We are of opinion that the judge did not err in refusing to give the first instruction which was prayed for by the counsel for the prisoner. It is not questioned but that the prisoner was entitled to the benefit of all those humane principles of the common law (82) which, in indulgence to the frailties of human nature, extenuate the guilt of homicide from murder to manslaughter. The great distinction between homicide committed with malice and homicide committed in a transport of passion suddenly excited by a grievous provocation, is as steadily to be kept in view in the trial of a slave charged with the murder of a white man as in that of a white man charged with the murder of his equal, or of a slave. But it cannot be conceded that the same matters which would be deemed in law a sufficient provocation to free a white man, who had committed a homicide in a moment of passion, from the guilt of murder will have the same effect when the party slain is a white man and the offender a slave. It has been authoritatively held that the killing of a slave by a white man may be reduced from murder to manslaughter by acts which, proceeding from a white man, would not in law constitute a sufficient provocation. Among equals, the general rule is that words are not, but blows are, a sufficient provocation; while in Tackett's case it was declared that there might be words of reproach *Page 68 so aggravating when uttered by a slave as to excite the temporary fury which negatives the charge of malice. S. v. Tackett, 8 N.C. 217, 218. This difference in the application of the same principle arises from thevast difference which exists, under our institutions, between the social condition of the white man and of the slave; in consequence of which difference what might be felt by one as the grossest degradation is considered by the other as but a slight injury. And from the same cause it must necessarily follow that some acts which between white persons are grievous provocations, when proceeding from a white person to a slave — whose passions are, or ought to be tamed down to his lowly condition — will not and cannot be so regarded. The degrees of homicide are indeed to be ascertained by common-law principles; but the principles themselves are necessarily, in their application, accommodated to the actual conditions of human beings in our society.
Nor do we apprehend that there was error in refusing to give the second instruction which was prayed for. It is the difference of condition between the white man and the slave, as recognized by our (83) legal institutions, and not the difference between personal merit and demerit, which creates a legal distinction between the sufficiency and insufficiency of the alleged provocation. This distinction, therefore, must be as broad as that difference, or it would not only be unsuited to the state of our society, and incompatible with the subordination of ranks essential to the safety of the state, but would be too vague to be admissible as a legal rule. It may be that the white man who debases himself by a familiar association with a slave, and, in the course of that association, is guilty of acts of meanness like that attributed, whether justly or unjustly, to the unfortunate deceased, has not claims to personal respect equal to those of the slave; but the distinction of castes yet remains, and with it remain all the passions, infirmities, and habits which grow out of this distinction.
With respect to the fourth instruction prayed for by the prisoner's counsel, we hold that the judge did err in refusing it, and instead thereof directing the jury, as we understand him to have directed, that the deceased had a right, because of the prisoner's insolence, to attack the latter with the knife and fence rail. In S. v. Hale, 9 N.C. 582, it was decided that the battery of a slave, by any other than his master, was perse a public offense; but at the same time it was declared that such a battery might be justified, if not excessive, by circumstances which would form no justification for the battery of a white man. It was not attempted to define those circumstances — nay, it was pronounced impossible to do so with precision. The nearest approach to a definition was that the circumstances must be of such a character as warranted *Page 69 the apparent breach of the public peace, "under the habits and feelings of society, securing at the same time the white from injury and insult and the slave from needless violence and outrage." Where we can find a rule established, it is our duty to adhere steadily to it. Wherever our predecessors have declared it impossible to draw the line, we dare not attempt it.
We feel ourselves, therefore, bound to say that insolence of a (84) slave does not justify an excessive battery; and we cannot hesitate to hold that an assault with a sharp-pointed knife, 3 inches long, and a piece of fence rail of the length of one's arm, is an attempt to commit an excessive battery, because these are not lawful instruments wherewith to check or to correct insolence. The language of his Honor, indeed, is "that if the prisoner used the provoking language testified by the witnesses, the deceased had a right to whip him"; but by the phrase "whip" he must necessarily be understood as meaning to whip in the manner testified by the witnesses. But if the language used were intended to convey only the idea of moderate chastisement, by an ordinary instrument of correction, the correctness of that instruction would depend materially upon the fact whether the insolence had been discontinued or was going on at the moment of correction. Upon this point the testimony seems to have been contradictory, or, at all events, was not free from doubt. One witness represented the reproachful language of the prisoner as continuing uninterrupted up to the moment of the conflict, while the other stated that it entirely ceased upon the finding of the piece of money. How the fact was it was the peculiar province of the jury to determine; and, in determining that fact, it might be very material to ascertain what was the motive of the prisoner's return, after he had been chased off by the deceased, and what the manner of his behavior when he so returned. If the insolence had been clearly discontinued, then the attack of the deceased upon the prisoner was for vengeance on account of past insolence, and not in order to stop continuing abuse. And, on this point, we are instructed by our predecessors that it is not necessary, in any case, that a person who hasreceived an injury, real or imaginary, from a slave, should carve out his own justice; for the law has made ample and summary provision for the punishment of all trivial offenses committed by slaves, by carrying them before a justice, who is authorized to pass sentence for their being publicly whipped. This provision, while it excludes the necessity of private vengeance, would seem to forbid its legality, since it effectually protects all persons from the insolence of slaves, even where their masters are unwilling to correct them upon complaint being made. S. v. Hale,9 N.C. 585. *Page 70
(85) If we could reconcile such a course to a sense of duty, we should forbear from examining the case any further. The prisoner was entitled to have the law applicable to his case correctly expounded to the jury. This, in our judgment, was not done; and, as the verdict may have been affected by that error, it is proper that he should have another trial. But it is impossible not to see that upon that trial the other questions which have been here argued must occur; and, therefore, so far as we have formed a decided judgment upon them, we cannot rightfully decline from now declaring it.
One of these is connected with the third instruction prayed for by the prisoner's counsel. If it be the meaning of that instruction that the case of the prisoner falls within the rule which obtains where parties become suddenly heated, and engage immediately in mortal conflict, fighting upon equal terms, and one killeth the other, we are obliged to say that the case of the prisoner is not within that rule. In mitigating the offense to manslaughter, where death ensues upon a sudden rencounter of this sort, the law shows its indulgence to that frailty of human nature which urges men, before they have an opportunity for reflection, to a compliance with those common notions of honor which forbid either to give way to or acknowledge the superior prowess of the other. Such notions spring from a sense of equality and the horror of personal disgrace. They do not prevail — they ought not to exist — between those who cannot combat with each other without degradation on the one hand and arrogance on the other. If that instruction is predicated upon the ground that the first assault, having been made by the deceased, constituted a provocation for the homicide committed by the latter, it then presents inquiries by no means free from embarrassment.
As yet a precise rule has not been laid down by which to pronounce what unlawful interference with the person of a slave by a white man shall be deemed a provocation sufficient to excite that transport of passion which, although a deadly weapon is used, may extenuate the killing of the assailant into manslaughter. And by whomsoever the (86) attempt to prescribe such a rule shall be made, he will find it no easy task to form a rule which shall consist with the principles of public policy on the one hand and with the just claims of humanity on the other. The superior rank of the assailant, the habits of humility and obedience which belong to the condition of the slave — habits which are not less indispensable to his own well-being than required by the inveterate usages of our people — clearly forbid that an ordinary assault or battery should be deemed, as it is between white men, a legal provocation. The law will not permit the slave to resist. It is his duty to submit, or flee, or seek the protection of his master; but it is impossible, *Page 71 if it were desirable, to extinguish in him the instinct of self-preservation; and although his passions ought to be tamed down so as to suit his condition, the law would be savage if it made no allowance for passion. He may have been disciplined into perfect obedience to the will of his master, and, therefore, habitually patient under his correction; but he cannot but feel a keen sense of wrong when authority is wantonly usurped over him by a stranger, and exercised with cruelty. There is therefore no difficulty in laying it down that a battery which endangers his life or great bodily harm, proceeding from one who has no authority over him, will amount to such a provocation. But between these extremes there are intermediate injuries of various grades. In regard to them, we are obliged to resort to the primary rule which pronounces on the character of provocations, and apply it according to the circumstances of each case. That is a legal provocation of which it can be pronounced, having due regard to the relative condition of the white man and the slave, and the obligation of the latter to conform his instinct and his passions to his condition of inferiority, that it would provoke well disposed slaves into a violent passion. And the application of the principle must be left, until a more precise rule can be formed, to the intelligence and conscience of the triers.
Two other points have been presented to our consideration, in the course of the argument, upon which it is proper to express our views. It has been correctly stated by the Attorney-General that although there should be a legal provocation, yet the homicide will be murder if committed under such circumstances of cruelty as manifest the (87) thoroughly wicked heart; and he has insisted that such circumstances of cruelty are manifested in the case before us. Cruelty, when the facts from which it is to be inferred all distinctly appear, is an inference of law, and, therefore, properly drawn by the court. But in this case the facts are not so set forth as to leave the question of cruelty one for legal inference. No more is stated than that several blows were struck with a stick of curled hickory of the ordinary size, and with the larger end thereof, without informing us more of the nature of those blows than that one of them was mortal. On the part of the prisoner it has been insisted, and properly insisted, that if the weapon used was not of the character called deadly, that is, likely to produce death or great bodily injury, the homicide would not be murder, although committed without legal provocation; and it has been argued that in this case the weapon was not of that character. No doubt there are many cases in which the court can distinctly see, from the nature of the instrument used, whether it be of a deadly character or not, and, therefore, need not that the jury should directly find the fact for their *Page 72 information. But this is not a case of that kind. It is one in which it falls peculiarly within the province of the jury to ascertain whether such a weapon, in such hands, and as it was used, was likely to produce fatal consequences or not.
PER CURIAM. Venire de novo.
Cited: S. v. Caesar, 31 N.C. 398, 408, 418; S. v. Curry, 46 N.C. 288;S. v. Medlin, 60 N.C. 491; S. v. Ellis, 101 N.C. 769; S. v.Robertson, 166 N.C. 363.
(88)