RECOMMENDED FOR FULL-TEXT PUBLICATION
Pursuant to Sixth Circuit I.O.P. 32.1(b)
File Name: 17a0174p.06
UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
BYRON LEWIS BLACK, ┐
Petitioner-Appellant, │
│
> No. 13-5224
v. │
│
│
WAYNE CARPENTER, Warden, │
Respondent-Appellee. │
┘
Appeal from the United States District Court
for the Middle District of Tennessee at Nashville.
No. 3:00-cv-00764—Todd J. Campbell, District Judge.
Argued: December 8, 2016
Decided and Filed: August 10, 2017
Before: COLE, Chief Judge; BOGGS and GRIFFIN, Circuit Judges.
_________________
COUNSEL
ARGUED: Kelley J. Henry, OFFICE OF THE FEDERAL PUBLIC DEFENDER, Nashville,
Tennessee, for Appellant. John H. Bledsoe, OFFICE OF THE TENNESSEE ATTORNEY
GENERAL, Nashville, Tennessee, for Appellee. ON BRIEF: Kelley J. Henry, OFFICE OF
THE FEDERAL PUBLIC DEFENDER, Nashville, Tennessee, for Appellant. Andrew H. Smith,
OFFICE OF THE TENNESSEE ATTORNEY GENERAL, Nashville, Tennessee, for Appellee.
BOGGS, J., delivered the opinion of the court in which GRIFFIN, J., joined, and COLE,
C.J., joined in part. COLE, C.J. (pg. 22), delivered a separate opinion concurring in the majority
opinion except for Section II.E and concurring in the judgment.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 2
_________________
OPINION
_________________
BOGGS, Circuit Judge. In 1986, Byron Black shot his girlfriend Angela’s ex-husband,
Bennie. Black pleaded guilty to malicious shooting and was sentenced to two years of
imprisonment at a Davidson County, Tennessee, workhouse. In 1988, while on a weekend
furlough from that workhouse, Black entered Angela’s home, shot Angela in the head as she
slept, and then shot nine-year-old Latoya and six-year-old Lakeisha (Angela’s children by
Bennie) once and twice, respectively, killing all three victims. Black returned to the workhouse
at the end of his furlough before law-enforcement officers discovered the bodies.
Black’s trial and post-conviction proceedings have spanned nearly thirty years.
Seventeen years have elapsed since Black filed the federal habeas petition presently before us.
The Supreme Court and the Tennessee courts have recently recognized limitations imposed by
the Eighth Amendment on the power of states to execute mentally retarded persons. But, for the
reasons that follow, these jurisprudential developments do not give Black a reprieve from his
sentence of death. We affirm the district court’s denial of post-conviction relief.
I
Black stood trial for the 1988 triple murder. A jury found Black guilty of murder and
burglary and sentenced him to death for one murder and life imprisonment for the other two
murders. The Tennessee Supreme Court affirmed on direct appeal. The Tennessee Court of
Criminal Appeals denied post-conviction relief, and the Tennessee Supreme Court denied further
post-conviction review. In 2000, Black filed a federal habeas petition in which he raised various
claims including a claim that his mental retardation precluded the imposition of the death
penalty. The petition was dismissed as meritless. Black v. Bell, 181 F. Supp. 2d 832, 883 (M.D.
Tenn. 2001). Black appealed to our court, but the Supreme Court shortly thereafter decided
Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 321 (2002) (holding that the Eighth Amendment prohibits states
from executing “mentally retarded criminals”), so we granted Black’s motion to hold his appeal
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 3
in abeyance while Black exhausted an Atkins claim in the Tennessee courts. Black v. Bell,
No. 02-5032 (6th Cir. July 26, 2002) (order).
The Tennessee trial court conducted an evidentiary hearing and denied Black’s Atkins
claim as meritless, the Tennessee Court of Criminal Appeals affirmed, and the Tennessee
Supreme Court denied further review. Black v. State, No. M2004-01345-CCA-R3-PD, 2005 WL
2662577 (Tenn. Crim. App. Oct. 19, 2005), perm. app. denied (Tenn. Feb. 21, 2006). Our court
then remanded Black’s appeal to the district court so that it could consider Black’s federal
habeas claim in light of Atkins. Black v. Bell, No. 02-5032 (6th Cir. May 30, 2007) (order). The
Supreme Court in Atkins had “le[ft] to the States the task of developing appropriate ways to
enforce” its prohibition on executing mentally retarded criminals. Atkins, 536 U.S. at 317. The
district court thus, quite understandably, looked to Tennessee law in analyzing Black’s Atkins
claim.
Tennessee had enacted a statute defining mental retardation as follows:
(1) Significantly subaverage general intellectual functioning as evidenced by a
functional intelligence quotient (I.Q.) of seventy (70) or below;
(2) Deficits in adaptive behavior; and
(3) The mental retardation must have been manifested during the
developmental period, or by eighteen (18) years of age.
Tenn. Code Ann. § 39-13-203(a) (2003).
The United States Supreme Court recently referred to a definition of mental retardation
substantially similar to this tripartite Tennessee definition as the “the generally accepted,
uncontroversial intellectual-disability diagnostic definition.” Moore v. Texas, 137 S. Ct. 1039,
1045 (2017).
For its part, the Tennessee Supreme Court held in 2004 that the first part of Tennessee’s
statutory definition of mental retardation imposed a “bright line rule” requiring an Atkins
petitioner to demonstrate an IQ of seventy or below. Howell v. State, 151 S.W.3d 450, 456–59
(Tenn. 2004) (agreeing with the State that § 39-13-203(a)(1) “should not be interpreted to make
allowance for any standard error of measurement or other circumstances whereby a person with
an I.Q. above seventy could be considered mentally retarded” (emphasis added)).
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 4
The district court considered Black’s IQ scores as follows:
IQ Scores Before Age 18
Date of Test Name of Test Score Black’s Approximate Age
1963 Lorge Thorndike 83 7
1964 Unknown 97 8
1966 Lorge Thorndike 92 10
1967 Otis 91 11
1969 Lorge Thorndike 83 13
IQ Scores After Age 18
Date of Test Name of Test Score Black’s Approximate Age
1989 Shipley-Hartford 76 33
1993 WAIS–R 73 37
1997 WAIS–R 76 41
2001 WAIS–III 69 45
2001 Stanford-Binet-IV 57 45
Black argued to the district court that the Tennessee courts’ denial of his Atkins claim
was improper in part because those courts “refused to consider standard errors in test
measurement [and] the ‘Flynn Effect,’1 permitted the State’s experts to testify, and placed the
burden of proof on the Petitioner.” Black v. Bell, No. 3:00-0764, 2008 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 33908,
at *15 (M.D. Tenn. Apr. 24, 2008). Black had argued in state court, and argued again to the
1
The Flynn Effect, named after intelligence expert James Flynn, is a “generally recognized phenomenon”
in which the average IQ scores produced by any given IQ test tend to rise over time, often by approximately three
points per ten years from the date the IQ test is initially standardized. See Ledford v. Head, No. 1:02-CV-1515-JEC,
2008 WL 754486, at *7 (N.D. Ga. Mar. 19, 2008); see also Am. Ass’n on Intellectual and Developmental
Disabilities, Intellectual Disability: Definition, Classification, and Systems of Supports 36–41 (11th ed. 2010).
The WAIS–III test, for example, was published in 1997. When the WAIS-III was designed, it was
administered to a “standardization sample” of 2,450 adults from the United States who were sorted into cohorts by
age and other characteristics. D. Wechsler, The Psychological Corp., WAIS–III Administration & Scoring Manual
(1997). IQ scores generated by the WAIS-III test essentially offer a measure of intelligence relative to the
standardization sample of 2,450 people, all of whom took the test in 1995. The Flynn Effect would thus predict that
average IQ scores generated by the WAIS–III in 2005 (ten years after it was normed) would be approximately three
points higher, on average, than those generated in 1995, and would predict that scores generated by the same test in
2015 would be approximately six points higher, on average, than those generated in 1995.
But there is no legal or scientific consensus that requires an across-the-board downward adjustment of IQ
scores to offset the Flynn Effect; rather, the Flynn Effect is one of many potential factors affecting the reliability and
validity of any individual IQ score, and a professional who is assessing an individual’s intelligence on the basis of
an IQ score would take the Flynn Effect and other factors into consideration as part of that assessment.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 5
district court, that his IQ scores should be reduced retroactively to account for both the standard
error of measurement (SEM) and the Flynn Effect.2
The district court noted that the Tennessee Court of Criminal Appeals, in rejecting
Black’s argument to adjust his IQ scores downward to account for the SEM or the Flynn Effect,
thoroughly considered the evidence provided by Black’s experts and the State’s experts. Black v.
Bell, 2008 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 33908, at *15–20. The district court itself was “not persuaded” by
Black’s arguments. Id. at *21. Applying Howell, which had also guided the decision of the
Tennessee Court of Criminal Appeals, the district court denied Black’s Atkins claim on the basis
that “the state court was not unreasonable in stating that the proof in the record did not support
the conclusion, under a preponderance of the evidence standard, that [Black’s] I.Q. was below
2
The SEM is distinct from the Flynn Effect. The SEM allows for the possibility that an IQ score either
overestimates or underestimates a subject’s true IQ. Contrary to common understanding, a SEM of “five points”
does not necessarily mean, for example, that a person with an IQ score of 75 must have a true IQ between 70 and 80.
Rather, the SEM represents the standard deviation of true IQ scores from reported IQ scores. See, e.g., Leo M.
Harvill, An NCME Module on Standard Error of Measurement, 10 Educ. Measurement: Issues & Prac. 33 (1991).
Thus, a SEM of five points means that a person with a reported IQ of 75 is approximately 68% likely to have a true
IQ within five points of 75 (i.e., between 70 and 80—one standard deviation on either side of 75), approximately
95% likely to have a true IQ within ten points (two standard deviations) of 75 (i.e., between 65 and 85), and
approximately 99.7% likely to have a true IQ within fifteen points (three standard deviations) of 75 (i.e., between 60
and 90). It is therefore a gross oversimplification to attempt to account for error in measurement by retroactively
reducing (or increasing) a reported IQ score by one SEM (or any number of SEMs).
Further, the SEM itself varies by test, subtest, and test-taker. The American Psychiatric Association states
in its Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders simply that “there is a measurement error of
approximately 5 points in assessing IQ.” Diagnostic & Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders 41–42 (4th ed., text
rev. 2000). But on the WAIS–III, for example, the SEM for an individual between the ages of 45 and 54, for the
full-scale IQ score (as opposed, for example, to a verbal-only or performance-only scale score) is reported as only
2.23 points. See Am. Ass’n on Mental Retardation, Mental Retardation: Definition, Classification & Systems of
Supports 51 (10th ed. 2002); see also Hall v. Florida, 134 S. Ct. 1986, 1995–96 (2014).
Thus, when experts acknowledge a SEM of “up to five points” on widely accepted IQ tests such as the
Wechsler (WISC and WAIS series) tests, and a SEM of “up to eight points” on “group-administered” tests like the
Lorge Thorndike, they are not saying that the maximum gap between reported score and true score is five (or eight)
points, respectively. Nor are they saying that, other than probabilistically, any given reported IQ score should be
viewed as being up to five (or eight) points higher or lower than the true IQ score. Rather, they are saying that the
maximum standard deviation between reported score and true score is five (or eight) points—meaning there is at
least a 68% likelihood that the individual’s true score is within five (or eight) points of the reported score.
It is worth noting that “group-administered” tests like the Lorge Thorndike are not really “group tests” in
the conventional sense: that is, the questions are not answered orally by groups of individuals. Rather, these tests
are administered (much like the SAT or the LSAT) to individuals who each complete an individual written IQ test
but may do so at the same time as others in a classroom-style setting under the guidance of a single administrator,
instead of in a one-on-one setting as Wechsler-series tests (like the WAIS) are administered.
In short, SEM is complicated—and there is no authority that requires any adjustment, let alone a downward
adjustment (when the true IQ score might just as well be higher than the reported score) to account for the SEM
when analyzing IQ scores as part of an Atkins determination.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 6
seventy before age 18.” Id. at *28–29. Nevertheless, the district court issued a certificate of
appealability, and Black again appealed to our court.
In 2011, however, before we issued an opinion on that appeal, the Tennessee Supreme
Court changed course and overruled Howell, holding that Tenn. Code Ann. § 39-13-203(a)(1)
“does not require that raw scores on I.Q. tests be accepted at their face value and that the courts
may consider competent expert testimony showing that a test score does not accurately reflect a
person’s functional I.Q. or that the raw3 I.Q. test score is artificially inflated or deflated.”
Coleman v. State, 341 S.W.3d 221, 224 (Tenn. 2011) (emphases added).
In light of Coleman, over a dissent, we again remanded Black’s Atkins claim to the
district court. Black v. Bell, 664 F.3d 81, 84 (6th Cir. 2011). Even though the Tennessee Court
of Criminal Appeals could not have known, at the time it denied Black’s state habeas relief, that
the Tennessee Supreme Court would replace Howell with its opinion in Coleman, we held that
the Tennessee Court of Criminal Appeals’ decision was “contrary to the latest Tennessee
Supreme Court’s decision on this subject.” Id. at 96. And because Atkins allowed states to
define the contours of Atkins itself (such that Atkins incorporated Coleman, so to speak, for
purposes of Black’s claim), we held that the Tennessee Court of Criminal Appeals’ decision was
“contrary to clearly established” federal “law under [the Antiterrorism and Effective Death
Penalty Act (AEDPA)].” Id. at 100–01. Thus, because no court had yet evaluated Black’s
Atkins claim under Coleman, we remanded Black’s Atkins claim for the district court to analyze
it “according to the proper legal standard, which was set out by the Tennessee Supreme Court in
Coleman.” Id. at 101. The district court denied Black’s claim, and for the reasons that follow,
we affirm.
II
On remand, the district court conducted a de novo review of Black’s Atkins claim.
The court accepted new briefing from Black and from the State. Black moved for an evidentiary
hearing, and the court denied Black’s motion on the ground that our remand was a limited
3
The Coleman court discussed “the validity and weight of raw scores of intelligence tests.” Coleman,
341 S.W.3d at 242 (emphasis added). The court was not referring to actual raw scores but rather to reported full-
scale IQ scores unadjusted for Flynn Effect, SEM, or other factors.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 7
remand directing the district court to review the record only, placing an evidentiary hearing
“beyond the scope of the remand.” R.150. Nevertheless, on January 3, 2013, the district court
held oral argument on the merits of Black’s Atkins claim, and the district court subsequently
issued a 31-page opinion evaluating the record, analyzing the evidence provided by Black’s
experts and the State’s experts, and concluding that Black had not “met his burden of proving
intellectual disability by a preponderance of the evidence.” Black v. Colson, No. 3:00-0764,
2013 WL 230664, at *19 (M.D. Tenn. Jan. 22, 2013) (emphasis added).
On appeal, Black contends that the district court erred in perceiving our remand to be a
limited remand; erred in denying Black an evidentiary hearing; erred in failing to apply a
summary-judgment standard in ruling on Black’s Atkins claim; and erred in its merits
determination that Black had not met his burden of establishing entitlement to Atkins relief. We
address each issue in turn.
A. Our Remand Was a Limited Remand
We review the interpretation of our own mandate de novo. United States v. Parks,
700 F.3d 775, 777 (6th Cir. 2012). Under the mandate rule, a district court is bound by the
scope of the remand issued by our court. Mason v. Mitchell, 729 F.3d 545, 550 (6th Cir.
2013); Scott v. Churchill, 377 F.3d 565, 570 (6th Cir. 2004). In concluding that we had
issued a limited remand, the district court relied on this language from our prior opinion:
A complete review must apply the correct legal standard to all of the relevant
evidence in the record. We therefore VACATE the district court’s denial of
Black’s Atkins claim and REMAND the case for it to review the record based on
the standard set out in Coleman and consistent with this opinion.
Black v. Bell, 664 F.3d at 101.
We agree that our remand was limited: the scope of the remand, as expressly stated in
this quoted language, was a review of the record under Coleman.
Black contends that the district court “erroneously restricted its review to the state court
record alone.” Appellant’s Br. 5. When AEDPA deference applies to an Atkins claim, the
district court would indeed be limited to reviewing the record that was before the state courts.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 8
Cullen v. Pinholster, 563 U.S. 170, 180–81 (2011). Here, however, because Black was entitled
to a de novo review of his Atkins claim without AEDPA deference, the district court was free to
consider the full record before it, including materials that were made part of the federal habeas
record after the close of state habeas proceedings. Black argues that the district court “believed
that it lacked authority . . . to consider record evidence presented in federal court.” Appellant’s
Br. 7. But the record does not support Black’s argument: the district court, to be sure, stated that
it was undertaking “a de novo review of the evidence admitted at the post conviction proceeding
in state court,” Black v. Colson, 2013 WL 230664, at *6, and that it “fully considered the
evidence in the state court record,” id. at *19, but nowhere in its memorandum opinion did the
district court state that it was considering only the state-court record, or that it was declining to
consider (or otherwise excluding) any of the exhibits that Black had provided to the district court
in the course of the federal habeas proceedings.
At oral argument before our court, Black’s counsel stressed that the district court erred by
failing to consider certain exhibits, namely the declaration of Dr. Marc J. Tassé, R.120-1, and the
declaration of Dr. Stephen Greenspan, R.120-2. But nothing in the record indicates that the
district court didn’t consider these exhibits—which were made part of the federal habeas record
in 2008—when it issued its opinion in 2013. Indeed, at the oral argument before the district
court in January 2013, Black’s counsel brought both declarations to the attention of the district
court, including record citations to each, and the district court in no way indicated that it would
decline to examine those items. R.160 at 22 (“I would be remiss to not point out another
objective measure of Mr. Black’s adaptive functioning in affidavit of Dr. Ste[ph]en Greenspan.
And that’s at Docket Entry 120-2.”); id. at 60 (“The Court: Is that what you called the screening
test? Ms. Henry: Yes, sir. And you will see in Docket Entry 120-1, there is testimony there
from Dr. Mar[c] Tass[é], who is the nation’s leading expert on assessing intelligence.”).
We therefore hold that the district court did not err in apprehending the scope of its
remand. The district court understood that its task was to conduct a de novo review of the record
before it—including, at a minimum, a de novo review of the state-court record applying Coleman
in the same way that the Tennessee Supreme Court would have done if the Atkins claim were
instead before that court. And while the district court was not prohibited under Pinholster from
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 9
considering additional evidence beyond the state-court record (because the district court was not
subject to AEDPA’s constraints), it was not error for the district court not to state whether and to
what extent it was considering materials such as Dr. Tassé’s and Dr. Greenspan’s declarations
that were part of the federal habeas record only. Indeed, as noted above, when the district court
heard oral argument, it did—without cavil—engage with aspects of the declarations of both Dr.
Tassé and Dr. Greenspan.
B. The District Court Did Not Abuse Its Discretion in Denying an Evidentiary Hearing
Relatedly, Black argues that the district court erred in denying him an evidentiary
hearing. We review the district court’s denial of an evidentiary hearing for abuse of discretion.
Cornwell v. Bradshaw, 559 F.3d 398, 410 (6th Cir. 2009); Getsy v. Mitchell, 495 F.3d 295, 310
(6th Cir. 2007) (en banc). The fact that Black was “not disqualified from receiving an
evidentiary hearing under [AEDPA] does not entitle him to one.” Bowling v. Parker, 344 F.3d
487, 512 (6th Cir. 2003). Rather, when a court is able to resolve a habeas claim on the record
before it, it may do so without holding an evidentiary hearing. See Sawyer v. Hofbauer, 299 F.3d
605, 612 (6th Cir. 2002).
Here, the district court did not abuse its discretion in denying Black’s motion for an
evidentiary hearing. Notably, even if we had authorized the district court to entertain new
evidence in evaluating Black’s Atkins claim, Black has not identified any evidence that he would
introduce other than exhibits already made part of the state or federal habeas record. And while
Black has cited authorities that support allowing an evidentiary hearing, Appellant’s Br. 11, 15–
16, 26, Black fails to support the contention that an evidentiary hearing was required in order for
the district court properly to evaluate the voluminous record before it under Coleman. At oral
argument, Black’s counsel argued that an evidentiary hearing would have provided Black an
opportunity to direct the court’s attention to the findings and conclusions, for example, of post-
conviction expert Dr. Tassé. But, as we have stated, Black was able to bring Dr. Tassé’s
declaration to the district court’s attention at the oral argument before that court, and, in any
event, the district court’s task was to review the record in the same way the Tennessee Supreme
Court would have reviewed it under Coleman—and the district court’s thorough 31-page opinion
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 10
reflects that it was able to do that within the scope of our limited remand and without conducting
an evidentiary hearing.
C. Principles of Summary Judgment
Do Not Apply to a Merits Ruling on a Federal Habeas Claim
Black’s brief on appeal makes various assertions that the district court should have
applied a summary-judgment standard in conducting its review, but Black cites no authority for
this supposed rule—a rule that would mean, it is worth noting, that Black would prevail so long
as any reasonable juror would grant him relief, giving Black the benefit of all reasonable factual
inferences. Appellant’s Br. 5 (“On remand, Black’s request for an evidentiary hearing was
denied. The district court erroneously . . . resolved factual disputes in favor of Respondent.”); id.
8 (“The district court compounded its error by failing to follow well-settled principles of
summary judgment in its memorandum opinion. The district court credited the testimony of the
State’s witnesses in the face of the expert opinions of Black’s witnesses. The district court
refused to draw inferences in favor of Black. Rather, it did just the opposite.”); id. 28–29
(apparently treating the Atkins proceeding as a summary-judgment proceeding at which Fed. R.
Civ. P. 56 governs because it was “a summary proceeding” without an evidentiary hearing).
Summary-judgment procedures simply do not apply to a federal habeas court’s final
adjudication of an Atkins claim. Rather, it is Black who had the burden of proving, by a
preponderance of the evidence, that he was entitled to relief. See Parke v. Raley, 506 U.S. 20, 34
(1992) (discussing “the preponderance of the evidence standard applicable to constitutional
claims raised on federal habeas”); Tenn. Code Ann. § 39-12-203(c) (“The burden of production
and persuasion to demonstrate intellectual disability by a preponderance of the evidence is on the
defendant.”). Part of the confusion in Black’s briefing appears to arise from the fact that the
State had filed a “Motion to Dismiss and for Summary Judgment” in the pre-Coleman federal
habeas proceedings—and indeed, when Black originally filed his petition in 2002, before Atkins
was decided, the district court granted “summary judgment” to the State on Black’s claims.
But the district court’s decision that Black now appeals was not summary judgment—it
was judgment. Indeed, nothing in the 2011-13 habeas proceedings leading up to the district
court’s January 2013 memorandum opinion was styled “summary judgment” at all: the State
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 11
filed a “Brief Opposing [Black’s] Atkins Claim,” and Black filed a “Brief In Support Of His
Atkins Claim,” but nothing in the record appears to justify (and Black does not direct us to
anything in the record that would justify) Black’s contention that the district court’s oral
argument and opinion constituted a summary-judgment proceeding. Nor is there any support for
the proposition that the district court’s Atkins determination was transformed into a summary-
judgment ruling because the district court declined to hold an evidentiary hearing, as Black’s
brief seems to imply. Appellant’s Br. 5. The district court’s Atkins determination was a final
judgment on the merits of Black’s Atkins claim, in which the district court properly weighed the
evidence, made credibility determinations, and declared one party the victor.
At such a proceeding, under Atkins (as it incorporates state law), Black had to prove
every element of his mental-retardation claim “by a preponderance of the evidence,” without
receiving the benefit of having any inferences drawn in his favor. Tenn. Code Ann. § 39-12-
203(c); see Coleman, 341 S.W.3d at 233 (“The statute places the burden on the criminal
defendant to prove by a preponderance of the evidence that he or she had an intellectual
disability at the time of the offense and requires the trial court rather than the jury to make the
decision.”).
We therefore hold that the district court did not err when it resolved the factual disputes
before it rather than employing a summary-judgment standard.
D. The District Court’s Merits Ruling Was Correct
We review the district court’s denial of habeas relief de novo. Bigelow v. Williams,
367 F.3d 562, 569 (6th Cir. 2004). But we review underlying factual findings for clear error, and
we bear in mind that, contrary to the assertions in Black’s brief, Black carries the burden of
persuasion:
Our review of the district court’s factual findings is highly deferential. We start
from the premise that a district court’s factual findings in a habeas proceeding are
reviewed for clear error. Lucas v. O’Dea, 179 F.3d 412, 416 (6th Cir. 1999).
“‘Clear error’ occurs only when [the panel is] left with the definite and firm
conviction that a mistake has been committed. If there are two permissible views
of the evidence, the factfinder’s choice between them cannot be clearly
erroneous.” United States v. Kellams, 26 F.3d 646, 648 (6th Cir. 1994). We are
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 12
also mindful that in a habeas proceeding the petitioner “has the burden of
establishing his right to federal habeas relief and of proving all facts necessary to
show a constitutional violation.” Romine v. Head, 253 F.3d 1349, 1357 (11th Cir.
2001).
Caver v. Straub, 349 F.3d 340, 351 (6th Cir. 2003).
The Supreme Court “le[ft] to the States the task of developing appropriate ways to
enforce” its decision in Atkins, 536 U.S. at 317, but the Court has invalidated state procedures for
evaluating Atkins claims when those procedures are “[n]ot aligned with the medical community’s
information,” Moore, 137 S. Ct. at 1044 (2017) (invalidating Texas scheme where “indicators of
intellectual disability [were] an invention of the [Texas Court of Criminal Appeals] untied to any
acknowledged source”), and thereby “creat[e] an unacceptable risk that persons with intellectual
disability will be executed.” Ibid. (quoting Hall, 134 S. Ct. at 1990; see also id. at 1992
(invalidating Florida scheme that foreclosed “all further exploration of intellectual disability”
where prisoner’s seven IQ scores in the evidentiary record were all above 70 (ranging from 71 to
80) and two IQ scores that had been excluded from the record were under 70)).
To prevail on his Atkins claim under Coleman, Black would need to “prove by a
preponderance of the evidence”:
(1) Significantly subaverage general intellectual functioning as evidenced by a
functional intelligence quotient (I.Q.) of seventy (70) or below;
(2) Deficits in adaptive behavior; and
(3) The intellectual disability must have been manifested during the
developmental period, or by eighteen (18) years of age.
Coleman, 341 S.W.3d at 233 (quoting Tenn. Code Ann. § 39-13-203(a) (2010)).4
4
The only difference between this statute and the 2003 version quoted in Part I, supra, is that the term
“intellectual disability” replaced the term “mental retardation” in the 2010 version of the statute. In 2014, the
Supreme Court in Hall used the term “intellectual disability” and acknowledged that previous opinions of the Court
had used the term “mental retardation” to describe the same phenomenon. Hall, 134 S. Ct. at 1990. But the next
year, in Brumfield v. Cain, 135 S. Ct. 2269, 2277, 2291 (2015), the Court used both terms in the same decision.
Because the vast majority of Black’s legal proceedings transpired before the term “mental retardation” began to fall
out of favor, and because Atkins itself used “mental retardation,” we have also used that term throughout this
opinion, but we use “intellectual disability” in this section because it is the predominant term used by Coleman.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 13
Black argues that the district court wrongly concluded that he did not have significantly
subaverage general intellectual functioning as evidenced by a functional IQ score of seventy or
lower before he turned eighteen. The district court’s conclusion largely rested on its analysis of
the series of IQ tests that Black has taken over the course of his life, see Black v. Colson, 2013
WL 230664, at *6–7, and the crux of Black’s argument is that the court wrongly analyzed those
IQ scores.
As set forth in Part I, supra, Black’s school records reveal IQ scores ranging from 83 to
97 when Black was age seven to thirteen. After those tests, the next IQ test on record was
administered to Black in 1989 (at age 33) before he stood trial for the triple murder: he scored
76. During Black’s first post-conviction proceeding in state court, he was twice administered the
WAIS–R (once in 1993 at age 37, once in 1997 at age 41) and scored 73 and 76, respectively.
And during federal habeas proceedings (after his death sentence had been upheld by the
Tennessee courts), Black scored 69 on the WAIS–III and 57 on the Stanford-Binet-IV, both
administered in 2001 when Black was 45.
The district court relied strongly on the IQ testing done during Black’s school-age years
as most probative of Black’s mental condition prior to age eighteen. Id. at *10. Not
surprisingly, Black maintains that this reliance is misplaced. First, Black argues that these test
scores are invalid because the tests were “group-administered.”5 In the state post-conviction
proceedings, Dr. Daniel H. Grant, a neuropsychologist and forensic psychologist, testified that
the appropriate mental-health testing models establish that group-administered tests are
unreliable and should not be used to determine intellectual disability. Dr. Greenspan’s
declaration avers that group-administered tests are not acceptable for intellectual-disability
determinations because they have much weaker reliability and validity and there is a lack of
information about the circumstances under which the tests were administered. And Dr. Tassé’s
declaration avers that group-administered tests “are not well normed nor possess the
psychometric properties necessary to be used in diagnostic decision-making.” Dr. Tassé states
that these tests “serve a screening purpose” but that he would not rely upon results from these
5
As noted in Part I, supra, “group-administered” tests are written tests completed by individuals on their
own; they are simply administered in a classroom setting as is the case with the SAT or other paper-based
standardized tests.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 14
tests “when making or refuting a diagnosis of mental retardation.” Of course, these declarations
do not, without more, provide much help for Black: even if Black had persuaded the district
court to reject his childhood IQ scores as useful for “making or refuting a diagnosis of mental
retardation,” he would still have fallen short of carrying his burden to prove that he was
intellectually disabled by age eighteen.
Moreover, a state expert and psychologist, Dr. Eric Engum, testified during state post-
conviction proceedings that group-administered tests are relevant when considering whether an
individual is intellectually disabled. While agreeing with Dr. Grant that these tests are not as
accurate as individually administered tests, Dr. Engum believes that they are properly used as
indicators of how well a child is functioning; if the test raised a concern about a child’s
intellectual capacity, the child would have been referred for more testing. Although the SEM for
group-administered tests is higher (up to eight points) than the SEM for individually
administered tests (up to five points),6 Black was not referred for more testing (and indeed, Black
graduated high school with a standard diploma), and all his childhood test scores would still be
well above the numerical threshold for intellectual disability even if they were retroactively
adjusted downward by one SEM.
Black next argues that even his adulthood IQ tests administered between 1989 and 1997,
the scores from which fall in the low-to-mid 70s, overstate his level of intellectual functioning
and that his results should be construed as below 70 when adjusted for the Flynn Effect. At oral
argument, Black’s counsel argued that the Supreme Court’s decision in Brumfield v. Cain, 135 S.
Ct. 2269 (2015), “require[s]” us to look at the “Flynn-adjusted scores” as reported in Dr. Tassé’s
report. R.120-2; Oral Argument 25:10-26:00 (discussing Brumfield and Hall). But neither
Brumfield nor Hall imposes any such requirement—indeed, neither case even mentions the
Flynn Effect.
What they do mention is the SEM. Brumfield, 135 S. Ct. at 2278 (rejecting the argument
“that Brumfield’s reported IQ score of 75 somehow demonstrated that he could not possess
subaverage intelligence,” where Louisiana law categorically prohibited consideration of factors
6
See n.2, supra.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 15
such as the SEM when a defendant’s reported IQ score was above 70); Hall, 134 S. Ct. at 1995–
96 (“For purposes of most IQ tests, the SEM means that an individual’s score is best understood
as a range of scores on either side of the recorded score.”). But as noted above, the SEM
accounts for the possibility that an individual’s true IQ score is either higher or lower than the
reported score. And while the Supreme Court has rejected rigid rules that prevent a court from
considering evidence of the SEM altogether, see, e.g., id. at 1999–2001, the Court’s decisions in
no way require a reviewing court to make a downward variation based on the SEM in every IQ
score, let alone to do the same with the Flynn Effect.
Further, while the Tennessee Supreme Court in Coleman held that “an expert should be
permitted to base his or her assessment of the defendant’s ‘functional intelligence quotient’ on a
consideration of” “a particular test’s standard error of measurement, the Flynn Effect, the
practice effect, or other factors affecting the accuracy, reliability, or fairness of the instrument or
instruments used to assess or measure the defendant’s I.Q.,” Coleman only requires a downward
adjustment to counteract the Flynn Effect when the IQ test administered to a given individual is
an “older version” than the then-current version of the test on the market. Coleman, 341 S.W.3d
at 242 n.55. Black has not raised any argument that any of his specific IQ scores is required to
be corrected for the Flynn Effect under Coleman because an earlier-normed version of the test
was administered.
Rather, Black’s argument is that we should retroactively lower his IQ scores because his
experts say that we should. Black submitted evidence from various experts about the impact of
the Flynn Effect. Dr. Grant testified, for instance (in the state post-conviction hearing), that the
Flynn Effect should result in a four-point reduction in his IQ score from the 1993 testing,
lowering the score from 73 to 69. Dr. Grant also said that the Flynn Effect should lower the
1997 score by five points from 76 to 71. Dr. Grant also opined that the WAIS–III, administered
in 2001, which produced a score of 69, was a more accurate instrument than the WAIS–R and
thus produced more accurate results. Dr. Greenspan’s declaration avers that the Flynn Effect
would reduce the 1993 test by four points to 69 and the 1997 test by six points to 70.
Dr. Greenspan also agreed that the 2001 test (with a score of 69) used a more current instrument
than previous assessments had. Similarly, Dr. Tassé opined that the Flynn Effect would reduce
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 16
Black’s 1993 results by four points to 69 and his 1997 results by five points to 71. Dr. Tassé
further maintained that the 2001 WAIS–III results should be lowered to a score of 67 due to the
Flynn Effect.
On the other hand, the State presented testimony that the impact of the Flynn Effect was
overstated by Black’s experts. While Dr. Engum was aware of the Flynn Effect and the need to
revise and restandardize IQ tests, he questioned the appropriateness of relying on the Flynn
Effect to lower IQ scores retroactively based on the passage of time. Dr. Susan Vaught, a
neuropsychologist, testified that it was not standard practice to correct scores due to the Flynn
Effect nor was it routinely considered by practitioners as a basis for lowering an IQ score. Upon
consideration of the parties’ evidence (including specific mention of Dr. Grant’s, Dr. Engum’s,
and Dr. Vaught’s testimony), the district court concluded that the Flynn Effect provided “weak
support for the statutory requirement that [Black] have scores at or below 70 before he turned
age 18.” Black v. Colson, 2013 WL 230664, at *10. The court accepted the existence of the
Flynn Effect but concluded that the 1993 and 1997 tests were not as probative of Flynn’s mental
ability before age eighteen as the earlier tests, and declined to accept Black’s argument that
retroactively reducing IQ scores was a “scientifically valid remedy” to account for the Flynn
Effect. Ibid.
Black further argues that the district court should have credited the 2001 IQ tests that
placed Black’s IQ score at 57 and 69. The district court noted, however, that Black was 45 years
old when these tests were administered (and, incidentally, Black was 45 years old before he was
ever “diagnosed as having mental retardation,” id. at *13). The 2001 IQ scores were also
generated after Black had been under a sentence of death for more than a decade. Unlike in a
competency hearing under Ford v. Wainwright, 477 U.S. 399 (1986), where these scores might
be probative of a prisoner’s insanity at the time of execution, these recent scores have far less
probative value, if any, in showing Black’s mental capacity before he turned eighteen. Black has
argued that his mental retardation at age 45 was (unless rebutted by the State) evidence of
lifelong mental retardation sufficient to satisfy the requirement that mental retardation manifest
itself before age 18; indeed, Black presented expert witnesses’ findings that Black had a brain
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 17
disorder, perhaps caused by fetal alcohol spectrum disorder, but the district court found those
experts were “not persuasive.” Id. at *14.
Specifically, Dr. Albert Globus, a neuropsychiatrist, examined Black and conducted an
extensive review of his past medical records and social history. While he did not conduct any
IQ testing, Dr. Globus reviewed recent positron emission tomography (PET) scans of Black’s
brain, which revealed “definite abnormalities,” including “changes in the cerebral cortex, the
brain ventricles, and the white matter indicating organic damage to the structure of the brain.”
Dr. Globus also observed “[h]ypometabolism of glucose in the orbito-frontal cortex, the medial
and polar temporal cortex, and the caudate and/or the putamen.” Based on Black’s life history,
Dr. Globus opined that Black had an organic brain disorder with an onset well before his current
offense. Dr. Globus concluded that these findings were “ consistent” with Black’s having an
IQ of 70 or lower, which rendered him intellectually disabled—but while Dr. Globus stated that
“evidence of early onset brain damage secondary to alcohol ingestion by [Black’s] mother” was
“sufficient to produce an IQ lower than all but two or three per cent of the population,”
Dr. Globus’s evaluation of Black’s mental ability centered around Black’s current ability (in
2001, when Dr. Globus wrote his report). Dr. Globus did not affirmatively state that Black’s IQ
was 70 or lower before age eighteen.
The district court made several specific page citations to Dr. Globus’s testimony. See,
e.g., id. at *11. But the district court did not assign great weight to Dr. Globus’s findings
because Dr. Globus had not substantiated the facts concerning alcohol use by Black’s mother
that Dr. Globus relied upon in his report, and because Dr. Globus admitted that the brain scans
that he analyzed did not actually reveal whether Black’s brain abnormalities were caused by fetal
alcohol spectrum disorder or instead by an adulthood injury. Ibid.
Dr. Ruben Gur, a neuropsychologist, also concluded that Black suffered from a brain
disorder. Dr. Gur noted damage in Black’s frontal- and temporal-lobe functions and commented
that Black’s “deficits are particularly pronounced in executive functions, memory and emotion
processing.” Dr. Gur opined that these limitations potentially resulted from certain exposures
during Black’s childhood. These exposures may have included his mother’s alcohol
consumption while pregnant with him, or lead poisoning arising from his childhood living
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 18
conditions. Black also suffered several head injuries while playing football, although no formal
diagnosis of concussion was ever made. At the time of Dr. Gur’s report, Dr. Gur noted that
Black demonstrated symptoms associated with serious psychiatric disorders, including paranoid
and delusional beliefs—but these disorders are not necessarily concomitants of mental
retardation.
The district court thoroughly evaluated all these reports, and the district court elected to
disregard this most recent evidence of Black’s mental ability because the district court was not
persuaded that any injury that might have caused mental retardation had occurred before Black
turned eighteen. Id. at *14.
In short, Black’s argument requires three steps: (1) reject Black’s childhood “group-
administered” IQ scores (83, 97, 92, 91, 83); (2) either rely exclusively on the 2001 IQ scores
(69, 57), or else apply a downward adjustment to the pre-2001 adulthood IQ scores (76, 73, 76)
to account for the Flynn Effect and the SEM, so as to reduce those scores to below 70; and
(3) presume that the adulthood scores, in the absence of contradictory childhood IQ scores (and
by disregarding evidence put on by the State to rebut Black’s contention that his mother’s
alcohol consumption caused Black to suffer any brain damage that caused any level of mental
retardation), are evidence of lifelong mental retardation that must have manifested itself before
age eighteen. Each of these three steps is a necessary condition for Black to prevail on his Atkins
claim as we see it. And Black has not shown us any authority that would support taking any of
these steps.
At the end of the day, without stronger evidence that Black’s childhood IQ scores did
not accurately reflect his intellectual functioning before he turned eighteen, the district court
held that Black could not carry his burden of showing, by a preponderance of the evidence, that
he had significantly subaverage general intellectual functioning before he turned eighteen.
Having reviewed the entire record, we cannot find fault with the district court’s
conclusion; after all, even if Black’s childhood IQ scores were reduced by both eight points to
account for the SEM (using the higher SEM applicable to group-administered tests, rather than
five points for individually administered tests) and up to four points to counteract the Flynn
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 19
Effect,7 they all would still exceed seventy. To be sure, there is almost always a possibility that a
reported IQ score significantly higher than 70 is an inaccurate reflection of a true IQ score of 70
or below—indeed, there is approximately a one-in-300 chance that a reported IQ of 92 on a
group-administered test (like Black’s 1966 Lorge Thorndike score) reflects a true score lower
than 70. But that possibility does not satisfy Black’s burden to prove his intellectual disability
by a preponderance of the evidence.
E. Implications of the Flynn Effect
There is good reason to have pause before retroactively adjusting IQ scores downward to
offset the Flynn Effect. As we noted above, see n.1, supra, the Flynn Effect describes the
apparent rise in IQ scores generated by a given IQ test as time elapses from the date of that
specific test’s standardization. The reported increase is an average of approximately three points
per decade, meaning that for an IQ test normed in 1995, an individual who took that test in 1995
and scored 100 would be expected to score 103 on that same test if taken in 2005, and would be
expected to score 106 on that same test in 2015. This does not imply that the individual is
“gaining intelligence”: after all, if the same individual, in 2015, took an IQ test that was normed
in 2015, we would expect him to score 100, and we would consider him to be of the same
“average” intelligence that he demonstrated when he scored 100 on the 1995-normed test in
1995. Rather, the Flynn Effect implies that the longer a test has been on the market after initially
being normed, the higher (on average) an individual should perform, as compared with how that
individual would perform on a more recently normed IQ test.
At first glance, of course, the Flynn Effect is troubling: if scoring 70 on an IQ test in 1995
would have been sufficient to avoid execution, then why shouldn’t a score of 76 on that same test
administered in 2015 (which would produce a “Flynn-adjusted” score of 70) likewise suffice to
avoid execution? Further, even if IQ tests were routinely restandardized every year or two to
reset the mean score to 100, and even if old IQ tests were taken off the market so as to avoid the
Flynn Effect “inflation” of scores that is visible when an IQ test continues to be administered
7
Of Black’s five childhood IQ scores, the 1969 Lorge Thorndike test is the most susceptible to Flynn Effect
inflation. The Lorge Thorndike test was published in 1957, so a reduction of the 1969 score by approximately four
points would offset the maximum expected inflation of that score that would be attributable to the Flynn Effect.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 20
long after its initial standardization, that would only mask, but not change, the fact that IQ scores
are said to be rising.
Indeed, perhaps the most puzzling aspect of the Flynn Effect is that it is true. As Dr.
Tassé states in his declaration, “[t]he so-called ‘Flynn Effect’ is NOT a theory. It is a well-
established scientific fact that the US population is gaining an average of 3 full-scale IQ points
per decade.” The implications of the Flynn Effect over a longer period of time are jarring:
consider a cohort of individuals who, in 1917, took an IQ test that was normed in 1917 and
received “normal” scores (say, 100, on average). If we could transport that same cohort of
individuals to the present day, we would expect their average score today on an IQ test normed
in 2017—a century later—to be thirty points lower: 70, making them mentally retarded, on
average.
Alternatively, consider a cohort of individuals who, in 2017, took an IQ test that was
normed in 2017 and received “normal” scores (of 100, on average). If we could transport that
same cohort of individuals to a century ago, we would expect that their average score on a test
normed in 1917 would be thirty points higher: 130, making them geniuses, on average.
It thus makes little sense to use Flynn-adjusted IQ scores to determine whether a criminal
is sufficiently intellectually disabled to be exempt from the death penalty. After all, if Atkins
stands for the proposition that someone with an IQ score of 70 or lower in 2002 (when Atkins
was decided) is exempt from the death penalty, then the use of Flynn-adjusted IQ scores would
conceivably lead to the conclusion that, within the next few decades, almost no one with
borderline or merely below-average IQ scores should be executed, because their scores when
adjusted downward to 2002 levels would be below 70. Indeed, the Supreme Court did not
amplify just what moral or medical theory led to the highly general language that it used in
Atkins when it prohibited the imposition of a death sentence for criminals who are “so impaired
as to fall within the range of mentally retarded offenders about whom there is a national
consensus,” 536 U.S. at 317. If Atkins had been a 1917 case, the majority of the population now
living—if we were to apply downward adjustments to their IQ scores to offset the Flynn Effect
from 1917 until now—would be too mentally retarded to be executed; and until the Supreme
Court tells us that it is committed to making such downward adjustments, we decline to do so.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 21
III
Because Black cannot show that he has significantly subaverage general intellectual
functioning that manifested before Black turned eighteen, we need not analyze whether Black
has the requisite deficits in adaptive behavior, which he would also be required to demonstrate in
order to be entitled to Atkins relief.
IV
In sum, the district court did not err in denying Black’s Atkins claim under the applicable
standard set forth by the Tennessee Supreme Court in Coleman.
AFFIRMED.
No. 13-5224 Black v. Carpenter Page 22
_________________
CONCURRENCE
_________________
COLE, Chief Judge, concurring in the opinion except for Section II.E. I concur with the
majority opinion except as to the section discussing the implications of the Flynn Effect. In
holding that Black did not prove that he had significantly subaverage general intellectual
functioning, we concluded that Black’s childhood IQ scores would be above 70 even if we
adjusted those scores to account for both the SEM and the Flynn Effect. Accordingly, I would
not address the question of whether we should apply a Flynn Effect adjustment in cases generally
because it is unnecessary to the resolution of Black’s appeal. Regardless, courts, including our
own in Black I, have regarded the Flynn Effect as an important consideration in determining who
qualifies as intellectually disabled. See, e.g., Black v. Bell, 664 F.3d 81, 95–96 (6th Cir. 2011);
Walker v. True, 399 F.3d 315, 322–23 (4th Cir. 2005).