State v. Magee Pub. Co.

RYAN, District Judge

(dissenting). I am unable to concur in the conclusion reached by the majority of the court; and inasmuch as the question proposed for decision involves the construction of the state Constitution and such construction determines the existence of power as between the executive and the judicial departments of the government, I conceive that a statement of the reasons that lead to such dissent appropriately reflects both the importance and the delicacy of what is decided. .

There is really only one question in the case. It is: Does section 6 of article 5 of the state Constitution, viz., “Subject to such regulations as may be prescribed by law, the Governor shall have power' to grant reprieves and pardons, after conviction for all offenses except treason and in cases of impeachment,” warrant the exercise of the pardoning power by the Governor upon a conviction for criminal contempt as maintained by the state ? If answered in the affirmative, there is an end to the question; for in that case what may be thought of the wisdom of so vesting the power, or indeed of the exercise of it in any given case, becomes at once irrelevant; and it devolves upon the judiciary to defer to the assertion of the power at every point of contact. On the other hand, if answered in the negative, the act of the Executive considered in this case was a futile gesture, destitute of legal effect.

The question is not, unhappily, one of such simplicity that it may be settled readily on an inspection of the constitutional provision referred to; this is apparent from the exhaustive study of authorities and the careful analysis of the main and incidental question evidenced by the opinion of the court, the concurring in which by my colleagues in this case of itself lends great weight to the conclusion evolved.

An element usually attended with doubt in the cases cited is settled here; the contempt in this case is a criminal contempt. Also, the argument may be rescued from confusion by holding firmly to the fact that the proceedings here involved were summary in character, as distinguished from ordinary proceedings under the Criminal Code, which latter plainly have to do with a crime in the usual acceptance of the term, to which the pardoning power of the Governor undoubtedly extends.

The argument of the court,’ compressed to brevity, conies to this: All precedent and authority supports the affirmative of the question. The contrary doctrine is found only in cases in which what was so said was unnecessary to the decision of the court, hence, being mere obiter dictum, lacks persuasiveness. The texts cited by the court, in that they rest upon the cases that the court follows, of course add nothing as authority.

The cases accepted as authority are Ex parte Hickey, 4 Smedes & M. (Miss.) 751; State ex rel. Van Orden v. Sauvinet, 24 La. Ann. 119, 13 Am. Rep. 115; Sharp v. State, 102 Tenn. 9, 49 S. W. 752, 43 L. R. A. 788, 73 Am. St. Rep. 851; Re Mullee, 7 Blatchf. 23, Fed. Cas. No. 9, 911.

These are the facts in Ex parte Hickey, decided in 1844. While the circuit court for one of the counties of Mississippi was in session, the grand jury returned an indictment for murder against a certain defendant. Upon the returning of the indictment, the presiding judge of the court, ignoring the advice of the district attorney, refused to order the issuance of a bench warrant for the defendant, on the ground that he was already under bail and further proceedings to secure his attendance upon court unnecessary. The fact that the defendant was thus allowed to go at large, the crime with which he was charged being one that .provoked considerable feeling in the community, prompted Hickey, who was the editor of a local newspaper, to write and publish therein an editorial which viciously abused the presiding judge for gross official misconduct. For this Hickey was tried by the court as for a criminal contempt and sentenced to jail for five months and to pay a fine in the sum of $500. Immediately thereafter, the Governor of the state granted to the contemner a full and complete pardon. Thereupon the judge ordered a bench warrant against the contemner, who under ir, was rearrested and made to serve the sentence imposed, notwithstanding the pardon of the Governor. The contemner then brought habeas corpus proceedings in the Supreme Court of the state to determine his right to liberty; and it was in regard to the efficacy of the writ upon the return made thereto by the sheriff reciting the above facts, that the opinion of the court now considered was rendered. A matter of procedure disposed of in favor of the relator, the court considered, in order three questions, determinative of the relator’s right to liberty: First, whether the court had jurisdiction to sentence for consequential contempt; second, whether, if so, the sentence actually imposed was valid; third, the power of the Governor to pardon. Obviously if either or both of the first two questions were resolved in favor of the prisoner, he was entitled to his liberty, and if both against him he would nevertheless prevail if the pardon was upheld.

The reasoning of the court to the first question from historical development, from the adjudicated cases, and from the statements of eminent commentators, it is unimportant to review. The court concluded that the exercise of such power was unknown to the common law and hence did not exist. It said:

“The proposition which is thus laid down is, that the doctrine of consequential contempts, in its present broad understanding, was unknown to and not confirmed by the earliest costitutional law of England — Magna Charta.”

That the English and some American courts claimed the right to punish for consequential contempts, the court admitted; but the assertion of such right, it said, was a mere assumption of power which they did not possess. And if as to this there were any doubts the Constitution of the state set them at rest. The constitutional provisions referred to were the Bill of Rights similar to those in most Constitutions, and the provision as to the freedom of the press, viz.:

“Every citizen may freely speak, write and publish his sentiments on all subjects, being responsible for the abuse of that liberty.”

So the court concludes, denying the' jurisdiction of the trial court to punish for consequential contempt:

“The reflections of the petitioner upon the circuit judge of Warren county, as set forth in the petition complained of, when judged by the practice and assumptions of the English, and some of the American courts, constitute an undoubted contempt of an aggravated character; but when passed through the crucible of our state Constitution, instead of a contempt of court, they become a mere libel on the functionary, and subject only to the punishment prescribed by law for the latter offense.”

Thus bolding tbat the power investigated was a mere unsurpation, tbat the act complained of was not a contempt of court at all but a criminal libel, the court observed further tbat the Legislature of the state bad enacted a statute, then in force, which was definitive of the whole law upon the subject, viz.:

“The courts shall have power to fine and imprison any person who may be guilty of a contempt of court while sitting, either in the presence or hearing of such court; provided, that such fine shall not exceed one hundred dollars, and no person, for such contempt, shall be imprisoned for a longer period than the term of the court in which the contempt shall have been committed.”

It is observed, therefore, tbat the court decided tbat the act complained of was not a contempt of court at all but a criminal libel; tbat as a matter of jurisdiction the court was without power to punish for consequential contempt, even if the act bad been a consequential contempt, tbat even if the act complained of was within the scope of the statute and hence a contempt, the sentence imposed exceeded the statute and was void. It is apparent tbat upon such determination of these questions all doubt was immediately foreclosed as to the relator’s right to liberty. the argument which the court elaborated on the subject of the power of the Governor to pardon for criminal contempt, which offense, it said, was not before it, might nevertheless be sound; but the case thus reviewed, if persuasive at all, is such by reason of the arguments advanced. It is not precedent or authority. Tbat is clear.

Regarding tbat part of the opinion in Ex parte Hickey, which considered the validity of the pardoning power upon a criminal contempt as argument not as authority, the conclusion reached tbat the pardon was valid rests upon two grounds: First, tbat the right to pardon for criminal contempt reposed in the king under the English system; and, secondly, tbat the offense either was one against the functionary (presiding judge), to whom it was offered considered as a mere individual, or one against the state. It was not the former; therefore, it was the latter. These arguments will be considered later.

Historically, the next case in which the question was discussed as pertinent to the decision was that of State ex rel. Van Orden v. Sauvinet, decided by the Supreme Court of Louisiana in 1872. I quote the facts in the case as summarized in the opinion itself:

“The facts seem to be that In the month of February of the present year suit was brought against Van Orden, the relator, by J. B. Eouis to recover from him a cash box and its contents, alleged to contain the amount of thirty-five thousand dollars in money and public securities, which box and alleged contents had been deposited with the relator for safe-keeping. A writ of sequestration was. issued to take the box out of the hands of the relator, and ujDon his refusal to deliver it he was sentenced to be arrested by the sheriff and to be held in custody by him for the period of ten days as for a contempt of court. Application was then made to the Governor oi the state for a pardon which was granted.”

The case came into the Supreme Court on habeas corpus, the sheriff having refused to release the prisoner until ordered so to do by the court.

Such were the facts. The Supreme Court of Louisiana, in the opinion rendered, made no observation upon the nature of contempt proceedings, anti made no distinction between civil and criminal contempt. It -upheld the pardon upon the reasoning that the existence of such power on the part of the Governor is deducted from the scheme of checks and balances in our system of government; and upon the authority of Ex parte Hickey, which case it specifically refers to as an authority; and it was the sole authority relied upon. The opinion says:

“But we are not without authority on the question of the power of the Governor to grant pardons in cases of contempt. In Ex parte Hickey, etc.”

It then summarizes the doctrine approved by it in regard to tbe pardoning power of the Governor in contempts, quoting from Ex parte Hickey the precise language set out in full in the opinion of the court in this ease. Consideration of the arguments advanced upon the check and balance theory is deferred. The case of Ex parte Hickey as authority it is unnecessary to appraise further. The majority opinion cites and relies upon this case as authority; dismissing the criticism directed against it to the effect that the facts made the contempt civil and not criminal as untenable, it observes that the Louisiana ease considered the facts as constituting criminal contempt and quotes and approves the reasons assigned, at once indicative of the interpretation and persuasive of the validity of it, viz., that the punishment for the contempt is in the nature of a penalty in which the party injured has no interest and which concerns the state only as the offended party. The observation of the majority opinion accepting this argument and conclusion is deserving of careful attention. The contempt in the Louisiana case was not prosecuted in a separate proceeding, and, as observed by the court, unless the imprisonment was “in a case in which the court had appellate jurisdiction, the proceeding would have been dismissed.” Says the court on this point:

“We regard the order under which the party in this case was arrested, and is held in custody by the sheriff, as constituting a part of the proceedings in the suit of Lewis v. Van Orden. The order of sequestration was rendered by the judge in the exercise of 'his judicial functions in determining the issues presented by the parties. The order of imprisonment consequent upon the realtor’s alleged contempt, forms part of the proceedings in the action pending. It grew out of and constituted an important part of those proceedings * * * * We do not view it in the light of a separate, independent, isolated action or proceeding detached from the main action, and wholly unconnected with it.”

Here then the situation is made plain. The plaintiff in the main action had a certain right, and since it concerned the possession of a box containing $35,000 in money and securities, of no inconsequential value to him, the right had to do with the possession of the box delivered to the defendant in trust for safekeeping. The defendant refused to return the bos, and the plaintiff brought an action in court for the possession of it, and under appropriate proceedings secured a writ of sequestration against the defendant. Notwithstanding the force of the writ, the defendant refused to do as judicially commanded. Hence the court, resorting to the only remedy that was left, and without which the action of the court in the premises would have been impotent and pitiable, coerced the defendant by imprisonment. That the imprisonment was for ten days is utterly irrelevant. The court retained • jurisdiction of the main action and could have repeated the term of imprisonment ad infinitum until the purpose of it was accomplished; and the defendant could have purged himself at any time within the term by performance. This was civil contempt. Gompers v. Buck’s Stove & R. Co., 221 U. S. 418, 31 Sup. Ct. 492, 55 L. Ed. 796, 34 L. R. A. (N. S.) 874; State ex rel. Rodd v. Verage, 177 Wis. 295, 187 N. W. 830, 23 A. L. R. 491. Otherwise the majority opinion in this case seriously erred as to what constitutes civil contempt. • Now it has been held uniformly and consistently by every court that the pardoning power of the king does not and never did extend to civil contempt. The case now considered is the only one extant that has ever announced so startling doctrine as that contained in the statement in the Louisiana case, quoted and adopted by the majority opinion. The facts were incapable of any construction other than that of civil contempt. The penalty imposed for disobedience to the writ of sequestration, was in substantial character a remedy in which the plaintiff had the same property right that he had in the thing itself, the securing of which to him the penalty purposed. And when the Governor of Louisiana pardoned the defendant, he silenced judicial proceedings and effectually transferred the property in litigation from the plaintiff to the defendant. If the doctrine thus announced by the majority opinion be sound, since chancery courts act only in personam tbeir decrees henceforth may have effect only if the party against whom they are directed is persuaded to obey them. Certainly they cannot command without at least the tacit imprimatur of the chief executive.

“While it is sparingly to be used, yet the power of courts to punish for contempts is a necessary and integral part of the independence of the judiciary, and is absolutely essential to the performance of the duties .imposed on them by law. Without it they are mere boards of arbitration, whose judgments and decrees would be only advisory.” Gompers v. Buck’s Stove & R. Co, 221 U. S. 418, 31 Sup. Ct. 492, 55 L. Ed. 809, 34 L. R. A. (N. S.) 874.

I do not maintain that this opinion is dictum. I am willing to admit that if the pardoning power of the Governor extends to civil contempt, a fortiori it extends to criminal contempt. I am merely calling attention to the egregious absurdity of the opinion of the court in State ex rel. Van Orden v. Sauvinet and how utterly unworthy it is as authority and precedent.

The next case cited is that of Sharp v. State, decided by the Supreme Court of Tennessee in 1899. The misconduct upon which the contempt was based was that of packing a jury. The case came before the Supreme Court on appeal by the sheriff, who in habeas corpus proceedings in the district court was directed to release the contemner for the reason that the Governor had granted him a pardon. The pardon was valid, the Supreme Court held, because coming within the term of the constitutional provision invoked. “He (the Governor) shall have power to grant reprieves and pardons after conviction except in cases of impeachment.” The authority of the court for holding that a sentence for contempt is such a conviction as is intended by the language employed in the Constitution is Ex parte Hickey, State v. Sauvinet; and In re Mullee, 7 Blatchf. 23, Fed. Cas. No. 9,911. There are other cases cited, but an examination of them discloses that they are not in point. The Mississippi and Louisiana cases are in this opinion quoted at considerable length as setting forth the correct statement of the law and as authority. Inasmuch as the Tennessee case follows the first two decisions mentioned, it adds to them as authority only to the force of its approval. If it adds any weight to the argument advanced, it is found in the case in Re Mullee, which it cites. The Mullee Case grew out of a contempt, in violating an injunction order of the federal court for which that court imposed a fine upon the contemner, which the latter was unable to pay and for that reason applied to the court for the remission of the punishment. To the application the court agreed, but expressed the opinion that he was without power to grant it. Of course, an opinion thus expressed lacks the persuasive force of authority, which, in order to properly deserve the appellation, requires that an applicable rule of law be urged on one side and disputed on the other and thus presented to the court for decision. But conceding the case to be authority for the purpose of argument, the reason of the opinion is based on the proposition that the offense is one against the United States and not against the functionary, which, it is seen, is the same argument that guided the conclusion reached in Ex parte Hickey, and this argument is fortified by the citation of the opinion of Mr. Attorney General Gilpin in Re Dixon, in which the advice of the Attorney General, to the effect that the President has the pardoning power in contempt cases, was bottomed upon the fact that such power was acknowledged to be vested in the king. This is the reasoning of the Louisiana case.

I hazard the observation, therefore, that none of the cases dealing with the pardoning power of the Governor upon a criminal contempt, upon which the majority opinion relies, carries such weight as precedent and authority as to justify the conclusion reached. For the purpose of this discussion I am not unwilling to concede that the cases cited to the point by the state are dicta. But I do maintain that in the absence of authority and precedent it becomes the manifest duty of the court to consider this case as one of first impression, whcih it is, and consequently to recur to basic principles, to analyze them in the light of all that has been said upon the question at issue, whether dicta or not, and reach such conclusion as these principles inevitably lead to.

What is a contempt? The contempt inquired about is one punishable by summary methods, the one involved in this case. Definition by assemblage of apt words nicely expressive of the thing defined in the abstract is of little practical utility. What is valuable is a true conception of the idea, that which comes irresistibly from a knowledge of the thing ir. the concrete; from a clear understanding of the practical operation of the court as an institution of government to which the contemner, his conduct, and the punishment inflicted are related.

The government of the state of New Mexico, like its ■ great prototype, the government of the United States, is a constitutional government, republican in form, in which complete and ultimate sovereignty, which resides in the people, by grant of power through the great fundamental law, is delegated to three departments of the government, the Executive, the Legislative, and the Judicial. Each is sovereign and possesses all the attributes of sovereignty in its own field of activity, and each is essential to the effective and orderly conduct of government, the ultimate purposi of which is the general welfare of society. The division of sovereignty in this manner was deemed as necessary as tyranny was held infamous. The division has been styled a system of checks and balances, but in active operation the limitation of each department, according as power is committed to it, forbids the assumption of like power by the other two; for were this not so, the absorption of all power by the most energetic and strongest department would destroy the others, and thus frustrate the very purpose of the division. The proper characterization of the distribution is that of co-ordination, for each department is independent and supreme in its own field. The idea of the system of cheek and balances properly understood excludes all interference by one department with the powers that belong to another. This is made clear by article 3 of the state Constitution:

“Distribution of powers. Section 1. The powers of the government of this state are divided into three distinct departments, the Legislative, Executive and Judicial, and no person or collection of persons charged with the exercise of powers properly belonging to one of these departments, shall exercise any powers properly belonging to either of the others, except as in this Constitution otherwise expressly directed or permitted.”

The Supreme and district courts are created by a grant of power contained in article 6 of the state Constitution. An examination of this article, or indeed of the entire instrument, discloses that nowhere are the Supreme or district courts clothed expressly with power to punish for contempt. How then do they possess such power? The question is not a novel one, and was answered as to the power exercised in this respect as well as in many others by Chief Justice Marshall, in McCulloch v. Maryland, 4 Wheat. 422, 4 L. Ed. 602-605:

“Had it been intended to grant this power as one which should be distinct and independent, to be exercised in any case whatever, it would have found a place among the enumerated powers of the government. But being considered merely as a means, to be employed only for the purpose of carrying into execution the given powers, there could be no motive for particularly mentioning it.”

Commenting hereon, the United States Supreme Court says in Marshall v. Gordon, 243 U. S. 521, 37 Sup. Ct. 448, 61 L. Ed. 885, L. R. A. 1917F, 279 Ann. Cas. 1918B, 371:

“The rule of constitutional interpretation announced in McCulloch v. Maryland, 4 Wheat. 316, 4 L. Ed. 579, that that which was reasonably appropriate and relevant to the exercise of a granted power was to be considered as accompanying the grant, has been so universally applied that it suffices merely to state it. And as there is nothing in the inherent nature of the power to deal with contempt which causes it to be an exception to such rule, there can be no reason for refusing to apply it to that subject.”

In wbat respect is power to punish for contempt an implied power; that is, reasonably relevant and appropriate to the exercise of the power expressly granted, namely, the power judicially to administer the law of the land? The answer is best given by a consideration of the decisions of the United States Supreme. Court. Incidentally, the matter first came before that court with reference to the implied power to the federal Legislature, but what was so announced is not inapposite to the point here considered, for recently the same court has reiterated approval and applied all thus said to the judicial power as equally appropriate to it. Toledo Newspaper Co. v. United States (October term, 1917) 247 U. S. 402, 38 Sup. Ct. 560, 62 L. Ed. 1193.

The case of Anderson v. Dunn came before the federal Supreme Court (February term, 1821), 6 Wheat. 204, 5 L. Ed. 242, upon the question whether the United States House of Representatives could imprison, for contempt of its authority, the alleged con-temner, who was arrested by the sergeant-at-arms of: that body, under a house warrant, having brought a charge against such officer for false imprisonment. To the question thus presented, Mr. Justice Johnson said, upholding the contempt power of the House:

“It is true that such a power if it exists, must be derived from implication, and the genius and spirit of our institutions are hostile to the exercise of implied powers. Had the faculties of man been competent to the framing of a system of government which would have left nothing to implication, it cannot be doubted that the effort Would have been made by the framers of the Constitution. But what is the fact? There is not in the whole of that admirable instrument a grant of powers which does not draw after it others, not expressed, but vital to their exercise; not substantive and independent, indeed, but auxiliary and subordinate. * * *
“But if there is one maxim which necessarily rises above all others in the practical application of government, it is, that the public functionaries must be left at liberty to exercise the powers which the people have intrusted to them. The interests and dignity of those who created them, require the execution of the powers indispensable to the attainment of the ends of their creation. Nor is a casual conflict with the rights of particular individual any reason to be urged against the exercise of such powers.
. “That ‘the safety of the people is the supreme law,’ not only comports with, but is indispensable to, the exercise of those powers in their public functionaries, without Which that .safety cannot be g-uarded. On this principle it is, that courts of justice are universally acknowledged pose silence, respect, and decorum, in their presence, and submission to their lawful mandates, and, as a corollary to this proposition, to preserve themselves and their officers from the approach and insults of pollution.”

In Marshall v. Gordon (October term, 1916) 240 U. S. 521, 37 Sup. Ct. 448, 61 L. Ed. 881, L. R. A. 1917F, 279, Ann. Cas. 1918B, 371, the federal Supreme Court again bad under consideration the contempt power of the national 'House of Eepresentatives; and reaffirming what bas been said in Anderson v. Dunn, supra, and clarifying the doctrine of that case with reference to later cases decided by it, and with reference to the English ease, Kielley v. Carson, it again stated the essential meaning of contempt:

“What does this implied power embrace? Is thus the question. In answering, it must be borne in mind that the power rests simply upon the implication that the right to be vested, by their very creation, with power to im-of some other and substantive authority expressly conferred. The power is therefore but a force implied to bring into existence the conditions to which constitutional limitations apply. It is a means to an end, and not the end itself. Hence it rests solely upon the right of self-preservation to enable the public powers given to be exerted. * * *
“Without undertaking to inclusively mention the subjects embraced in the implied power, we think from the very nature of that power it is clear that it does not embrace punishment for contempt as punishment, since it rests only upon the right of self-preservation; that is, the right to prevent acts which, in and of themselves, inherently obstruct or prevent the discharge of legislative duty or the refusal to do that which there is an inherent legislative power to compel in order that legislative functions may be performed. And the essential nature of the power also makes clear the cogency and application of the two limitations which were expressly pointed out in Anderson v. Dunn, supra; that is, that the power, even when applied to subjects which justify its exercise, is limited to imprisonment, and such imprisonment may not be extended beyond the session of the body in which the contempt occurred. Not only the adjudged cases, but congressional action in enacting legislation as well as in exerting the implied power, conclusively sustain the views just stated. Take, for instance, the statute referred to in Re Chapman, where, not at all interfering- with the implied congressional power to deal with the refusal to give testimony in a matter where there was a right to exact it, the substantive power had been exerted to make such refusal a crime, the two being distinct the one from the other.”

Again in Toledo Newspaper Co. v. United States, 247 U. S. 402, 38 Sup. Ct. 560, 62 L. Ed. 1186, which was a review of a sentence of contempt imposed upon the contemner for abusive language toward the federal court, with reference to an injunction suit pending before it, reviewing the Marshall v. Gordon Case, and previous decisions in line with it, the court said:

“While the Marshall Case concerned the exercise of legislative power to deal with contempt, the fundamental principles which its solution involved are here applicable to' the extent that they may not be inapposite because of the distinction between legislative and judicial power. Indeed, the identity of the constitutional principles applicable to the two cases, subject to the difference referred to, was pointed out on pages 542 and 543, where it was said: ‘So, also, when the difference between the judicial and legislative powers is considered and the divergent elements which, in the nature of things, enter into the determination of what is self-preservation in the two cases, the same result is established by the statutory provision dealing with the judicial authority to summarily punish for contempt; that is, without resorting to the modes of trial required by constitutional limitations or otherwise for substantive offenses under the criminal law. Act of March 2. 1831, 4 Stat. at L. 487, c. 99, Comp. Stat. 1916, § 1245.’
“Clarified by the matters expounded and the ruling made in the Marshall Case there can be np doubt th,at the provisions [268 of the Judicial Code] conferred no power not already granted and imposed no limitations not already existing. In other words, it served but to plainly mark the boundaries of the existing authority resulting from and controlled by the grants which the Constitution made and the limitations which it imposed. And this is not at all modified by conceding that the provision was intended to prevent the danger by reminiscence of what had gone before or attempts to exercise a power not possessed, which, as pointed out in the Marshall Case, had been sometimes done in the exercise of legislative power. The provision, therefore, conformably to the whole history of the country, not minimizing- the constitutional limitations nor restricting or qualifying the powers granted, by necessary implication recog'nized and sanctioned the existence of the right of self-preservation; that is, the power to restrain acts tending to obstruct and prevent the untrammeled and unprejudiced exercise of the judicial power given by summarily treating such acts as a contempt and punishing accordingly. The test, therefore, is the character of the act done and its direct tendency to prevent and obstruct the discharge of judicial duty.”

And in harmony with what was said supra, in the case of Craig v. Hecht, 44 Sup. Ct. 103, 68 L. Ed. —, decided by the federal Supreme Court, at the present term, Mr. Chief Justice Taft, concurring in the opinion of the court, observed:

“The remedy of the judge as an individual is by action or prosecution for libel. If, however, the publication is intended and calculated to obstruct and embarrass the court in a pending proceeding in the matter of the rendition of an impartial verdict, or in the carrying- out of its orders and judgment, the court may, and it is its duty to protect the administration of justice by punishment of the offender for contempt.”

Without venturing on the perilous enterprise of framing an adequate definition, it may be said that a summary contempt of court, as is evident from the judicial expressions above set forth, and they are of the highest character, carries these fundamental conceptions : It is conduct intended and calculated to obstruct and embarrass the court in pending proceedings in the matter of the rendition of an impartial verdict (criminal contempt), or in the carrying out of orders and judgment (civil contempt), which justifies the court, or rather makes it the duty of the court, to visit such punishment upon the offender as will protect the administration of justice. Taft, C. J., in Craig v. Hecht, supra. The substance of the proceeding is the exertion by the court of the implied power of self-preservation. The object of the exertion of the power is not punishment as punishment. Toledo Newspaper Co. v. United States, supra. But the punishment is only a means to an end. Id. And the quantum of punishment is limited of necessity, by the end which it contemplates, “the least possible punishment adequate to the end proposed.” Anderson v. Dunn. The end is, of course, the effective and impartial administration of justice.

Conceding that what is above said is a correct analysis of the essential nature of contempt, it follows that the entire operation of proceedings in contempt matters is within the power of self-preservation, implied to courts by reason of the grant to them of the judicial function. The power to punish for contempt emanates from the court, and not from the lawmaking power created by the Constitution. This is so far the fact that a conviction in summary contempt proceeding bears no relation to a conviction for criminal contempt as defined by the lawmaking power, both convictions referring to the same act. In re Chapman, 166 U. S. 661, 17 Sup. Ct. 677, 41 L. Ed. 1159; Marshall v. Gordon, 243 U. S. 521, 37 Sup. Ct. 448, 61 L. Ed. at page 881, L. R. A. 1917F, 279, Ann. Cas. 1918B, 371. A court punishing for criminal contempt is vindicating its own authority and not administering the criminal law. Re Debs, 158 U. S. 564, 15 Sup. Ct. 900, 39 L. Ed. 1092; Eilenbecker v. Plymouth County District Court, 134 U. S. 31, 10 Sup. Ct. 424, 33 L. Ed. 801; Bessette v. W. B. Cokney Co., 194 U. S. 324, 24 Sup. Ct. 665, 48 L. Ed. 997. The relation of the power to the effective and impartial administration of justice is such as to be essential to it. Re Debs, supra; Gompers v. Buck’s Stove Co., 221 U. S. 418, 31 Sup. Ct. 492, 55 L. Ed. 807, 34 L. R. A. (N. S.) 874. And since the power is essential, the Legislature can no more deprive courts created by the Constitution of it than they can deprive them of the power to perform the judicial function. Hale v. State, 55 Ohio St. 210, 45 N. E. 199, 36 L. R. A. 254 and note, 60 Am. St. Rep. 691.

That a crime, therefore, as judicially defined, and a criminal contempt, bear no kinship one to the other, would seem to be the statement of a truism. The two conceptions are mutually exclusive, diverso intuitu. Re Chapman, supra. They are as different as the lawmaking' function is different from tbe judicial function; as tbe general welfare of society, witb wbieb tbe criminal laws are concerned, is different from tbe vindication of the authority of a particular court with reference to a pending case.

It is true the constitutional provision upon tbe construction of which this case turns employs the term “offense,” yet there is not such a distinction between the two expressions as to lend any force whatsoever to the argument based upon the use of the one word rather than the other. “So the words ‘offense’ and ‘crime’ are synonymous when applied to convictions of a public nature.” 16 C. J. 52. In Campion v. Gillan, 79 Neb. 367, 112 N. W. 586, 11 L. R. A. (N. S.) 865, 126 Am. St. Rep. 673, 16 Ann. Cas. 319, the Supreme Court of Nebraska examined the provisions of the Constitution of that state as to the pardoning power, which is:

“The Governor shall have power to grant reprieves and pardons, after , conviction for all offenses except treason and cases of impeachment.”

It said:

“The Constitution gives the Governor power to pardon ‘offenses,’ and it is sug-g'ested that bastardy is an offense, although we have no statute defining and punishing it as a crime, and so the Governor may pardon the wrongdoer and relieve him from all consequences of his act. The provision of our Constitution is too plain to lead to such absurd conclusions. The word ‘offense’ in a public statute is generally, though not always, used as synonymous with ‘crime.’ In State v. West, 42 Minn. 147, 43 N. W. 845, it is said that the terms ‘crime,’ ‘offense’ and ‘criminal offense’ are all synonymous and are ordinarily used interchangeably. At all events, the words are so used in the section of the Constitution under consideration. There can be no doubt that ‘crime’ in the latter part of the section is used as an exact equivalent of the word ‘offense’ in the first part, and that the words ‘convict’ and ‘sentence’ are used with reference to both. Unless there has been a crime and conviction the Governor cannot interfere with a pardon.”

Indeed, that the nature of an ordinary criminal prosecution is wholly foreign to that of summary proceedings for criminal contempt is universally recognized by all courts. Crimes are punishable only in courts baying criminal jurisdiction. Criminal .con-tempts, however, are punishable in all courts of record whether or not their jurisdiction be limited to civil, chancery, or appellate matters. This court, for instance, is without original criminal jurisdiction. Yet I doubt if it would so far hold to the proposition that a criminal contempt committed against it was a “crime” that the offense would of necessity go unpunished unless by the usual course of indictment and trial by a court of inferior jurisdiction.

Moreover, the designation of a criminal contempt as a crime or offense considered with reference to another constitutional provision leads to serious difficulties, for this reason: It is a familiar rule of statutory construction that statutes, and the same rule applies to constitutional provisions, in pari materia should be construed together, because, the cardinal purpose of construction being the ascertainment of legislative intent, it is presumed that provisions relating to the same subject-matter are consistent and harmonious, so that an expression conveying a fixed meaning in one provision carries the identical meaning in another provision in pari materia. Section 14, art. 2, of our Constitution, provides:

“In all criminal prosecutions the accused shall have the right,” etc., of a “public trial by an impartial jury of the county or district in which the offense is alleged to have been committed.”

Now it is clear that this provision is in pari materia with the constitutional provision, supra, relating to the pardoning power. The expression cannot carry radically different meanings in the two provisions; it cannot be Dr. Jekyll to support a pardon and Mr. Hyde to deny a trial by jury.

The decisions uniformly disavow the applicability, of such constitutional provisions to a criminal contempt. The reason is obvious; on the one hand, the power of self-preservation ex vi termini implies the exclusive right to the court to try the offender and to judge as to the punishment adequate to the vindication of its own authority (Gompers v. Buck’s Stove Co., supra), and, on the other hand, defines the conduct of the contemner as not coming at all within the meaning of such constitutional guaranties (Re Debs, supra).

The overwhelming weight of authority is to the effect that a criminal contempt of court is not a crime, and a proceeding thereon, not a criminal proceeding, and that positively considered, because thA proceeding is only the exertion by the court of the power of self-preservation, it is sui generis. I refer the bar to the very able opinion of the Supreme Court of Arizona decided December 30, 1922, Van Dyke v. Superior Court, 24 Ariz. 508, 211 Pac. 576, in which case there is a careful and exhaustive analysis of about all the authorities in regard to the nature of a criminal contempt. The case concludes:

“It is no less certain that it is not a criminal action which is to be prosecuted by indictment or information as provided by our Constitution and Penal Code (Const. art. 2 . Penal Code, § 750). It is perhaps not unwarranted to say that virtually all the authorities which announce any express holding- as to the nature of a proceeding to punish for criminal contempt go upon the assumption that such a proceeding is sui generis, being the exercise of the inherent power of courts to free themselves from influences calculated or tending- to obstruct, embarrass, or corrupt the administration of justice. Prom these general principles, in their bearing upon the specific cases of applications to secure changes of venue, or to disqualify the presiding- judge, the rule is deduced that, unless the statute contain language broad enough in meaning to include a proceeding instituted to punish for contempt, the change of judge or venue cannot be made, and that the language ‘criminal action’ or ‘civil action’ is not to be interpreted as embracing a contempt proceeding.” Bessette v. W. B. Conkey Co., supra.

. Here it might be worthy to note that the language employed by some of the decisions of the federal Supreme Court as to the nature of criminal contempts has been misinterpreted to mean that that court considered proceedings in regard to them as criminal proceedings. A careful reading of tbe cases forbids sucb a conclusion. That court has always characterized contempt proceedings as sui generis, and, for the purpose of review only, has considered them as governed by the rules applicable to criminal matters. This is the interpretation which the court itself has expressed as to these cases. In Toledo Newspapar Co. v. United States, supra, to this point the court says:

“We are of opinion that a motion to dismiss the writ, of error must prevail, since it is settled that a conviction for a criminal although summary contempt is, for the purposes of our reviewing power, a matter of criminal law not within our jurisdiction on error” — citing numerous cases, among them, as being- within the interpretation thus announced, Gompers v. United States, 233 U. S. 604, 34 Sup. Ct. 693, 58 L. Ed. 1115, Ann. Gas. 1915D, 1044, which case the majority opinion refers to as decisive of the proposition that a criminal contempt is a crime or offense within the meaning- of the constitutional provision defining the pardoning power.

The view which this court thus takes of the case is not in harmony with that of the federal Supreme Court itself.

I recur now to Ex parte Hickey, to assess the soundness of the argument therein elaborated to the conclusion that a criminal contempt was within the pardoning power of the Governor, notwithstanding that it had been found by the court that there was no contempt involved in the case.

The provision of the Constitution of Mississippi (Const. 1832, art. 5, § 10), examined by that court was, the Governor shall, etc., “have power to grant reprieves and pardons, and to remit fines in all criminal and penal cases, except treason and impeachment”; the language employed, in form, being more restrictive than the language employed in our Constitution, though not so in substance. At the threshold the court tacitly admitted that in order to sustain the pardon, it was essential to bring a contempt of court as an offense within the classification of a “criminal charge” or “criminal case,” which expression it held to be witbin the purview of Blackstone’s definition, namely:

“A crime or misdemeanor is an act committed or omitted m violation of a public law either forbidding- or commanding it.”

The court proceeded, and very correctly, upon the premise that the acts pardonable, under the Constitution, were public offenses, which are generally defined as “the doing that which a penal law forbids to be done or omitting to do what it commands.” 32 Cyc. 1249. That is to say, a contempt of court to be pardonable must be a crime or a public offense. The minor premise is attempted to be established evidently by drawing a distinction between public offenses and civil wrongs, which latter are wrongs to the individual in which the public have no interest. A contempt of court it was argued, because it is not an offense against the functionary as an individual, was consequently a public offense and a crime. The fallacy of the argument lies in the manner of establishing the minor premise. To affirm logically that X is A because it is not B requires, first, satisfactory proof that of necessity X must be found within the alternatives. A contempt of court, as has been shown, is in essential character neither a criminal case nor a civil ease, but sui generis, that is, an offense against the court; so that the possibility of X being C instead of A or B being proven, the whole argument collapses.

It is to be noticed, also, that the court had just announced the doctrine that an offense to the person of the functionary was a criminal libel and not a contempt. We come, therefore, by transposing terms, to the weird proposition that a contempt of court is an offense against the state and a crime because it is not a criminal libel which is crime. The argument, I think, need not be criticized further.

It was maintained in Ex parte Hickey that the constitutional provision in regard to the freedom of the press, quoted supra, together with the other provisions already mentioned, operated to metamorphose to a criminal libel, wbat, judged by tbe practice and assumption of some of tbe courts, English and American, would have been a criminal contempt and as to publications at least to restrain the power of the court to punish as for the latter offense. To this doctrine the final answer, I believe, was given by Mr. Chief Justice White in Toledo Newspaper Co. v. United States:

“We might well pass the proposition by because to state it is to answer it, since it involves in its very statement the contention that the freedom of the press is the freedom to do wrong with impunity, and implies the rig-ht to frustrate and defeat the discharge of those g-overnmental duties upon the performance of which the freedom of all, including that of the press, depends. The safeguarding and fructification of free and constitutional institutions is the very basis and mainstay upon which the freedom of the press rests, and that freedom, therefore, does not and cannot be held to include the right virtually to destroy such institutions. It suffices to say that, however complete is the right of the press to state public things and discuss them, that right, as every other right enjoyed in human society, is subject to the restraints which separate right from wrongdoing.”

There remains then to be considered the proposition which, it has been seen, constitutes the principal argument, by implication at least, in the ease followed by the majoritj’' of the court to the effect that the Governor possesses the power to pardon for criminal contempt because like power was in fact possessed and exercised by the king under the English system. It is unnecessary to observe that by statutory recognition the common law of England is here the rule of practice and decision except as modified by express statute. Upon this rule there is imposed the limitation that only so much of that system is adopted as is compatible with our peculiar conditions and with the genius of our government and institutions. That the .application of the limitation to the question considered excludes the power of the Governor to pardon for criminal contempt upon the ground of analogy to the power of the king becomes immediately apparent. Under our system, as stated above, all power emanates from the people. Under the English system, all power emanates from the king, who is in theory “the source and fountain of justice.” The executive here has such power only as the Constitution confers upon him, but the king could pardon for criminal contempt because in him was reposed originally all judiciary power. He could review judicial action because the courts were his courts and perform the judicial functions because such power was by him delegated to them. Says Blaekstone in this regard :

“The sole executive power of the laws is vested in the person of the king; it will follow that all courts of justice, which are the medium by which he administers the laws, are derived from the power of the crown. For whether created by act of Parliament or letters patent, or subsisting by prescription (the only methods by which any court of judicature can exist), the king’s consent in the two former is expressly, in the latter impliedly, given. In all these courts the king is supposed in contemplation of law to be always present; but as that is in fact impossible, he is then represented by his judges, whose power is only an emanation of the royal prerogative.”

The power of the Governor and the power of the king under the English system to the extent that they affect the power to pardon for criminal contempt are irreconcilable. See State ex rel. Rodd v. Verage, 177 Wis. 295, 187 N. W. 830, 23 A. L. R. 508; Re Nevitt, 117 Fed. 448, 54 C. C. A. 622; Taylor v. Goodrich, 25 Tex. Civ. App. 109, 40 S. W. 515.

Therefore, I say, the cases followed by the court not only lack persuasiveness as authority, in that they are cast to the mold of Ex parte Hickey, but the doctrine announced by them as supporting the conclusion reached that the Governor may pardon for criminal contempt is clearly fallacious.

“A pardon is an act of grace, proceeding from the power intrusted with the exceeuion of the laws, which exempts the individual on whom it is bestowed from the punishment the law inflicts for a crime he has committed.” This is the language of Chief Justice Marshall in United States v. Wilson, 7 Pet. 150, 8 L. Ed. 640, and is the classical definition of a “pardon.” It is seen that the very essence of the pardoning power lies in this: That because the Governor (as here) is charged with the execution of the laws he may pardon by an act of grace for an infraction of such laws. The laws, with the execution of which the executive is charged, are penal laws of statutory recognition because they are public offenses, and it is consequently public offenses that the framers of the Constitution had in mind in defining the pardoning power. State ex rel. Rodd v. Verage, 177 Wis. 295, 187 N. W. 830, 23 A. L. R. 509:

“As the Governor is charged with the duty of seeing that the laws be faithfully executed, it is in strict accordance with the theory of the power of pardon that he should have power to pardon offenders against the laws which it is his duty to execute. But should such power extend to offenses with respect to which he has no duty or concern? Does the power of one to pardon the violation of a law which it is not his duty to execute comport with the theory of the pardoning- power? If the Governor is not charged with the duty' of enforcing obedience to the orders of the court, on what theory should he have the power to forgive disobedience of those orders? The power of the sovereign to pardon is much like the power of an individual to remit a debt. A. may remit a debt owing to him by C., but B. is without power to remit the debt which C. owes to A.”

Here tbe fact is to be attended to that when we speak of an offense against the state, what is meant is a public offense, one of legislative recognition; that is, either defined by express statute or known to common law and adopted by legislative act. Clarified by this statement, a discussion of the offense here considered as against organized society or as against the majesty of the law is a matter of vocabulary and rhetoric, not of actuality and substance; for, if organized society denounces an act as criminal, it does so through constitutional methods, that is, by legislative act. Obviously, the majesty of the law is a pure abstraction and can- neither declare an act criminal nor impose a penalty for its violation. It is true that the court is that institution of the government which bespeaks the majesty of the law and which is the very cornerstone of organized society; consequently, a criminal contempt of court, in that it outrages the dignity and authority of the court, is, in this respect, essentially an offense against the majesty of the law, against organized society, against the state; but in the sense of being an offense against the public law with the execution of which the Governor is charged, it emphatically is not an offense against the state.

Indeed, the statement of the constitutional provision itself lends no little force to the proposition that by the application to it of the ordinary rule of interpretation the “offenses” which the Governor may pardon are such offenses as are of usual statutory recognition. The classification of crimes at common law was treason, felonies, and misdemeanors. 16 C. J. 55. The inference is legitimate that, when “treason.” was excepted from the' offenses pardonable, the word “offense” was intended to mean the classification in which treason would have been included save for the exception.

So far as the judicial function is concerned, there is no relation whatsoever between the pardon of an ordinary crime as denounced by legislative act and the pardon of a criminal contempt. The pardon of a criminal after conviction, when he is beyond the jurisdiction of the court, has no more to do with the impartial and unembarrassed administration of justice with reference to a pending case, with the court as an institution of government, than has the failure of the sheriff to arrest one suspected of a crime, before he has been brought within the jurisdiction of the courc. The acts of executive officers in both instances concern the welfare of society, and are meaningless so far as they might affect the court as an institution of government. On the other hand, the contempt power is an essential part of the judicial function without which justice cannot be impartially and effectively administered. To this effect the United States Supreme Court says, in Re Debs, quoting with approval the Supreme Court of Mississippi in Watson v. Williams, 36 Miss. 331:

“The power to fine and imprison for contempt, from the earliest history of jurisprudence, has been regarded as a necessary incident and attribute of a court, without which it could no more exist than without a judge. It is a power inherent in all courts of record, and coexisting' with them by the wise provisions of the common law. A court without the power effectually to protect itself against the assaults of the lawless, or to enforce its orders, judgments, or decrees against the recusant parties before it, would be a disgrace to the legislation, and a stigma upon the age which invented it.” 39 L. Ed. 1106.

If the contempt power is so defined' with reference to the administration of justice and if tbe punishment inflicted is a means to an end, it would seem to be incontrovertible that to exempt an individual from such punishment destroys the means to the end and frustrates the accomplishment of that end, so that the Governor consequently can no more annul the punishment than he can destroy the court itself. If the exercise of the contempt power is, as above stated, the exertion by the court of the implied power of sélf-preservation, that it cannot be interfered with by another department of government is an a priori judgment; if the definition of the power in its essential character be correct, the denial of the pardoning power with reference to it becomes a matter of logical necessity. The same implication from which the power is derived serves to exclude the pretensions of the Governor to pardon. This is made clear by the great Justice Story, the associate and' compeer of Marshall himself, in Story on the Constitution (5th Ed.) §1503:

“It would seem to result from the principle on which the power of each branch of the Legislature to punish for contempts is founded that the executive authority cannot interpose between them and the offender. The main object is to secure a purity, independence, and ability of the Legislature adequate to the discharge of all of their duties. If they can be overawed by force, or corrupted by largesses, or interrupted in their proceedings by violence, without the means of self-protection, it is obvious that they will soon be found incapable of legislating with wisdom or independence. If the executive should possess the power of pardoning any such offender, they would be wholly dependent upon his good will and pleasure for the exercise of their own powers. Thus, in effect, the rights of the people intrusted to them would be placed in perpetual jeopardy. The Constitution is silent in respect to the right of granting pardons in such cases, as it is in respect to the jurisdiction to punish for • contempts. The latter arises by implication; and, to make it effectual, the former is excluded by implication.”

What the great justice said above is forcibly expressed with more particularity by Judge Sanborn, of the United States Circuit Court of Appeals, in Re Nevitt, 117 Fed. 456, 54 C. C. A. 630:

“If the President has the power to pardon those who are committed for criminal contempts of the authority of the courts, and thus to relieve them from fines or imprisonments inflicted to punish them for their disobedience, this immemorial attribute of judicial power is thus practically withdrawn from the courts and transferred to the executive; for he may pardon whom he will, and he would have the power to so exercise this authority as to deprive the courts of all means to punish for disobedience of their orders. Is there any provision of the Constitution of the United States which grants this inherent and essential attribute of judicial power, or the authority to control its exercise, to the executive? Congress has undoubted authority to punish recalcitrant witnesses for contempt of its authority. The offenses of such witnesses are as much offenses against the United States as the offenses of witnesses jurors, or parties who disobey the orders, writs, or processes of the courts. May the President pardon such witnesses who are committed for the purpose of punishing them for the disobedience of such orders and processes, and thus deprive Congress and the courts of the ability to punish for disobedience of their lawful orders and processes? If a court fines or imprisons a juror because he refuses to obey its mandate when summoned, or because he refuses to act when he appears, may the President immediately pardon him, and thus relieve him from all punishment for disobedience of the order of the court? May he pardon all jurors for all disobedience of the mandates of the courts, and thus practically deprive the courts of the power to summon jurors? If riotous persons are fined or imprisoned for disturbing, defying, and preventing the proceedings of a court, may the President pardon them, and thus deprive the court of the power to continue its sessions and to discharge its functions? In other words, has the executive the power, if he chooses to exercise it, of drawing' to himsefl all the real judicial power of the nation which the Constitution vested in express terms in the courts, by means of his supreme control of the inherent and essential attribute of that power — the authority to punish for- disobedience of the orders of the courts? These questions seem to suggest their answers.”

To tbe same effect the doctrine is elaborated by the Court of Civil Appeals of Texas in Taylor v. Goodrich, 25 Tex. Civ. App. 124, 40 S. W. 523:

"The real Inquiry is ■whether a contempt proceeding is a criminal case, within the meaning of this constitutional provision. If the words ‘criminal case’ are confined to the crimes mentioned in the Penal Code, and should be held to be construed only as the terms ‘crime,’ and ‘offense’ are therein defined, there would be little difficulty in reaching a correct conclusion upon this question; for the question of contempt is not mentioned in the Penal Code, and is not there characterized as a crime or offense. When we inquire into the reason of the law that confers the power upon the courts to punish for contempts, we cannot well perceive that the Constitution, in authorizing' the executive to pardon crimes, and remit fines in criminal cases, intended that the power should be exercised in contempt cases, and that such cases should be regarded as criminal. The efficiency and integrity of courts demand that they shall have the right, in order to transact their business in an orderly-way, to require the observance of decorum, and to punish those who may interfere with them when exercising their judicial functions, or who may at such times, by willful conduct, interfere with the peace of the court, or bring it into contempt. If the power is given to the Governor to pardon in cases of this character, it admits the weakness and want of the power in the court to preserve its standing and to protect itself from contempt, and would virtually lodge in the Governor the final power to determine if a contempt has been shown to the court, and whether the party should be punished. Such a concession of authority is incompatible with many provisions of law on the subject of contempt. How could a court preserve the ends of justice by compelling an unwilling witness to testify, if the Governor could relieve him from the punishment inflicted by the court for his refusal? How may a court enforce its orders in injunction and mandamus, and in other proceedings, if a Governor may virtually set them aside by pardoning the one who has wilfully disobeyed them. How may obedience to the process of the court be enforced, if a Governor may stand between the court and the one that has disobeyed it. How may a court, in an orderly and efficient way, perform its official functions and public duties, if a Governor may paralyze its power in furtherance of these ends? The moment you admit that a Governor has the power to cripple a court in the performance of its duties, in the way noticed, then it virtually follows, as a sequence, that the courts, in the administration of justice, are under the control of the Governor, and while he cannot influence their judicial acts and conduct, he may control them. It is not believed that the Constitution of this state intended to invest him with any such power.”

In re Nevitt is valuable only for tbe argument tbat it contains; for that part of the case wbicb bad to do with the right of the President to pardon is, as the court stated, dicta. the statement of the court, however, in the case of Taylor v. Goodrich, with reference to the pardoning power, is authority and precedent. the criticism made against it in this respect, to the effect that it is not in point because of the fact that in Texas there are no crimes except those defined by statutes, is, I think, made unavailing by a cursory examination of the case and the reasons given by the court that lead to the conclusion reached. the court itself said that its decision depended upon the interpretation of the constitutional provision defining the pardoning power. Very clearly such interpretation is a judicial and not a legislative matter, so that the court was not concluded by the legislative act in excluding a criminal contempt from the definition of crimes. It is clear that what the court did was to give weight to the legislative interpretation that a criminal contempt is not a substantive crime; but, even bad the Legislature defined, a “criminal contempt” as a substantive crime, certainly it could not be held that its act in so doing was bniding on the court. It might be observed further to this point,, that if the contention that a summary contempt is a substantive crime be true in fact, and under the laws of Texas there are no crimes except those of legislative definition, then it would result that the courts of Texas are without power to punish criminal contempt — a conclusion wbicb, I apprehend, might come as a considerable surprise to the judiciary of Texas. the criticism proves too much.

the duties of the Governor are executive, except as the approval or veto of a legislative act is the exercise of legislative function. Nowhere in the Constitution is power conferred upon the Governor to review or interfere with judicial proceedings. that power is conferred upon the Supreme Court. It alone has appellate jurisdiction as to the orders, decrees, and judgments of and a superintending control over inferior courts. Article 6, State Constitution. Tbe grant of judicial power in one case is no clearer or more emphatic than is tbe exclusion of it in tbe other. That tbe granting’ of a pardon for a criminal contempt is tbe exercise of a superintending control oyer the court in which such proceedings were had is too plain to require argument. The Governor of an American state is not only the repository of those powers constitutionally conferred' upon him, but he is the titular head and actual leader of the particular party which put him in office, and as such he is not insensitive to political draughts — a consideration which most strongly denies any intent or purpose on the part of those who designed our fundamental law to press upon the judicial process the dead hand of political expediency. On the contrary, a vigorous independent judiciary is the very bulwark of our institutions. The Constitution reflects such a conception of the judiciary. That the typical state executive may be depended upon not to exercise the power here asserted except in rare instances, though such power be conceded to him. and that the fears for the judiciary here expressed are fanciful rather than real, is an irrelevant consideration. Finem volunt media. The question concerns the constitutional existence of power; that granted, it may be exercised in any of the. instances above stated and to the frustration of judicial power as indicated. Only, if the extension of the pardon power to criminal contempt be clearly indicated by the language of the Constitution should the pardon in this case be upheld; not by forcibly reading that intent into the provision examined.

For these reasons I dissent.