists plaintiffs in their over- breadth claim.8 Leaving aside these possible fringe applications of the regulation, we again note that the regulation by its terms only restricts pictures; a prisoner may read anything he pleases. __________ 8 To the extent that the Dissent's insistence on individualized determinations turns on a view that general rules with any impact on First Amendment values must correspond to the underlying reason in every application, see, e.g., Dissent at 1 (suggesting that government must show that "any pictorial display of nudity or sexual activity will be harmful to the rehabilitation of all prisoners") (emphasis in original), it asserts a burden that few general rules could satisfy. The dissent's appeal to the value of ideas, pointing by way of example to the vistas opened for Malcolm X by his prison reading, see Dissent at 15-16, thus makes little sense here. Congress could, we think, reasonably be skeptical of the proposition that study of the pictures in Penthouse would help a prisoner become "an intelligent customer in the mar- ketplace of ideas." If anything, the ban could strengthen the impact of literature by removing the distraction of pictures that in almost every case would be pornographic. In any event, even under conventional overbreadth doc- trine outside of prison, overbreadth claims by those on the margins of pornography have fared poorly. See, e.g., Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U.S. 50, 61 (1976) ("Since there is surely a less vital interest in the uninhibited exhibition of material that is on the borderline between pornography and artistic expression than in the free dissemi- nation of ideas of social and political significance ... we think this is an inappropriate case in which to adjudicate the hypothetical claims of persons not before the Court.") And regardless of the type of speech at issue, narrow or improba- ble excesses of a statute are not a ground for invalidation before application shows their reality: [W]here a statute regulates expressive conduct, the scope of the statute does not render it unconstitutional unless its overbreadth is not only "real, but substantial as well, judged in relation to the statute's plainly legitimate sweep." Even where a statute at its margins infringes on protected expression, "facial invalidation is inappropri- ate if the 'remainder of the statute ... covers a whole range of easily identifiable and constitutionally proscriba- ble ... conduct....' " Osborne v. Ohio, 495 U.S. 103, 112 (1990) (citations omitted) (ellipses in original). Accordingly, such problems of applica- tion can be left to the time when, if ever, they arise. We find that the statute and regulation satisfy Safley's demand for reasonableness, scoring adequately on all four factors. * * * Plaintiffs argue that if we are unpersuaded by the district court's analysis we should remand the case to allow them to introduce evidence supporting their position. But that sug- gestion misconceives the legal issue under Safley. The ques- tion is not whether curtailment of pictorial smut will advance the prisons' rehabilitative project, but whether Congress could reasonably have believed that it would do so. The studies cited above, coupled with Congress's implicit appeal to ethical norms against the undue stimulation of carnal appe- tites, indicate the reasonableness of such a belief. If the Bureau of Prisons applies the regulations in a manner that would violate the Safley priciples, of course, that would be another case. Accordingly, the district court should have granted the defendants' motion to dismiss plaintiffs' com- plaint insofar as that complaint rested upon Safley. * * * Besides the overbreadth issue, which we have already addressed in the Safley context, plaintiffs have raised two additional theories--excessive vagueness and a claim that the regulations' distinction between pictorial and verbal works is content-based. In fact, the distinction between pictorial and verbal works seems more directed to form than to content, and in any event we have seen that Safley's neutrality requirement both displaces conventional First Amendment strictures on content-based limits and is satisfied by these regulations. Although Safley may well function as an all- encompassing free speech test for the circulation of reading materials in prison, supplanting otherwise applicable First Amendment doctrine, it may be that plaintiffs' vagueness claim has independent force. If it did, of course, the role of the Bureau of Prisons, as manager rather than as law enforc- er, might well play an important role in resolution of the claim. Accordingly, as the district court has not addressed these vagueness issues, we remand the case for it to do so. In the meantime, we lift the permanent injunction that it has imposed on enforcement of the regulations. So ordered. Wald, Circuit Judge, dissenting: The prohibition to all federal prisoners of publications "featuring nudity" or depict- ing "sexually explicit" activities indisputably raises First Amendment concerns. See, e.g., Reno v. American Civil Liberties Union, 117 S. Ct. 2329, 2346 (1997) ("In evaluating the free speech rights of adults, we have made it perfectly clear that sexual expression which is indecent but not obscene is protected by the First Amendment.") (internal quotation omitted); Martin v. Struthers, 319 U.S. 141, 143 (1943) (noting that the right of freedom of speech "necessarily protects the right to receive [publications]"). Indeed, if the First Amendment, at its core, is designed to promote the free exchange of ideas, the debate in this case goes to the very heart of its protections. The government argues that the reason all publications featuring nudity or sexually explicit material, whether or not they are pornographic or obscene, should be withheld from all federal prisoners is that any pictorial display of nudity or sexual activity communicates messages that are harmful to the rehabilitation of all prison- ers. Relying on what it claims to be the inherent reasonable- ness of a legislative judgment that such materials are always inimical to rehabilitation, the government throughout this case has steadfastly resisted creating any kind of record to support such a wide-reaching incursion on the constitutional rights of incarcerated individuals. Today, the majority un- questioningly endorses the government's approach. Because I believe this result sets an unwise and arbitrary precedent that runs contrary to prior case law, I respectfully dissent.1 __________ 1 I find it very significant that two of our sister courts have recently reached results opposite from that set forth by the majori- ty today. In Mauro v. Arpaio, 1998 WL 550190 (9th Cir. Sept. 1, 1998), the Ninth Circuit invalidated a county prison system's ban on the possession of all materials containing "any graphic representa- tion of frontal nudity." Although the county claimed that its interests in safety, the rehabilitation of inmates, and the reduction of sexual harassment of guards supported such a ban, the court held that the county had not "carried its burden to show that such a far reaching prohibition is 'reasonably related' to legitimate penological interests"; in particular, it had "offer[ed] no proof or reasoned It appears to need restating once again that prisoners do not lose all their constitutional rights when the prison door clangs behind them. While the prison gate may serve to isolate those inside from the outside world, it does not, as the Supreme Court has taken pains to emphasize, "form a barrier separating prison inmates from the protections of the Consti- tution." Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 84 (1987). Although the majority pays lip service to this canon, it ignores an important corollary: Whatever sentiments we might hold regarding prisoners for the crimes they have committed, these sentiments must not infect our determination of the prisoners' constitutional rights. Indeed, the Supreme Court has recently reaffirmed, albeit in a different context, that " 'a bare ... desire to harm a politically unpopular group cannot constitute a legitimate governmental interest.' " Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 634 (1996) (quoting Department of Agriculture v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534 (1973)) (invalidating state constitutional amendment prohibiting official action de- signed to protect homosexual persons from discrimination). So long as prisoners retain constitutional rights, including First Amendment rights, see O'Lone v. Estate of Shabazz, 482 U.S. 342, 348 (1987) ("Inmates clearly retain protections __________ explanation" for the ban. Id. at *7. And in Waterman v. Verniero, 1998 WL 416585 (D.N.J. July 22, 1998), a district court invalidated a state statute prohibiting inmates in a specialized facility for sex offenders from possessing or obtaining "sexually oriented materi- als" (defined as any description or depiction of "sexual activity or associated anatomical area"; see Waterman v. Verniero, 1998 WL 354932, at *4 (D.N.J. June 29, 1998) (preliminary injunction)). Despite the state's claim that such materials would disrupt the rehabilitation of sex offenders at the institution, the court held that the state legislature that enacted the ban was motivated by public outrage over pedophiliac crimes rather than rehabilitative interests. Waterman, 1998 WL 416585, at *3. Moreover, the court noted, the literature on the effects of such publications was too unsettled to support a finding that a rational relationship existed between the ban and rehabilitative interests. Id. In both cases, the courts found the broad scope of the ban, in particular its application to publications featuring nudity, to be unjustifiable in light of any evidence advanced by the government to support it. afforded by the First Amendment ...."), our duty is to ensure that these rights are not impermissibly curtailed.2 It is equally true, however, that the unique and difficult task of running a prison will often necessitate some incursion on inmates' constitutional rights. A prisoner's desire to leave the prison once a week to attend religious services, for example, or his desire to correspond with other inmates may conflict with the prison's need to maintain institutional securi- ty. In these instances, courts must give a large measure of deference to the prison administrators who are actively in- volved in the daily operations of the institution. Courts are not in the best position to judge when or in what manner certain institutional interests may require some action on the part of prison officials to respond to the "complex and intract- able" problems of prison administration. Procunier v. Mar- tinez, 416 U.S. 396, 405 (1974), overruled in part by Thorn- burgh v. Abbott, 490 U.S. 401 (1989). Most of these problems, as the Supreme Court reminds us, "require expertise, com- prehensive planning, and the commitment of resources, all of which are peculiarly within the province of the legislative and executive branches of government." Id. As the majority has duly noted, the Court's standard in Safley recognizes the need to forge a balance between the competing interests of prison administration and prisoners' constitutional rights. As I read this standard, it embraces two principles. First, fundamental rights of prisoners must give way to governmental concerns more readily than the __________ 2 As our Chief Judge has previously noted, the special place of prisoners in our society makes them more dependent on judicial protection than perhaps any other group. Few minorities are so "discrete and insular," so little able to defend their interests through participation in the political process, so vulnerable to oppression by an unsympathetic ma- jority. Federal courts have a special responsibility to ensure that the members of such defenseless groups are not deprived of their constitutional rights. Doe v. District of Columbia, 701 F.2d 948, 960 n.14 (D.C. Cir. 1983) (separate statement of Edwards, J.). fundamental rights of nonprisoners. In adopting a test "less restrictive than that ordinarily applied to alleged infringe- ments of fundamental constitutional rights," O'Lone, 482 U.S. at 349, the Court intended to ensure that "courts afford appropriate deference to prison officials," id. To require that prison regulations infringing upon fundamental rights under- go strict scrutiny, as they would outside the prison context, would place an inordinately high obstacle in the way of prison administrators' attempts to run their institution safely and efficiently. Second, and significantly, the Court did not in- tend Safley 's lesser standard of review to negate prisoners' constitutional rights altogether, as the majority seems to suggest. The Court did not say, for example, that prison regulations are valid if there is any conceivable basis for their existence, as rational basis review is typically formulated. See, e.g., United States R.R. Retirement Bd. v. Fritz, 449 U.S. 166, 179 (1980) (noting that where, under rational basis review, "there are plausible reasons for Congress' action, our inquiry is at an end"). Rather, the task for courts is to determine, while giving appropriate deference to the judg- ment of prison officials, whether a challenged regulation is, in fact, reasonable or whether it is an "exaggerated response" to the "legitimate governmental interest put forward to justify it." Safley, 482 U.S. at 89-90 (emphasis added); see also Laurence H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law 1445 n.21 (2d ed. 1988) ("Any limit placed on the Court's imagination vis-a-vis legislative purpose must be recognized as a tightened form of scrutiny."). A governmental institution is permitted "regulation more intrusive than what may lawfully apply to the general public," Majority Opinion ("Maj.Op.") at 5, not simply because of its status but rather because of the identifi- able, and unique, needs of that institution. And although the need for flexibility is perhaps at its highest in the prison environment, the need for limits on that flexibility is also paramount: Unlike government employees, students, or other participants in governmental institutions, prisoners have no choice about whether to be subject to the power of the state. To read Safley--as the majority appears to--as permitting unblinking deference to any "plausible" legislative judgment about the "rehabilitative" benefits of denying a prisoner's most fundamental constitutional right, i.e., her freedom to read, renders any and all prisoners' constitutional rights a nullity. I had thought it went without saying that courts do not rely on the mere assertion of a regulation's drafters that the regulation is reasonable; to do so would amount to an abdication of our judicial role. See, e.g., Salaam v. Lockhart, 905 F.2d 1168, 1171 (8th Cir. 1990) ("We would misconstrue [Thornburgh, O'Lone, and Safley ] if we deferred not only to the choices between reasonable policies made by prison offi- cials but to their justifications for the policies as well."); Campbell v. Miller, 787 F.2d 217, 227 n.17 (7th Cir. 1986) ("[D]eference to the administrative expertise and discretion- ary authority of correctional officials must be schooled, not absolute."). Nor can the judicial role be diminished to the disappearing point solely because the original decisionmaking body in this case is Congress itself rather than the Bureau of Prisons ("BOP"). Cf. Sable Communications of California, Inc. v. FCC, 492 U.S. 115, 129 (1989) ("To the extent that the federal parties suggest that we should defer to Congress' conclusion about an issue of constitutional law, our answer is that while we do not ignore it, it is our task in the end to decide whether Congress has violated the Constitution. This is particularly true where the Legislature has concluded that its product does not violate the First Amendment.").3 The Safley standard reconciles prisoners' constitutional rights with institutional needs and defers to prison administrators as the most appropriate articulators of those needs; so long as Congress acts with those same needs in mind, it is entitled to the same deference. But were we simply to defer to Con- gress's assertion that the Ensign Amendment ("the Amend- ment") was reasonably related to the interest asserted, there would be no need for judicial review at all, for no statute __________ 3 Of course, because the majority concludes that the BOP's regu- lations, and not the Ensign Amendment, are controlling in this case, the majority's focus on Congress's conclusions may be misguided. See, e.g., Maj. Op. at 11 ("It does not matter whether we agree with the legislature, only whether we find its judgment rational."). But see note 4, infra. infringing on inmates' constitutional rights would fail to satis- fy this test. The Court has reminded us that the Safley standard "is not toothless," Thornburgh, 490 U.S. at 414 (internal quotation omitted); more precisely, it is not a license for lawmakers, any more than prison wardens, to shortchange the constitutional rights that the Supreme Court has insisted prisoners continue to possess. Only if our assessment is not a cursory one can we give adequate weight to both concerns that underlie the Safley standard. See, e.g., Salaam, 905 F.2d at 1171 n.6 ("Reasonableness in this context refers not only to the relation between the goals of a regulation and its means, but also to the balance struck between the needs of the prison administrators and the constitutional rights of prisoners."). It is crucial, therefore, to ensure that although the strict- ness of our review is lessened, it is not eliminated altogether. Our task, ultimately, is to assess the fit between the interest proffered and the remedy adopted--whether the regulation under consideration is a reasonable means of addressing the legitimate penological interest put forward by the govern- ment. In Safley itself, for example, although the prison's asserted interests in security and rehabilitation were suffi- cient to justify some restriction on the right to marry, the Court held that the particular restriction adopted was too broad to be upheld. See Safley, 482 U.S. at 97-98 ("No doubt legitimate security concerns may require placing reasonable restrictions upon an inmate's right to marry, and may justify requiring approval of the superintendent. The Missouri reg- ulation, however, represents an exaggerated response to such security objectives."); id. at 98 ("[I]n requiring refusal of permission absent a finding of a compelling reason to allow the marriage, the rule sweeps much more broadly than can be explained by petitioners' penological objectives."). In Thorn- burgh, by contrast, the pre-Amendment version of the restric- tions under consideration here were found to represent a reasonable response to institutional concerns because the "individualized nature" of the determinations ensured that the policy would not result in "needless exclusions." Thornburgh, 490 U.S. at 416-17; see also id. (noting that even a publica- tion that met one of the criteria for exclusion would be rejected "only if it is determined to meet that standard under the conditions prevailing at the institution at the time"). These cases illustrate that the standard of review established by Safley sets some limits on the means the government may use to further penological interests. Although these limits are flexible, they are by no means as vaporous as the majori- ty rules them to be. I agree that rehabilitation is, conceptually, a legitimate governmental interest, even if no one is sure how to achieve it and the Federal Sentencing Guidelines have abandoned it as an attainable goal. Compare Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.S. 817, 823 (1974) ("[S]ince most offenders will eventually return to society, another paramount objective of the corrections sys- tem is the rehabilitation of those committed to its custody.") and Dawson v. Scurr, 986 F.2d 257, 260 (8th Cir. 1993) (noting that rehabilitation is a "legitimate objective") with Kerr v. Puckett, 138 F.3d 321, 324 (7th Cir. 1998) ("Congress abandoned 'rehabilitation' as a justification of imprisonment when it enacted the Sentencing Reform Act of 1984.") and S. Rep. No. 98-225 (1983), at 38, reprinted in 1984 U.S.C.C.A.N. 3182, 3221 ("[A]lmost everyone involved in the criminal justice system now doubts that rehabilitation can be induced reliably in a prison setting, and it is now quite certain that no one can really detect whether or when a prisoner is rehabilitated."). Where the majority and I part company is on the ultimate question: Has any "valid, rational connection" between the extremely broad ban on publications featuring nudity or explicit sexual activity and rehabilitation been shown in this case? And while I certainly do not discount the possibility that a ban more narrowly targeted on certain kinds of violent pornography or even on certain types of prisoners might satisfy this requirement, I cannot conclude, on the present record, that these regulations implementing the Amendment pass muster.4 __________ 4 The majority characterizes Amatel's attack on the Amendment itself as a "pre-enforcement challenge" that is invalid because, in promulgating implementing regulations, the government has I believe that the determination of whether a regulation (or statute) is reasonably related to a legitimate penological interest must depend, in all but the most obvious cases, on the evidentiary support for that nexus in the record before the court. Of course I recognize too that the question of what or how much evidence is necessary may depend on what logic or everyday experience show us to be the connection between the disputed means and the rehabilitative end. If the Amendment prohibited the distribution of publications containing escape plans, the connection between the ban and the penological interest in institutional security would be obvious, and we could uphold such a prohibition based on little or no demonstrated evidence. Where, as here, however, the connection (between nudity and rehabilitation) is far murkier, courts (and I would include legislators as well) far removed from the day-to-day operations of a prison are much __________ "waived certain provisions of the law." Maj. Op. at 4, citing Salvation Army v. Department of Community Affairs, 919 F.2d 183, 192 (3d Cir. 1990). In contrast to Salvation Army, however, we have no "express assurance" that the BOP will not enforce the breadth of the Amendment, cf. Salvation Army, 919 F.2d at 192; indeed, the regulations state simply that "publications containing nudity illustrative of medical, educational, or anthropological con- tent may be excluded" from the definition of "features," see 28 C.F.R. s 540.72(b)(3) (1997) (emphasis added). Moreover, at oral argument, counsel for the BOP acknowledged that under the cur- rent regulations, wardens retain considerable discretion as to whether a publication "features" nudity. See Tr. of Oral Arg. at 6. The government's "waiver" of certain portions of the Amendment thus cannot be so blithely assumed and may in fact be an impermis- sible narrowing of the Amendment's mandate. See, e.g., Public Citizen v. FTC, 869 F.2d 1541, 1557 (D.C. Cir. 1989) ("While agencies may safely be assumed to have discretion to create excep- tions at the margins of a regulatory field, they are not thereby empowered to weigh the costs and benefits of regulation at every turn; agencies surely do not have inherent authority to second- guess Congress' calculations."); Alabama Power Co. v. Costle, 636 F.2d 323, 358 (D.C. Cir. 1979) ("Categorical exemptions from the clear commands of a regulatory statute, though sometimes permit- ted, are not favored."). less able to answer the question accurately on their own; indeed, the very reason that Safley prescribes a great mea- sure of deference to prison administrators is that they are in the best position to provide answers involving means and ends in prison administration. See, e.g., Kennedy v. Los Angeles Police Dep't, 901 F.2d 702, 713 (9th Cir. 1989) ("The principle that courts must provide wide latitude to prison policies needed to maintain institutional order and security necessarily presupposes that the administrators have crafted those policies with careful deliberation.") (citation omitted). We would normally be expected to give a healthy dose of deference to the judgment of prison officials as to their experience and apprehensions in support of a regulation, but where, as in these regulations, these same officials were, so far as we can tell, never consulted on the Amendment's merits and under its terms are not allowed to exercise any judgment about what kinds of nudity or sexually explicit material are allowed inside the prison walls, I do not believe Safley permits us simply to assume the existence of evidence showing a connection between the regulation and a rehabilita- tive goal, as we might under rational-basis review and as the majority has in fact done here. Safley itself provides a useful example of how too Spartan a record can doom a regulation. The Court's rejection of the marriage restriction at issue in that case clearly turned on the quality of the evidence before the Court; four times the Court concluded that the regulation was not reasonably relat- ed to penological interests based "on this record." See Saf- ley, 482 U.S. at 97 ("We conclude that on this record, the Missouri prison regulation, as written, is not reasonably related to these penological interests."); id. at 98 ("Nor, on this record, is the marriage restriction reasonably related to the articulated rehabilitation goal."); id. at 99 ("Moreover, although not necessary to the disposition of this case, we note that on this record the rehabilitative objective asserted to support the regulation itself is suspect."); id. ("On this record, however, the almost complete ban on the decision to marry is not reasonably related to legitimate penological objectives.") (emphases added). This repeated qualification of the Court's negative conclusion about the validity of the regulation starkly suggests that while a reasonable relation- ship might possibly have been demonstrated between the marriage restriction and the interests asserted, the prison had failed to present sufficient evidence to establish that relationship. The majority's apparent conclusion that the government bears no responsibility for compiling evidence to support the breadth of its ban--in other words, that the courts may simply hypothesize a rational connection--runs counter to the wisdom of several other circuit courts. See, e.g., Shimer v. Washington, 100 F.3d 506, 509 (7th Cir. 1996) (prison admin- istration "must proffer some evidence to support its restric- tion of ... constitutional rights" under Safley standard); Mann v. Reynolds, 46 F.3d 1055, 1061 (10th Cir. 1995) (invalidating restrictions on contact visits with attorneys, noting that "defendants were unable to provide any evidence the restrictions on contact were reasonably related to prison security"); Muhammad v. Pitcher, 35 F.3d 1081, 1085 (6th Cir. 1994) (invalidating prison mail regulation because "there is no evidence in the record supporting Defendants' factual claim" that policy was reasonably related to interest in con- serving resources); Walker v. Sumner, 917 F.2d 382, 386 (9th Cir. 1990) ("Prison authorities cannot rely on general or conclusory assertions to support their policies. Rather, they must first identify the specific penological interests involved and then demonstrate both that those specific interests are the actual bases for their policies and that the policies are reasonably related to the furtherance of the identified inter- ests. An evidentiary showing is required as to each point."); Waterman, 1998 WL 354932, at *10 ("To establish that a legitimate penological interest supports a statute, a state must provide evidence that the interest it proffered is the actual basis for the statute."); Powell v. Riveland, 991 F. Supp. 1249, 1254 (W.D. Wash. 1997) (upholding restriction on sexually explicit incoming mail where "[p]rior to implement- ing the policy, research was done on the effects of sexually explicit material and the policy/regulation was written to target those harmful materials"). In sum, it is clear, as Judge Posner has suggested, that the Safley analysis cannot be met simply on the basis of "pure conjecture." Reed v. Faulkner, 842 F.2d 960, 963 (7th Cir. 1988); see also id. ("[T]o suppose that the wearing of dreadlocks [as an expres- sion of religious belief] would lead to racial violence is, on this record, the piling of conjecture upon conjecture. The poten- tial infringement of the free-speech clause of the First Amendment is too plain to warrant comment."). Safley cer- tainly does not stand for the proposition that Congress or prison officials may "set constitutional standards by fiat." Whitney v. Brown, 882 F.2d 1068, 1074 (6th Cir. 1989). I might, therefore, have been able to go along--as the majority does here--with deferring to Congress had the government seen fit to proffer evidence that links a ban on the prohibited publications to rehabilitation or if the connec- tion between that ban and rehabilitation was so self-evident that no further evidence was necessary to demonstrate its reasonableness. But neither event has occurred, and the majority's once-over-lightly of the scientific literature that does exist certainly does not accomplish the task, as the majority itself admits. See Maj. Op. at 14 ("The point of this is not to suggest that a causal link has been shown. The array of academic authority on the other side is at least as substantial, and quite possibly more so."). At best, it can be said that a few studies have shown a causative relationship between violent pornography and short-term increases in aggression--perhaps a helpful finding with regard to the security interests of prison authorities but next to useless in determining the effect on any long-term interest in rehabilita- tion.5 In all other respects, the relationship between pornog- __________ 5 Of course, the evidence to support a prison regulation need not be in the form of scholarly studies; affidavits from prison officials could also suffice as the basis for analysis. See, e.g., Safley, 482 U.S. at 98 (testimony of prison officials that they had experienced no problems with the marriages of male inmates relied on as evidence that ban was overbroad); Harper v. Wallingford, 877 F.2d 728, 733 (9th Cir. 1989) (finding prison regulation banning receipt of material espousing consensual sexual relationships between male raphy and criminal activity is merely correlative,6 and there is no evidence that simply viewing nonpornographic nudity or depictions of sexual activities (as opposed to pornography) has any effect at all.7 See, e.g., Edward Donnerstein, Daniel Linz & Steven Penrod, The Question of Pornography 177 (1987) (stating conclusion of Attorney General's Commission on Pornography that "in general, the scientific evidence shows no causal relationship between exposure to [nonviolent and nondegrading sexual] depictions and acts of sexual vio- lence" and noting that the authors' "view of the scientific literature ... is in agreement with this conclusion"); id. at 40-48 (citing studies finding that exposing already angered men to nonviolent pornography can cause a short-term in- crease in their aggressive tendencies); Ernest D. Giglio, Pornography in Denmark: A Public Policy Model for the United States? in 8 Comparative Social Research 281, 285 (Richard F. Tomasson ed., 1985) ("[A] positive causal relation- ship between pornography and sex crimes has not been documented by criminologists and psychologists."); Berl Kutchinsky, Obscenity and Pornography: Behavioral As- pects, in Encyclopedia of Crime and Justice 1077, 1083 (Sanford Kadish ed., 1983) (noting that the authoritative studies on the link between pornography and crime have concluded that there is apparently no causative relationship between nonviolent pornography and sex crimes). Indeed, it __________ adults and juvenile males to be reasonably related to rehabilitation based on affidavit from prison psychiatrist). 6 Correlation cannot be sufficient to satisfy Safley 's requirement of a "valid, rational connection." Even if it could be shown, for example, that the majority of those who commit violent crimes are also avid Bible readers, this finding would not constitute a basis for prohibiting all prisoners from reading the Bible. 7 By pornography, I mean "a depiction (as in writing or painting) of licentiousness or lewdness: a portrayal of erotic behavior de- signed to cause sexual excitement." Webster's Third New Interna- tional Dictionary 1767 (1976). There is, of course, much material that features nudity or depicts sexual activity that would not qualify as pornography under any definition, including many highly regard- ed works of art. is unclear even in the studies finding a positive connection between violent pornography and aggressive behavior wheth- er the aggression is due to the violent content of the material or its sexual content. See, e.g., Larry Baron & Murray A. Straus, Four Theories of Rape in American Society 8 (1989) ("It seems reasonable to conclude ... that it is the violent content rather than the sexual content that facilitates aggres- sion."); Richard A. Posner, Sex and Reason 368 (1992) ("[T]he effects [of violent pornography] may be due to the violence per se rather than to the erotic component."). Thus, while it is entirely possible that a narrower publication ban than that accomplished by the Amendment could be supported by the available literature, cf., e.g., Dawson, 986 F.2d at 262 (uphold- ing regulation limiting time, place, and conditions under which certain inmates could view materials), neither the government nor the majority has laid the barest foundation for the far-reaching ban promulgated. The majority's level of comfort in relying on any statement of any legislator as to what he thinks will encourage rehabilitation as the sole basis for taking away a First Amendment right is very surprising to me, especially since its holding today goes far beyond what any court has previously condoned in depriving prisoners of constitutional rights on the mere assertion of a legislator that he supposes rehabilitation to be so advanced. In this respect, I believe that it needs to be stressed that the assertion of "rehabilitation" as the reason for impinging on prisoners' First Amendment rights is particularly discon- certing in its potential for abuse. Unlike its interest in institutional security, the contours of the government's inter- est in rehabilitation are quite amorphous and ill-defined. At the most basic level, the goal of rehabilitation might be stated as returning the prisoner to society in a state so that he will henceforth behave in a law-abiding manner, but no one, not even Congress, is so immodest as to claim secure knowledge of how this goal is to be achieved in individual cases, let alone in the aggregate; most often, rehabilitation efforts involve therapy, drug and alcohol counseling, basic education, or job training, but even in these positive attempts, the results are far from reassuring. Against that backdrop, it is extremely difficult, if not impossible, to ascertain precisely if or how a particular publication may work to frustrate the rehabilitative goals of prisoners. To start with, there is no consensus on whether in order to transform a law violator into a good citizen, he must be "remolded" attitudinally and instilled with desirable values or whether it is sufficient that he be con- vinced that further criminal activity would be counterproduc- tive in his own case, whatever his vision of society or the world. Rehabilitation may also be viewed--in the majority's parlance--as an effort to direct the "character growth" of prisoners by limiting the reading materials to which he has access. See Maj. Op. at 11. But, whatever the rehabilitative vision, it should not be possible to proceed on some vague assertion of an interest in "rehabilitation" without the need to define the term or to show a connection between the pro- scribed activity and the chosen definition; to do so runs an overwhelming risk of overregulation and invasion of the in- nermost recesses of the human mind and spirit. Indeed, undertaking the Herculean task of "character-molding" is inherently problematic in its First Amendment implications, for it presumably involves casting emerging prisoners in society's own image. This, of course, is the antithesis of First Amendment freedoms; indeed, "[t]otalitarian ideologies we profess to hate have styled as 'rehabilitation' the process of molding the unorthodox mind to the shape of prevailing dogma." Sobell v. Reed, 327 F. Supp. 1294, 1305 (S.D.N.Y. 1971); cf., e.g., Tinker v. Des Moines Indep. Community Sch. Dist., 393 U.S. 503, 511 (1969) (noting "this Nation's repudiation of the principle that a State might so conduct its schools as to foster a homogeneous people") (internal quota- tion omitted). Under this theory, lawmakers who believe that books on Russian history may lead to disrespect for the United States may ban those books for prisoners; lawmakers who hold pro-life views may prevent prisoners from reading publications describing Roe v. Wade; and lawmakers who hold an antiquated view of the role women should play in society may ban the distribution in prisons of publications with feminist themes. Each of these actions could logically be taken in the name of rehabilitation, broadly defined, and each, without doubt, would contribute to a continual eviscer- ation of the First Amendment rights of prisoners. Cf., e.g., Stanley v. Georgia, 394 U.S. 557, 565-66 (1969) ("Our whole constitutional heritage rebels at the thought of giving govern- ment the power to control men's minds.... [I]t cannot constitutionally premise legislation on the desirability of con- trolling a person's private thoughts."); McCabe v. Arave, 827 F.2d 634, 638 (9th Cir. 1987) ("Given the strength of First Amendment protection for freedom of belief, prison authori- ties have no legitimate penological interest in excluding reli- gious books from the prison library merely because they contain racist views.") (citation omitted); American Booksel- lers Ass'n, Inc. v. Hudnut, 771 F.2d 323, 330 (7th Cir. 1985), aff'd mem., 475 U.S. 1001 (1986) ("If the fact that speech plays a role in a process of conditioning were enough to permit governmental regulation, that would be the end of freedom of speech."). These examples may sound extreme-- they are--but the majority's rationale easily encompasses them in its umbrella-like authorization for restricting prison- ers' reading material on the basis of a minimum plausibility test for tying the censorship to some vague rehabilitation concept. Even if the goal of rehabilitation is a more modest one--to convince the prisoner his own best interest lies in avoiding future crime--it is hard to see how that goal is furthered by returning him unequipped to be an intelligent customer in the marketplace of ideas. And while serious questions may well be raised about the value of some of the publications banned under the Amendment, there is much that falls under this broad ban that speaks intelligently to mankind, including prisoners: Michelangelo's David, for example, or grim photo- graphs of naked bodies piled in the pits of Germany's concen- tration camps.8 There is even a potential for such depictions __________ 8 The majority suggests that the application of the regulations to prohibit artistic depictions of nudity or to documentary photographs of wartime atrocities would be "bizarre." See Maj. Op. at 17. But, in fact, even the regulations do not provide for any exceptions to the nudity ban based on a publication's artistic or political content. See 28 C.F.R. s 540.72(b)(3) (providing possible exception only for of nudity to strike a life-changing chord with some prisoners, a change that should not be prevented from coming to fruition. Malcolm X wrote of his prison experience: I have often reflected upon the new vistas that reading opened to me. I knew right there in prison that reading had changed forever the course of my life. As I see it today, the ability to read awoke inside me some long dormant craving to be mentally alive.... My home- made education gave me, with every book that I read, a little bit more sensitivity to the deafness, dumbness, and blindness that was afflicting the black race in America. Alex Haley & Malcolm X, The Autobiography of Malcolm X 180 (1965).9 If rehabilitation is to be deemed a legitimate penological interest, the term must be given some shape, at least when it collides with fundamental liberties. Of course, as the majori- ty notes, the Constitution has nothing to say about what messages the government may choose to communicate as a speaker. See, e.g., Rust v. Sullivan, 500 U.S. 173, 193 (1991) ("The Government can, without violating the Constitution, selectively fund a program to encourage certain activities it believes to be in the public interest, without at the same time funding an alternate program which seeks to deal with the problem in another way."). Congress or the BOP may make __________ nudity "illustrative of medical, educational, or anthropological con- tent"). And although the Victoria's Secret catalog and the Sports Illustrated Swimsuit Edition are listed by the BOP as permissible publications, the basis for their exclusion from the ban is left to conjecture. Cf. id. s 540.72(b)(2) (defining "nudity" as "a pictorial depiction where ... female breasts are exposed"). As for the notion that explicit descriptions of sexual activities and nudity are still permitted (an illustrated version of Henry Miller's Tropic of Cancer is banned but a nonillustrated version is not), this only underscores the arbitrariness of the rehabilitative nexus. 9 Of course, lawmakers who believe that Malcolm X inspires separatism and racial consciousness may, under the "remolding" theory of rehabilitation, prohibit prisoners from reading his writings as well. whatever recreational reading it wishes available in the prison libraries without offending the Constitution; they may even provide each prisoner with a tract on the harms of pornogra- phy in the hope that some readers will take its lessons to heart. But it is quite a different matter for prisons to deny all access to certain publications in the name of rehabilitation, particularly in such a broad and overreaching manner as this one. If prisoners are to retain any First Amendment rights, the mere assertion of "rehabilitation" as the interest to be served by a particular regulation cannot serve to extinguish those rights altogether. Because the Amendment and the regulations eliminate the discretion of prison wardens to make individual determina- tions about how particular publications will affect particular prisoners in particular prison settings, even rehabilitatively, I believe it was incumbent upon the government to point to some evidence demonstrating a connection between all publi- cations that are sexually explicit or that feature nudity and a tendency to engage in criminal or disruptive behavior, keep- ing in mind that our task is to determine whether such a connection is reasonably likely to exist, not whether one might be conceivable. Cf., e.g., Mauro, 1998 WL 550190, at *7 (considering whether all materials depicting nudity are "reasonably likely" to cause violence or to be used to harass guards). Neither the government nor the majority has point- ed to any such evidence. Indeed, the proposition that all material that is sexually explicit or that features nudity will have a detrimental effect on rehabilitation is belied by the prior actions of the prison officials under the pre-Amendment policy. At that time, prison officials were authorized to prohibit sexually explicit materials that they believed would negatively affect the disci- pline or "good order" of the institution. Significantly, the prison officials--to whose expertise the Supreme Court has repeated deferred on matters such as this--did not choose to prohibit all material that is sexually explicit or that features nudity. Rather, they evaluated the publications individually to determine which ones, in their expert opinions, posed a potential threat and which did not; indeed, as the majority notes, "explicit heterosexual material" was ordinarily admit- ted. See Thornburgh, 490 U.S. at 405 n.6 (quoting Program Statement 5266.5(b)(2)). It was this "individualized nature" of the determinations that led the Thornburgh Court to conclude that the regulations at issue in that case were rationally related to security interests, the nature of which, like rehabilitation, can change over time.10 See Thornburgh, 490 U.S. at 417 ("We agree that it is rational for the Bureau to exclude materials that ... are determined by the warden to create an intolerable risk of disorder under the conditions of a particular prison at a particular time."). Because I believe that, on this record, there is no basis for concluding that there is a rational connection between the interest asserted by the government--rehabilitation--and the restriction chosen to further that interest--a ban on the delivery to all federal prisoners of all publications that are __________ 10 It should be noted in this respect that a seemingly innocuous publication may be quite detrimental to a prisoner's rehabilitation, depending on the circumstances. See, e.g., Waterman, 1998 WL 354932, at *3, *4 (citing concerns of prison officials that pictures of children from the Sears catalog should not be seen by pedophile prisoners). The need for individualistic determinations when behavior modifi- cation is at stake was also a concern in Washington v. Harper, 494 U.S. 210 (1990), in which the Court upheld a prison policy that permitted the involuntary administration of antipsychotic drugs to inmates, given that the policy was not unnecessarily broad and supported by a wealth of evidence: Its exclusive application is to inmates who are mentally ill and who, as a result of their illness, are gravely disabled or represent a significant danger to themselves or others. The drugs may be administered for no purpose other than treat- ment, and only under the direction of a licensed psychiatrist. There is considerable debate over the potential side effects of antipsychotic medications, but there is little dispute in the psychiatric profession that proper use of the drugs is one of the most effective means of treating and controlling a mental illness likely to cause violent behavior. Id. at 226. sexually explicit or that feature nudity, I would affirm the decision of the district court. As the majority considers the remaining Safley factors, however, I will also offer a few thoughts. The second Safley factor considers whether there are "al- ternative means of exercising the right that remain open to prison inmates." Safley, 482 U.S. at 90. Although this right must be viewed "sensibly and expansively," Thornburgh, 490 U.S. at 417, it cannot be viewed so broadly as to eliminate any reason for analysis (or as unhelpfully as the majority's sar- donic reference to an "entitlement to smut"). The Thorn- burgh Court, for example, noted that although the regulation under consideration in that case permitted the warden to make individualized determinations as to each publication, an exercise of discretion that might appear to produce inconsis- tent results, "greater consistency might be attainable only at the cost of a more broadly restrictive rule against admission of incoming publications," which "might itself run afoul of the second [Safley ] factor." Id. at 417 n.15. Because the Amendment eliminates a wide variety of publications that feature nudity for artistic or other reasons, prisoners do not have sufficient means of exercising their right to receive many constitutionally protected materials. Cf., e.g., Mauro, 1998 WL 550190, at *8 ("[I]n direct contradiction of the Supreme Court's cautionary language in Thornburgh, Marico- pa County has enacted a regulation that sweeps too broadly, indiscriminately eliminating large categories of materials without individualized consideration."). The third factor considers "the impact accommodation of the asserted constitutional right will have on guards and other inmates." Safley, 482 U.S. at 90. Where the institu- tional interest asserted for a publication ban is security, accommodation of the inmate's First Amendment rights may indeed cause the "ripple effect" of which the Safley Court warned, see id.; a breach of security with respect to one prisoner is likely to result in other breaches in the prison. In this case, however, there is no evidence by which to judge whether permitting certain inmates to view publications that are sexually explicit or that feature nudity will have an adverse effect on the rehabilitation of other inmates. Reha- bilitation is a gradual process, and it is entirely possible that any momentary lapses caused by the inadvertent receipt of an inappropriate publication may be reversed with additional rehabilitative efforts. This is not true of security breaches: Once an inmate has received information on how to escape from the prison, he cannot be made to forget it. It thus cannot be concluded, on this record, that accommodation of Amatel's First Amendment right will have a significant effect on the rehabilitation of other inmates. Finally, the fourth factor considers whether there are "obvious, easy alternatives" that "fully accommodate[ ] the prisoner's rights at de minimis cost to valid penological interests"; if so, this may be evidence that the regulation is an "exaggerated response" to prison concerns. Id. at 90-91. One such alternative comes immediately to mind: the pre- Amendment policy, under which wardens had discretion to examine each incoming publication and determine whether institutional interests favored its prohibition. The Court's approval of this policy in Thornburgh eliminates any concerns the majority might have that such a policy would be deemed arbitrary or particularly burdensome; indeed, since prison officials under the current policy must examine each publica- tion to determine whether it is sexually explicit or features nudity, the prior policy arguably represents no additional administrative burden. Moreover, other aspects of the Amendment suggest that it is indeed an "exaggerated response" to rehabilitative con- cerns. The Amendment does not allow the warden to take into account whether a prisoner is in a high- or low-security institution, whether a prisoner is male or female, what kinds of crimes the prisoner has committed,11 the nature of the __________ 11 For example, the government has provided no evidence on why a ban on nudity is necessary to rehabilitate those convicted of nonsexual and/or nonviolent crimes. I can think of no reason why an embezzler, a tax evader, or a person held in contempt for refusing to testify will be rehabilitated if prevented from looking at publications that "feature" nudity. (The statements of the only two prisoner's sentence,12 how long the prisoner has been incar- cerated and how long he or she has left to serve, whether the prisoner is receiving rehabilitative treatment,13 or even whether a prisoner is in a prison environment that provides an opportunity to share the material with anyone else (partic- ularly with other prisoners convicted of sex crimes). In these respects, the Amendment "sweeps much more broadly than can be explained by [the government's] penological objec- tives." Safley, 482 U.S. at 98 (invalidating ban on all prisoner marriages by noting that prison officials had experienced no problems with marriages by male inmates or with inmate- civilian marriages; the prison's rehabilitative concern "ap- pear[ed] from the record to have been centered almost exclu- sively on female inmates marrying other inmates or ex- __________ members of Congress who offered floor comments on the Amend- ment suggest that their concern was with sex offenders. See 142 Cong. Rec. H8262 (daily ed. July 24, 1996) ("[I]f we do not adopt my amendment, we are sending the message that it is OK to provide sexually explicit magazines and books to the very prisoners who have committed violent acts against women.") (statement of Rep. Ensign); id. ("Far too often, those individuals convicted of crimes have the opportunity, while in prison, to use materials that glamorize the very acts for which they were convicted.") (statement of Rep. Christensen).) Moreover, the Amendment's ban may also extend to those in- mates who have not yet been convicted but rather are imprisoned while awaiting trial. The government has not suggested any reason for it to take a rehabilitative interest in these individuals, nor do I think it can legitimately do so. See, e.g., McGinnis v. Royster, 410 U.S. 263, 273 (1973) ("[I]t would hardly be appropriate for the State to undertake in the pretrial detention period programs to rehabili- tate a man still clothed with a presumption of innocence."). 12 The government would seem to have less rehabilitative interest in, for example, prisoners who have been sentenced to life in prison without parole or to death. 13 In some prisons, material featuring adult nudity is an effective part of a rehabilitative program. See, e.g, Waterman, 1998 WL 354932, at *7 (citing evidence that adult pornography may be helpful in turning pedophiles away from child pornography). felons," id. at 99, and thus did not account for the ban on other inmate marriages). The majority's decision to remand this case for further consideration of Amatel's vagueness challenge leaves a scintil- la of hope that this ill-conceived statute will ultimately fail. Because I cannot agree with the majority's Safley analysis, however, or with its decision to lift the district court's injunc- tion in the interim, I respectfully dissent. Conclusion Justice Holmes once remarked that hard cases make bad law. See Northern Sec. Co. v. United States, 193 U.S. 197, 400 (1904) (Holmes, J., dissenting). Claims of prisoners to read magazines like Playboy or Penthouse may not be the ideal vehicles for the articulation of First Amendment rights. But, as Dostoyevsky observed, "the degree of civilization in a society is revealed by entering its prisons." F. Dostoyevsky, The House of the Dead 76 (C. Garnett trans., 1957). Today's ruling that prisoners may be stripped of rights to view publications of their choice on the mere assertion of legisla- tors or regulators--far removed from the prison scene and without supporting evidence of any kind--that those publica- tions will hinder their "rehabilitation" goes well beyond prior precedent and the case law in other circuits. It is a most troubling precedent.