Michael CHANDLER, individually and as next friend of his son, Jesse Chandler, et al., Plaintiffs-
Appellees,
v.
Fob JAMES, Jr., in his official capacity as Governor of the State of Alabama and President of the State
Board of Education, et al., Defendants-Appellants.
Nos. 97-6898, 97-6953.
United States Court of Appeals,
Eleventh Circuit.
July 13, 1999.
Appeals from the United States District Court for the Middle District of Alabama. (No. CV-96-D-169-N),
Ira De Ment, Judge.
Before TJOFLAT, Circuit Judge, and GODBOLD and HILL, Senior Circuit Judges.
HILL, Senior Circuit Judge:
Plaintiffs brought this action challenging the facial constitutionality of Alabama's statute permitting
non-sectarian, non-proselytizing student-initiated prayer, invocations and benedictions during compulsory
or non-compulsory school-related assemblies, sporting events, graduation ceremonies and other school-related
events. Plaintiffs also challenged the statute as applied by the DeKalb County School Board. The district
court held the statute unconstitutional on its face, granted plaintiffs partial summary judgment on their claims
regarding the statute as applied, and enjoined defendants from enforcing the statute or continuing to conduct
the challenged practices. Defendants bring this appeal.
I.
In 1993, the Alabama Legislature enacted a statute containing the following provision:
(b) On public school, other public, or other property, non-sectarian, non-proselytizing
student-initiated voluntary prayer, invocation and/or benedictions, shall be permitted during
compulsory or non-compulsory school-related student assemblies, school-related student sporting
events, school-related graduation or commencement ceremonies, and other school-related student
events.
Ala.Code § 16-1-20.3(b) (1995).
In 1996, Michael Chandler, a vice-principal in the DeKalb County school system, and his son Jesse,
a student in that system, brought this action challenging the facial validity and the application of this statute
in the DeKalb County schools.1 Defendants included the Governor of the State of Alabama, the State
Superintendent of Education, the members of the State Board of Education, and the Superintendents and
members of the boards of education of the City of Talladega and of DeKalb County, Alabama.2
On March 12, 1997, the district court granted partial summary judgment for the Chandlers, holding
the statute facially unconstitutional. On October 29, 1997, the district court permanently enjoined DeKalb
County from enforcing the statute. On November 12, 1997, the district court issued findings of fact and
conclusions of law in its Supplemental Opinion and Order. That same day, but by separate Memorandum
Opinion and Order, the district court held that DeKalb had engaged in unconstitutional officially organized
or sponsored religious activities, and granted summary judgment to the Chandlers on their claim that DeKalb
had applied the statute unconstitutionally. The district court appointed a monitor to oversee the enforcement
of the Permanent Injunction. All defendants appealed from the Permanent Injunction, the Supplemental
Opinion and Order, and the Memorandum Opinion and Order.
In his brief, the Governor of the State of Alabama asserts that the district court erred in holding the
statute facially unconstitutional under the First Amendment. The Governor contends that the First
Amendment's prohibition against the establishment of a religion does not apply to the states by virtue of the
Fourteenth Amendment. The district court rejected this argument, as do we. Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310
U.S. 296, 303, 60 S.Ct. 900, 84 L.Ed. 1213 (1940). See also Everson v. Board of Educ., 330 U.S. 1, 8, 67
S.Ct. 504, 91 L.Ed. 711 (1947). Because the states are bound by the First Amendment, the district court did
1
Also named as plaintiffs are Jane Doe and her daughter Deborah Doe.
2
The Chandlers subsequently entered into a partial consent decree with the City of Talladega and the
district court dismissed the Talladega defendants from the case in 1996.
2
not err in evaluating Alabama's statute under it. Accordingly, we shall affirm the judgment of the district
court as to the Governor's appeal.3
The remainder of the appellants (referred to collectively as DeKalb) do not contest the district court's
holding that the statute is facially unconstitutional, nor that the DeKalb County schools engaged in
unconstitutional officially organized or sponsored religious activities. Therefore, we do not review the district
court's determinations of these issues.
Neither does DeKalb appeal that portion of the Permanent Injunction entered by the district court
which prohibits it from "aiding, abetting, commanding, counseling, inducing, ordering, or procuring ... school
organized or officially sanctioned religious activity in its schools including, but not limited to, vocal prayer,
Bible and devotional or scriptural readings, distribution of religious materials, texts, or announcements, and
discussions of a devotional or inspirational nature, in school or at school-related events, to include assemblies,
sporting events, and graduation ceremonies." Apparently, DeKalb concedes that, under Supreme Court
precedent, it may not prescribe prayer or allow state employees to lead, participate in or otherwise endorse
prayer of any type during curricular or extracurricular events.4 See Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577, 586, 112
S.Ct. 2649, 120 L.Ed.2d 467 (1992); County of Allegheny v. ACLU, 492 U.S. 573, 594, 109 S.Ct. 3086, 106
L.Ed.2d 472 (1989); Doe v. Duncanville Indep. Sch. Dist., 70 F.3d 402 (5th Cir.1995).
The Permanent Injunction, however, also prohibits DeKalb from "permitting" vocal prayer or other
devotional speech in its schools. While the injunction makes clear that it does not prohibit students from
voluntarily praying while at school or at school-related events, either individually or with each other, so long
as the prayer is purely private,5 it prohibits all prayer or other devotional speech in situations which are not
3
The Governor does not assert any other error by the district court. We do not decide whether the
district court erred in holding the statute facially unconstitutional for any reason not presented to us.
4
We do not, therefore, reach any of these issues.
5
The Permanent Injunction recites that nothing in it should be read to "affect the rights of
secondary-school students to engage in religious activity during noninstructional time that is consistent
3
purely private, such as aloud in the classroom, over the public address system, or as part of the program at
school-related assemblies and sporting events, or at a graduation ceremony. Furthermore, the prohibition
applies to bar not only school personnel from leading or participating in such public or vocal prayer or other
devotional speech or Bible reading, but also requires school officials to forbid students6 or other private
individuals from doing so while in school or at school-related events.
DeKalb does appeal this portion of the Permanent Injunction. It contends that the district court may
not constitutionally require it to forbid this speech, pointing out that the Supreme Court has made very clear
that "[p]rivate religious speech, far from being a First Amendment orphan, is as fully protected under the Free
Speech Clause as secular private expression." Capitol Square Review and Advisory Bd. v. Pinette, 515 U.S.
753, 760, 115 S.Ct. 2440, 132 L.Ed.2d 650 (1995).7 "There is a crucial difference between government
speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion,
which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect." Board of Educ. of Westside Community Schools
with the federal Equal Access Act, 20 U.S.C. Section 4071 et seq., or to quietly engage in religious
activity during noninstructional times." Permanent Injunction at 4.
6
We shall refer to all non-government, private parties collectively as "students."
7
The Departments of Justice and Education issued a statement of principles in the summer of 1995 "to
provide school officials with guidance [concerning] the extent to which religious expression and activities
are permitted in public schools." The first paragraph of the statement advises:
Student prayer and religious discussion: The Establishment clause of the First
Amendment does not prohibit purely private religious speech by students. Students
therefore have the same right to engage in individual or group prayer and religious
discussion during the school day as they do to engage in other comparable activity. For
example, students may read their Bibles or other scriptures, say grace before meals, and
pray before tests to the same extent they may engage in comparable non-disruptive
activities. Local school authorities possess substantial discretion to impose rules of order
and other pedagogical restrictions on student activities, but they may not structure or
administer such rules to discriminate against religious activity or speech.
News Release of U.S. Dep't of Educ., Aug. 17, 1995, at 3.
4
v. Mergens, 496 U.S. 226, 250, 110 S.Ct. 2356, 110 L.Ed.2d 191 (1990) (quoting Edwards v. Aguillard, 482
U.S. 578, 584, 107 S.Ct. 2573, 96 L.Ed.2d 510 (1987)) (emphasis in original).
Even the Chandlers agree that "[t]he Establishment Clause does not ban prayer. It bans state prayer."
(Plaintiffs' Reply Brief) (emphasis in original). They contend, however, that student-initiated religious speech
in the public schools is state prayer, and, therefore, DeKalb may not permit it.
Our review of the Permanent Injunction, then, is limited to the issue of whether the district court may
constitutionally enjoin DeKalb from permitting student-initiated religious speech in its schools.8 For the
following reasons, we hold the court may not. We vacate the Permanent Injunction and remand for further
proceedings.
II.
The district court's opinion holds that the Constitution requires it to prohibit public religious speech
in schools because the Establishment Clause is violated if government permits religious speech—even if
initiated by students—in schools or at school-related events. DeKalb contends that this conclusion is wrong
for two reasons. First, students are not state actors and, therefore, by definition, their actions cannot tend to
"establish" religion in violation of the Establishment Clause. Second, the Free Speech and Free Exercise
Clauses of the First Amendment require the State to tolerate genuinely student-initiated religious speech in
schools.
Students as State Actors and the Establishment Clause
The Establishment Clause prohibits Congress—or any other governmental body—from acting in such
a way as to establish a religion. Everson, 330 U.S. at 8, 67 S.Ct. 504. DeKalb argues that because students
are not state actors—Congress or a governmental body—their religious speech cannot, by definition, tend
to establish a religion.
8
DeKalb also appeals the district court's decision to appoint a monitor to enforce its injunction which
we discuss below.
5
It is true that ordinarily religious speech by private parties cannot establish religion, even if it occurs
in a public institution, such as a school. Mergens, 496 U.S. at 250, 110 S.Ct. 2356. On the other hand, it is
clear that private parties' religious speech can violate the Establishment Clause if the State uses such parties
as surrogates to accomplish what the State may not do. For example, if a school board may not
constitutionally write and require students to recite a prayer, as it most assuredly may not, Engel v. Vitale,
370 U.S. 421, 82 S.Ct. 1261, 8 L.Ed.2d 601 (1962), the school board may not avoid this prohibition by
delegating this function to others. Lee, 505 U.S. at 577, 112 S.Ct. 2649 (invalidating school board policy
permitting clergy to give prayers at graduation); Karen B. v. Treen, 653 F.2d 897 (5th Cir.1981)
(invalidating school board guidelines which required student or teacher-led prayers in classrooms). Nor may
the State establish a policy which "permits" private parties to speak, but then limits their speech to prayer or
other devotional speech. Ingebretsen v. Jackson Pub. Sch. Dist., 88 F.3d 274, 277 (5th Cir.1996) (authorizing
invocations, benedictions and prayers ); ACLU v. Black Horse Pike Reg'l Bd. of Educ., 84 F.3d 1471 (3d
Cir.1996) (school board policy permitted students to vote to have prayer at graduation); Harris v. Joint Sch.
Dist., 41 F.3d 447 (9th Cir.1994), vacated as moot, 515 U.S. 1155, 115 S.Ct. 2604, 132 L.Ed.2d 849 (1995)
(school policy permitted student to lead prayer ); Jager v. Douglas County Sch. Dist., 862 F.2d 824 (11th
Cir.1989) (authorizing student-led invocations and only invocations at school sporting events); Hall v. Board
of Sch. Comm'rs, 656 F.2d 999 (5th Cir.1981) (school policy permitted devotionals, and only devotionals);
Collins v. Chandler Unified Sch. Dist., 644 F.2d 759, 760-61 (9th Cir.1981) (authorizing invocations,
benedictions, and prayers only).
When the State commands religious speech, it steps over the Constitution to establish religion. In
each of these cases, it is the State's decision to create an exclusively religious medium which violates the
Establishment Clause; not the private parties' religious speech. It is not the "permitting" of religious speech
which dooms these policies, but rather the requirement that the speech be religious, i.e., invocations,
benedictions, or prayers.
6
This was the holding of the original school prayer case, Engel v. Vitale, in which the Court observed:
The Petitioners contend among other things that the state laws requiring or permitting use of the
Regents' prayer must be struck down as a violation of the Establishment Clause because that prayer
was composed by governmental officials as a part of a governmental program to further religious
beliefs. For this reason, petitioners argue, the State's use of the Regents' prayer in its public school
system breaches the constitutional wall of separation between Church and State. We agree with that
contention since we think that the constitutional prohibition against laws respecting an establishment
of religion must at least mean that in this country it is no part of the business of government to
compose official prayers for any group of the American people to recite as a part of a religious
program carried on by government.
370 U.S. at 425, 82 S.Ct. 1261 (emphasis supplied). The Court held, therefore, that "government in this
country, be it state or federal, is without power to prescribe by law any particular form of prayer which is
to be used as an official prayer in carrying on any program of governmentally sponsored religious activity."
Id. (emphasis supplied). This is all it held.
Some lower courts have extended Engel to require government to prohibit any public expression of
religious belief in schools. Support for this holding is said to be located in the Court's observation that the
denominational neutrality of the prayer did not "free it from the limitations of the Establishment Clause." Id.
at 430, 82 S.Ct. 1261. These courts interpreted this to mean that no religious speech could be tolerated in the
public schools because the Establishment Clause forbade it.
This is not what the Court said, however. The denominational neutrality of the Regent's prayer could
not "free it from the limitations of the Establishment Clause" because the prayer was "commanded" by the
State. It really did not matter what the prayer said; no prayer commanded by the State can survive scrutiny
under the Establishment Clause.
The Court specifically cautioned that "nothing could be more wrong" than to interpret Engel to
require "a hostility toward religion or toward prayer." Id. at 434, 82 S.Ct. 1261 (emphasis supplied). On the
contrary, "[t]he history of man is inseparable from the history of religion." The First Amendment, "which
tried to put an end to governmental control of religion and of prayer, was not written to destroy either." Id.
at 435, 82 S.Ct. 1261. Rather, it protects freedom of religious expression by forbidding government from
7
requiring us to "speak only the religious thoughts that government want[s][us] to speak and to pray only to
the God that government want[s][us] to pray to." Id. The Court summarized its holding in Engel in the
following way:
It is neither sacrilegious nor antireligious to say that each separate government in this country should
stay out of the business of writing or sanctioning official prayers and leave that purely religious
function to the people themselves and to those the people choose to look to for religious guidance.
Id. (emphasis supplied). Thus, Engel merely made clear that the Establishment Clause prohibits the
government from commanding prayer and prescribing its form.9
But DeKalb does not claim otherwise. DeKalb contends only that nothing in the First Amendment,
nor in any of the Supreme Court's interpretations of it, requires it to prohibit the religious speech of private
parties—such as students—if that speech is genuinely privately-initiated, i.e., not commanded by a school
board or state law. On the contrary, DeKalb argues, the First Amendment positively requires that it tolerate
students' religious speech to the same extent that it permits students' secular speech.
The Chandlers, on the other hand, contend that when the State permits students to speak religiously
in situations that are not purely private,10 the State lends its imprimatur to the speech, thereby endorsing and
advancing religion in violation of the "obligation of the public schools to provide a religiously neutral
environment." They also argue that all public religious speech in schools is unconstitutionally coercive of
some students because of "peer pressure." Consequently, schools must forbid all public religious speech in
school, including genuinely student-initiated religious speech.
Student Speech and the Free Exercise and Free Speech Clauses
This, then, is the question DeKalb asks us to answer. Do school officials have "the ability (and duty)
to impose content restrictions on purportedly 'private' speakers at school events," in order to achieve neutrality
9
The opt-out provision of the school board's policy was constitutionally insignificant in the context of
"governmentally composed prayers for religious services" in schools. 370 U.S. at 425, 82 S.Ct. 1261.
10
The Permanent Injunction, for example, permits students to "quietly engage in religious activity
during noninstructional times, so long as it does not unduly call attention thereto."
8
with respect to religion as the Chandlers contend (Chandlers' Brief at 27); or do the Free Exercise and Free
Speech Clauses require that school officials permit student religious speech at the same time, and in the same
place and manner as secular speech, as DeKalb contends? Under the Chandlers' theory, student religious
speech is attributable to the State thereby violating the constitutional requirement of neutrality. Students,
therefore, cannot be permitted to speak freely in school if religion is the topic; the State has a positive duty
to censor student speech if it is religious.
We disagree. The suppression of student-initiated religious speech is neither necessary to, nor does
it achieve, constitutional neutrality towards religion. For that reason, the Constitution does not permit its
suppression.
It is true that government must be neutral with respect to religion. But it is equally true, as Justice
Goldberg warned, that an:
untutored devotion to the concept of neutrality can lead to invocation or approval of results which
partake not simply of that noninterference and noninvolvement with the religious which the
Constitution commands, but of a brooding and pervasive dedication to the secular and a passive, or
even active, hostility to the religious. Such results are not only not compelled by the Constitution,
but, it seems to me, are prohibited by it.
School Dist. of Abington Township v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203, 306, 83 S.Ct. 1560, 10 L.Ed.2d 844 (1963)
(Goldberg, J. concurring).
The discriminatory suppression of student-initiated religious speech demonstrates not neutrality but
hostility toward religion because the:
exclusion of religious ideas, symbols, and voices marginalizes religion.... Silence about a subject
conveys a powerful message. When the public sphere is open to ideas and symbols representing
nonreligious viewpoints, culture, and ideological commitment, to exclude all those whose basis is
"religious" would profoundly distort public culture.
Michael W. McConnell, Religious Freedom at a Crossroads, 59 U. Chi. L.Rev. 115, 189 (Winter 1992).
The prohibition of all religious speech in our public schools implies, therefore, an unconstitutional
disapproval of religion. If endorsement is unconstitutional because it "sends a message to nonadherents that
they are outsiders," disapproval is unconstitutional because it "sends the opposite message." Lynch, 465 U.S.
at 688, 104 S.Ct. 1355 (O'Connor, J., concurring). "What is crucial is that a government practice not have
the effect of communicating a message of government endorsement or disapproval of religion." Id. at 692,
9
104 S.Ct. 1355 (emphasis supplied). "Cleansing" our public schools of all religious expression, however,
inevitably results in the "establishment" of disbelief—atheism—as the State's religion. Since the Constitution
requires neutrality, it cannot be the case that government may prefer disbelief over religion.11
Permitting students to speak religiously signifies neither state approval nor disapproval of that speech.
The speech is not the State's—either by attribution or by adoption. The permission signifies no more than
that the State acknowledges its constitutional duty to tolerate religious expression. Only in this way is true
neutrality achieved.
Because genuinely student-initiated religious speech is private speech endorsing religion, it is fully
protected by both the Free Exercise and the Free Speech Clauses of the Constitution. See Mergens, 496 U.S.
at 250, 110 S.Ct. 2356; Jones v. Clear Creek Indep. Sch. Dist., 977 F.2d 963 (5th Cir.1992). "Students do
not shed their constitutional rights ... at the schoolhouse gate." Tinker v. Des Moines Indep. Community Sch.
Dist., 393 U.S. 503, 506, 89 S.Ct. 733, 21 L.Ed.2d 731 (1969). Religious speech by students does not become
forbidden "state action" the moment the students walk through the schoolhouse door.
Furthermore, the Supreme Court has made clear that permitting religious speech or symbols in our
public institutions does not automatically constitute an unconstitutional State endorsement of religion. In fact,
"[t]here is an unbroken history of official acknowledgment by all three branches of government of the role
of religion in American life from at least 1789." Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 674, 104 S.Ct. 1355, 79
L.Ed.2d 604 (1984). References to our religious heritage are found in the statutorily prescribed national
motto on our currency, "In God We Trust," 36 U.S.C. § 186, and in the language "one nation under God,"
which is part of the Pledge of Allegiance to our flag—recited by public school children every day. Congress
11
We believe that the First Amendment's requirement that government "tolerate" diverse political
views, including those that are totally antithetical to our constitutionally guaranteed republican form of
government, applies to require that government "tolerate" atheistic views without also requiring that we
eschew religion. Tolerance of disbelief does not require that we deny our religious heritage, nor elevate
atheism over that heritage. The First Amendment requires only that the State tolerate both, while
establishing neither. Americans, however, are free to prefer one or the other and to express that
preference wherever they are permitted to speak. This means, of course, that a student may choose to
express his atheistic views as well as his religious ones.
10
opens with a prayer, and, indeed, the Supreme Court, itself, hears oral argument in a chamber decorated with
a depiction of Moses and the Ten Commandments. We celebrate Thanksgiving and Christmas as national
holidays, and Congress has directed the President to proclaim a National Day of Prayer each year "on which
[day] the people of the United States may turn to God in prayer and meditation at churches, in groups, and
as individuals." 36 U.S.C. § 169h.
The Constitution does not require a complete separation of church and state such that religious
expression may not be tolerated in our public institutions.12 In fact, "it affirmatively mandates
accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any." Lynch, 465 U.S.
at 673, 104 S.Ct. 1355 (emphasis supplied). The Supreme Court has made clear that "[a]nything less would
require the 'callous indifference' we have said was never intended by the Establishment Clause," and "would
bring us into 'war with our national traditions as embodied in the First Amendment's guaranty of the free
exercise of religion.' " Id. (quoting McCollum v. Board of Education, 333 U.S. 203, 211-12, 68 S.Ct. 461,
92 L.Ed. 649 (1948)).
The examples cited above all "evidence [our] accommodation of all faiths and all forms of religious
expression, and hostility toward none. Through this accommodation ... governmental action has 'follow[ed]
the best of our traditions' and 'respect[ed] the religious nature of our people.' " Lynch, 465 U.S. at 677-78,
104 S.Ct. 1355 (quoting Zorach v. Clauson, 343 U.S. 306, 314, 72 S.Ct. 679, 96 L.Ed. 954 (1952)).
12
In fact, the Constitution probably does not require a "wall" at all. The phrase comes from a letter
written by Jefferson who was neither present when the First Amendment was passed, nor consulted about
its language. In a short note to the Danbury Baptist Association written fourteen years after the Bill of
Rights was passed, he made a passing reference to idea that the First Amendment "build[s] a wall of
separation between church and State." See Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U.S. 38, 92, 105 S.Ct. 2479, 86
L.Ed.2d 29 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting). In any event, the "wall" concept has been acknowledged by the
Court itself, with what Justice Rehnquist characterized as "embarrassing candor," as merely a "blurred,
indistinct, and variable barrier," which "is not wholly accurate" and can only be "dimly perceived." Id. at
107, 105 S.Ct. 2479 (quoting Lemon v. Kurtzman, 403 U.S. 602, 614, 91 S.Ct. 2105, 29 L.Ed.2d 745
(1971)).
11
Genuinely student initiated religious speech can also be accommodated without resulting in an
unconstitutional State endorsement of religion.
Furthermore, even if permitting student-initiated religious speech advances religion in some sense,
this does not mean the speech violates the Establishment Clause. Even State action may incidentally advance
religion without offending the Constitution. Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263, 102 S.Ct. 269, 70 L.Ed.2d 440
(1981). The Supreme Court has recognized that "our precedents plainly contemplate that on occasion some
advancement of religion will result from governmental action." Lynch, 465 U.S. at 683, 104 S.Ct. 1355. "Not
every law that confers an 'indirect,' 'remote,' or 'incidental' benefit upon [religion] is, for that reason alone,
constitutionally invalid." Id. (quoting Committee for Public Educ. & Religious Liberty v. Nyquist, 413 U.S.
756, 771, 93 S.Ct. 2955, 37 L.Ed.2d 948 (1973)). Student-initiated religious speech, therefore, even if it
incidentally advances religion, does not violate the Establishment Clause because it is private speech
endorsing religion which the First Amendment protects. See Clear Creek, 977 F.2d at 965.
Finally, the fact that student religious speech may fall on deaf ears does not make it unconstitutionally
coercive. Lee, 505 U.S. at 577, 112 S.Ct. 2649. In Lee, the Supreme Court was careful to point out that:
We do not hold that every state action implicating religion is invalid if one or a few citizens find it
offensive. People may take offense at all manner of religious as well as nonreligious messages, but
offense alone does not in every case show a violation. We know too that sometimes to endure social
isolation or even anger may be the price of conscience or nonconformity.
505 U.S. at 597, 112 S.Ct. 2649.13 Those who do not espouse a speaker's religious beliefs are free not to
listen, and to express their disagreement by not participating in any way.
Accommodation of religious beliefs we do not share is, however, a part of everyday life in this
country:
In so acting, we express respect for, but not endorsement of, the fundamental values of others. We
act without expressing a position on the theological merit of those values or of religious belief in
general, and no one perceives us to have taken such a position.
13
Of course, in this case we do not have state action. Private religious speech has even less potential
for coercion.
12
Lee, 505 U.S. at 628, 112 S.Ct. 2649 (Souter, J. concurring). Respect for the rights of others to express their
beliefs, both political and religious, is the price the Constitution extracts for our own liberty.14 This is a price
we freely pay. It is not coerced.15 Only when the speech is commanded by the State does it
unconstitutionally coerce the listener.16
Ultimately, the issue in this case is not whether school officials may prescribe prayer or enlist
surrogates to that end. They may not. Nor is the issue whether school officials may prohibit religious speech
in schools, or censor the content of that speech. They may not. The real issue is what sort of time, place, and
manner limits may be imposed upon genuinely student-initiated religious speech in schools? When may
students pray? Where may they pray? Under what circumstances may they pray?
In answering these questions, we must fulfill the constitutional requirement of permitting students
freely to express their religious beliefs without allowing the machinery of government—the school—to be
used to command prayer. This requires that we resolve the tension between the right to pray and the right
to be free from government-mandated prayer. This is not an easy task. It would be easy simply to banish
14
Justice Scalia observed in Lee that "We indeed live in a vulgar age. But surely 'our social
conventions,' have not coarsened to the point that anyone who does not stand on his chair and shout
obscenities can reasonably be deemed to have assented to everything said in his presence.... I may add,
moreover, that maintaining respect for the religious observances of others is a fundamental civic virtue
that government (including the public schools) can and should cultivate—so that even if it were the case
that the displaying of such respect might be mistaken for taking part in the prayer, I would deny that the
dissenter's interest in avoiding even the false appearance of participation constitutionally trumps the
government's interest in fostering respect for religion generally." 505 U.S. at 637-38, 112 S.Ct. 2649
(Scalia, J. dissenting).
15
Justice Souter acknowledged this in Lee: "If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers
according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually
chosen to deliver a religious message, it would have been harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to
the State. But that is not our case." 505 U.S. at 630 n. 8, 112 S.Ct. 2649.
16
The "indirect coercion" identified in Lee by the plurality opinion was exerted over the audience by
the State 's command that there be religious speech at graduation. 505 U.S. at 592-93, 112 S.Ct. 2649.
Justice Kennedy's concern that "in the hands of government what might begin as a tolerant expression of
religious views may end in a policy to indoctrinate and coerce," id. at 591-92, 112 S.Ct. 2649 (emphasis
supplied), does not apply to the case of student-initiated religious speech.
13
prayer from our public institutions, but this would be not only constitutionally incorrect, but also
fundamentally unfair to our society.
III.
How, then, does a school accommodate religious expression without commanding it? DeKalb argues
that the answer is simple—it is to be "permitted." Not required. Not commanded. Not even suggested.
Simply, permitted. If students, or other private parties, wish to speak religiously while in school or at
school-related events, they may exercise their First Amendment right to do so.
The first principle must always be that genuinely student-initiated religious speech must be permitted.
A student's individual decision to pray or otherwise speak religiously is not the State's command. Clear
Creek, 977 F.2d at 965.17 Such speech is fully protected. Id. See also Mergens, 496 U.S. at 252, 110 S.Ct.
2356.
On the other hand, even genuinely student-initiated religious speech may constitute state action if
the State participates in or supervises the speech. See Duncanville, 70 F.3d at 406-07.18 Religious speech
in school by teachers, for example, is especially troublesome because "a teacher's [religious] speech can be
17
The Ninth Circuit also upheld a policy that permitted the top four students to speak on any topic of
their choosing without state approval in Doe v. Madison Sch. Dist., 147 F.3d 832 (9th Cir.1998), but the
court en banc ordered the district court to dismiss the complaint for lack of standing and mootness. No.
97-35642 (9th Cir. May 19, 1999).
18
While many subsequent courts have cited Duncanville for the proposition that student initiated
speech at school-related sporting events is un constitutional, the Fifth Circuit specifically held that,
"[s]tudents may voluntarily pray together, provided such prayer is not done with school participation or
supervision." 70 F.3d at 405 (emphasis supplied). Judge Jones, in her separate concurrence and dissent,
pointed out that:
This decision ... does not prevent students from exercising their constitutional rights of
free speech, association and free exercise by praying at appropriate times and in an
appropriate manner during athletic practices or games. Further, we must abide by the
Supreme Court's decisions ... that prevent active school leadership, encouragement or
promotion of the prayers. The only questions here are how teachers may respond to
student-initiated prayers and to what extent the school may "supervise" the prayers.
70 F.3d at 409.
14
taken as directly and deliberately representative of the school." Bishop v. Aronov, 926 F.2d 1066, 1073 (11th
Cir.1991). Teacher participation in student-initiated prayer "improperly entangles the State in religion and
signals an unconstitutional endorsement of religion." Duncanville, 70 F.3d at 406. In upholding the Equal
Access Act, which provides that schools must afford religious groups the same access to school facilities as
secular groups enjoy, the Supreme Court relied in part on the act's express prohibition on teacher participation
which "avoids the problems of the 'students' emulation of teachers as role models.' " Mergens, 496 U.S. at
251, 110 S.Ct. 2356 (quoting Edwards, 482 U.S. at 584, 107 S.Ct. 2573). Therefore, student religious speech
must be without oversight, without supervision,19 subject only to the same reasonable time, place, and manner
restrictions as all other student speech in school.
Because religious speech is protected speech, government may not censor its content. Lamb's
Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free Sch. Dist., 508 U.S. 384, 394, 113 S.Ct. 2141, 124 L.Ed.2d 352
(1993) (quoting Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Educ. Fund, Inc., 473 U.S. 788, 806, 105 S.Ct. 3439,
87 L.Ed.2d 567 (1985)) (the government violates the First Amendment when it denies access to a speaker
solely to suppress the point of view he espouses). Suppression of religious speech constitutes viewpoint
discrimination, the most egregious form of content-based censorship. Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of
19
What constitutes "supervision?" As Judge Jones wrote in Duncanville:
At a broad level, everything that goes on during practice or competition, including
student-initiated locker-room or basketball court prayer, is subject to the coaches'
"supervision." To outlaw supervision on this level would be to outlaw the otherwise
constitutional student-led prayers.... It must be, then, that the injunction pertains only to
active supervision and is thus redundant of the cautions that the school may not promote,
encourage or lead prayers.
70 F.3d at 410.
Supervision cannot mean, therefore, mere presence. Support for this view is found in
Mergens in which the Supreme Court found no constitutional infirmity with the provision of the
EAA which permits school employees to be present for custodial purposes at religious meetings
held on school property. 496 U.S. at 236, 110 S.Ct. 2356. We agree with Judge Jones that, for
supervision to amount to unconstitutional endorsement, it must cross the line into active
endorsement, encouragement or participation.
15
Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 831, 115 S.Ct. 2510, 132 L.Ed.2d 700 (1995). Government may not, therefore,
censor religion from the content of students' protected speech at school. Cornelius, 473 U.S. at 806, 105 S.Ct.
3439 ("Control over access to a nonpublic forum can be based on subject matter and speaker identity so long
as the distinctions drawn are reasonable in light of the purpose served by the forum and are viewpoint
neutral.") (emphasis supplied); Perry Educ. Ass'n v. Perry Local Educators' Ass'n, 460 U.S. 37, 46, 103 S.Ct.
948, 74 L.Ed.2d 794 (1983) (A "state may reserve the [nonpublic] forum for its intended purposes ... as long
as the regulation on speech is reasonable and not an effort to suppress expression merely because public
officials oppose the speaker's view.")
A student's right to speak religiously is not, however, without limit. The school may impose the
same reasonable restrictions on the time, place, and manner of religious speech as it does on secular student
speech. Furthermore, a student's right to express his personal religious beliefs does not extend to using the
machinery of the state as a vehicle for converting his audience. See Abington, 374 U.S. at 228, 83 S.Ct. 1560.
The Constitution requires that schools permit religious expression, not religious proselytizing. "The principle
that government may accommodate the free exercise of religion does not supersede the fundamental
limitations imposed by the Establishment Clause." Lee, 505 U.S. at 587, 112 S.Ct. 2649. Proselytizing
speech is inherently coercive and, the Constitution prohibits it from the government's pulpit. Id.
IV.
The Permanent Injunction enjoins DeKalb from "aiding, abetting, commanding, counseling,
inducing, ordering, or procuring" school organized or officially sanctioned religious activity. DeKalb does
not appeal this prohibition. The record in this case reveals, however, that there were many sincere, but
unconstitutional efforts by school personnel to do just what the injunction prohibits—to endorse, encourage,
or participate in student religious activity. For this reason, the appointment of a monitor by the district court
was not an abuse of discretion. See Local 28 of the Sheet Metal Workers' Int'l v. EEOC, 478 U.S. 421, 481-
16
82, 106 S.Ct. 3019, 92 L.Ed.2d 344 (1986). The monitor's task is to be vigilant in guarding against the
repetition of this unconstitutional activity by the schools.
The Permanent Injunction also forbids DeKalb from "permitting" students to speak religiously. This
it cannot constitutionally do. So long as school personnel do not participate in or actively supervise
student-initiated speech, DeKalb cannot constitutionally prohibit students from speaking religiously and the
Permanent Injunction cannot require it to.
We do not undertake to re-write the Permanent Injunction. The district court is in the best position
to do that. We note only that the Permanent Injunction may neither prohibit genuinely student-initiated
religious speech, nor apply restrictions on the time, place, and manner of that speech which exceed those
placed on students' secular speech.20
Accordingly, the Judgment of the district court is AFFIRMED as to the Governor's appeal. As to the
remaining defendants' appeals, the Permanent Injunction is VACATED and the case is REMANDED for
further proceedings not inconsistent with this opinion.
TJOFLAT, Circuit Judge, specially concurring:
I agree wholeheartedly with the majority's analysis in this case. I write separately, however, to
emphasize a more fundamental error made by the district court. I believe that many provisions of the
injunction entered by the district court were entered in violation of basic principles of equity jurisprudence
and constitutional law—namely, the principle that equity will not intervene where there is an adequate
remedy at law and the constitutional principle of separation of powers. These principles, for reasons that will
be explained hereafter, lead to the conclusion that a court should not enter an injunction that cannot be
20
This includes restrictions on announcements permitted in the schools' commencement programs, and
the distribution of religious literature.
17
enforced through coercive contempt sanctions. Some of the injunctive provisions at issue here cannot be so
enforced, and therefore must be vacated.1
In part I of this concurrence, after recognizing that injunctions are enforced through contempt
sanctions, I discuss the types of contempt sanctions generally available to a judge. I then explain that the
types of contempt sanctions available to address a violation of a particular injunction depend on the nature
of the injunction; not all types of sanctions are available for all injunctions. Finally, I explain why, based
on equitable and constitutional considerations, an injunction should be entered as a form of relief for a party
to a lawsuit only when one type of contempt sanction—coercive—is potentially available for violations. Part
II then applies this rule to the facts of this case.
I.
Injunctions are enforced through contempt sanctions. See 18 U.S.C. § 401(3) (1994). When it comes
to a judge's attention that an individual may not be in compliance with an injunction he has entered, he holds
a "show cause" hearing at which the allegedly noncomplying individual is asked to show cause why he is
disobeying the injunction. If the individual is in fact disobeying the injunction, and he is unable to provide
an acceptable excuse for doing so, then he is subject to the contempt powers of the court.2 In this part, I
discuss the types of contempt sanctions available to a court, and then discuss how this should impact the
court's decision whether to grant injunctive relief in the first instance.
A.
Contempt sanctions take one of three forms: punitive, compensatory, or coercive. Punitive sanctions
punish the contemnor for his conduct, and are imposed for the purpose of vindicating the authority of the
1
The issues I discuss herein were properly not relied upon by the majority opinion for the simple
reason that they were not raised by the appellants either in the district court or on appeal. They are,
however, sufficiently important to our system of jurisprudence that I feel it is appropriate—indeed
necessary—to address them sua sponte in this concurrence.
2
This procedure is laid out in more detail in Wyatt v. Rogers, 92 F.3d 1074, 1078 n. 8 (11th Cir.1996).
18
court. See Gompers v. Buck's Stove & Range Co., 221 U.S. 418, 441, 31 S.Ct. 492, 498, 55 L.Ed. 797
(1911).3 For instance, if an individual is served with a subpoena duces tecum but refuses to produce the
requested documents, and the court subsequently holds him in contempt and imposes a flat fine of $50
(payable to the court) for his contempt, the contempt sanction is properly classified as punitive. See Penfield
Co. of Cal. v. SEC, 330 U.S. 585, 592-93, 67 S.Ct. 918, 922, 91 L.Ed. 1117 (1947). In such a situation, the
opposing party is provided no relief, because it gets neither the requested documents nor the proceeds from
the fine. Furthermore, the contemnor has no way to purge the contempt (in other words, avoid the fine); if
he produced the requested documents five minutes after the court's decision, he would still be required to pay
$50. The sanction in such a case is intended to punish the contemnor for his contempt, thereby vindicating
the court's authority and thus deterring the contemnor and others from violating subsequent judicial orders
(issued by the same or any other court). Punitive sanctions are criminal in nature and therefore many of the
constitutional protections available in criminal proceedings—including the presumption of innocence, the
privilege against self-incrimination, the right to counsel, and the right to a jury trial in serious cases—must
be provided to the alleged contemnor before such sanctions can be imposed. See Young v. United States ex
rel. Vuitton et Fils S.A., 481 U.S. 787, 798-99, 107 S.Ct. 2124, 2133, 95 L.Ed.2d 740 (1987).4
The second form of contempt sanction is compensatory. Compensatory sanctions are civil in nature
and compensate the plaintiff for the damage caused by the contemnor's contempt. See United States v. United
3
The principles set forth in Gompers have been recently reaffirmed in International Union, United
Mine Workers of America v. Bagwell, 512 U.S. 821, 826-29, 114 S.Ct. 2552, 2556-58, 129 L.Ed.2d 642
(1994).
4
As stated in Young:
[D]efendants in criminal contempt proceedings must be presumed innocent, proved guilty
beyond a reasonable doubt, and accorded the right to refuse to testify against themselves;
must be advised of charges, have a reasonable opportunity to respond to them, and be
permitted the assistance of counsel and the right to call witnesses; must be given a public
trial before an unbiased judge; and must be afforded a jury trial for serious contempts.
Young, 481 U.S. at 798-99, 107 S.Ct. at 2133 (citations omitted).
19
Mine Workers of Am., 330 U.S. 258, 303-04, 67 S.Ct. 677, 701, 91 L.Ed. 884 (1947). The contempt sanction
in the well-known case of Jones v. Clinton, 36 F.Supp.2d 1118 (E.D.Ark.1999), falls into this category. In
that case, the court, having found that the defendant gave false deposition testimony, held the defendant in
contempt. The punishment for the contempt was a payment to the plaintiff of the expenses (including
attorney's fees) caused by the false testimony. See id. at 1134-35. Compensatory sanctions, unlike punitive
sanctions, provide a direct benefit to the plaintiff. Like punitive sanctions, however, the contemnor is unable
to purge his contempt: Were President Clinton now to amend his deposition answers to make them
completely accurate, the contempt sanctions would nevertheless remain in force.
The third form of contempt sanction is coercive. Coercive sanctions are also civil in nature, and are
intended to coerce the contemnor into doing an act that he is already required to do, but refuses to perform.
See Gompers, 221 U.S. at 441-42, 31 S.Ct. at 498. Thus, to use the previously cited example from Penfield,
if the district court had ordered the recipient of the subpoena duces tecum to pay a fine of $50 per day for
every day the recipient failed to produce the requested documents, such a sanction would be coercive.5
Coercive sanctions benefit the plaintiff by pressuring the defendant into performing an action that the plaintiff
desires to have performed. See id. at 442, 31 S.Ct. 492, 31 S.Ct. at 498. They also give the contemnor the
opportunity to purge his contempt: The punishment continues only as long as the contemnor refuses to
comply with the relevant court order. Hence, in regard to coercive sanctions, it is often said that a contemnor
carries the key to his prison in his own pocket. See, e.g., Blalock v. United States, 844 F.2d 1546, 1559 (11th
Cir.1988) (Tjoflat, J., specially concurring) (quoting In re Nevitt, 117 F. 448, 461 (8th Cir.1902)).
The lines separating each type of sanction from the others are not always clear. Consider a situation
in which a court imposes a $150 contempt sanction on a party, payable to the adverse party but in no way
correlated to the harm suffered by that party. The fact that the sanction is payable to the adverse party (and
5
The fine would presumably be paid to the court, although in theory it could be paid to the opposing
party. Regardless of who received the money, because the clear purpose of the fine would be to pressure
the contemnor into compliance, the fine would be classified as coercive.
20
not the court) makes the sanction appear compensatory, but the fact that the amount of the sanction is
unrelated to the harm suffered by the adverse party leads to the conclusion that the sanction is in fact punitive.
Cf. Thyssen, Inc. v. S/S Chuen On, 693 F.2d 1171, 1173-74 (5th Cir.1982). Furthermore, every contempt
sanction serves to some degree to vindicate the authority of the court (and thus is somewhat punitive) and to
dissuade the contemnor from repeating his misbehavior (and thus is somewhat coercive). See Gompers, 221
U.S. at 443, 31 S.Ct. at 498. One might argue that this fact renders meaningless the distinctions among the
types of contempt sanctions—for instance, because all contempt sanctions are somewhat punitive, it makes
no sense to distinguish punitive contempt sanctions from the other two types of contempt sanctions. This,
however, is the equivalent of arguing that because all men have facial hair, it makes no sense to distinguish
between bearded and non-bearded men. In both cases, the question is one of degree, and the fact that there
will be difficult cases at the margins does not deprive the conceptual categories of their significance. Instead,
difficult cases merely require a detailed "examination of the character of" the sanction being imposed in order
to determine whether it is punitive, compensatory, or coercive. Hicks v. Feiock, 485 U.S. 624, 636, 108 S.Ct.
1423, 1432, 99 L.Ed.2d 721 (1988).
B.
The types of sanctions—punitive, compensatory, or coercive—that can be used to enforce an
injunction depend on the character of the conduct being enjoined. Consider first an injunction that commands
the performance of a specific act. For instance, imagine a case in which the defendant operates a paper mill
that is discharging pollutants onto the plaintiff's land. The plaintiff brings a lawsuit alleging a nuisance, and
seeks an injunction ordering the defendant to shut down the mill. The plaintiff succeeds and the injunction
is granted. The defendant, however, continues to operate the paper mill. The court, after conducting a show
cause hearing and finding the defendant in contempt, could use any of the types of sanction previously
discussed: a punitive sanction (such as a flat fine of $10,000), a compensatory sanction (such as a fine of
21
$5,000, which is roughly equal to the harm caused, payable to the plaintiff), or a coercive sanction (such as
a fine of $100 per day until the paper mill is shut down).
Next, consider an injunction that forbids the performance of a specific act. For instance, imagine a
case in which an employee alleges that her corporate employer, through the actions of its CEO (who is also
the majority shareholder), has, on a number of occasions, touched her in inappropriate areas. The employee
claims that this behavior constitutes sexual harassment, in violation of 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a)(1) (1994).6
She files a lawsuit against her employer, seeking an injunction ordering the employer to cease the
harassment.7 She succeeds, and the injunction is granted. Nevertheless, the CEO continues the inappropriate
touching. The court, after conducting a show cause hearing and finding the employer in contempt, can assess
punitive sanctions (such as a flat fine of $10,000, payable to the court) or compensatory sanctions (such as
a fine equal to the harm caused, payable to the employee). Coercive sanctions, however, are not available,
because the act to be prevented by the injunction has already occurred—in other words, there is no way to
purge the contempt.8 See Gompers, 221 U.S. at 442, 31 S.Ct. at 498 ("[I]f the defendant does that which he
has been commanded not to do, the disobedience is a thing accomplished. [Contempt sanctions] cannot undo
or remedy what has been done....").
6
The employee's claim would be that the CEO had created an "abusive work environment," as opposed
to a claim of quid pro quo sexual harassment. See generally Harris v. Forklift Systems, Inc., 510 U.S. 17,
114 S.Ct. 367, 126 L.Ed.2d 295 (1993) (discussing "abusive work environment" claims).
7
Injunctions of this sort actually amount to nothing more than injunctions to "obey the law," which, for
reasons different from those outlined here, have repeatedly been held invalid. See, e.g., Payne v.
Travenol Labs., Inc., 565 F.2d 895, 897-98 (5th Cir.1978) (holding that injunctions to "obey the law"
violate the requirements of Fed.R.Civ.P. 65(d) that an injunction "be specific" and "describe in reasonable
detail ... the act or acts sought to be restrained"). (In Bonner v. City of Prichard, 661 F.2d 1206, 1209
(11th Cir.1981) (en banc), this court adopted as binding precedent all decisions of the former Fifth Circuit
handed down prior to October 1, 1981.)
8
The situation might be different depending on the nature of the harassment. For instance, if the
harassment consisted in part of the placement of pornographic pictures throughout the office, the
employee could seek an injunction ordering that the pictures be removed. If the injunction was granted, it
could be enforced through coercive sanctions—for instance, a fine of $200 per day until the pictures were
removed.
22
To make the point clearer, try to imagine a court attempting to enter coercive sanctions in the
situation outlined above. The court has enjoined the employer not to harass the employee. The employer
nevertheless does so, and, after a show cause hearing, is held in contempt. The court fines the employer $100
per day until ... well, until what? Presumably, until the court is persuaded that the harassing CEO will not
repeat his misbehavior. Thus, after three days of fines, the CEO contacts the judge and promises that he will
never again sexually harass the employee. The court thinks the CEO was shifting his eyes a bit much when
he made the promise, however, and therefore allows the fines to continue accumulating. After a week of
fines, the CEO makes the same promise, but this time on his knees and with his hands clearly visible so that
the court can see that the CEO's fingers are not crossed. The court is still unpersuaded, and continues
allowing the fines to accrue. This exercise would presumably continue until such time as the court, for
whatever reason, decided that the CEO had learned his lesson.9 Even then, the contempt would not have been
purged, because the harassment would already have been fully accomplished. The point is simply that when
an injunction forbids the performance of an act, coercive sanctions are not available to enforce the injunction.
Note that it is not the affirmative or negative phrasing of the injunction that is critical. An injunction
commanding the performance of specific act (for instance, "shut down the paper mill") could, in many cases,
just as easily be phrased as an injunction prohibiting a ongoing harm (for instance, "do not operate the paper
mill"). Likewise, an injunction forbidding the performance of a specific act (for instance, "do not sexually
harass the employee") could, in many cases, be phrased as an injunction commanding the performance of an
ongoing duty (for instance, "treat male and female employees equally"). Cf. International Union, United
Mine Workers of Am. v. Bagwell, 512 U.S. 821, 835, 114 S.Ct. 2552, 2561, 129 L.Ed.2d 642 (1994)
(suggesting that an injunction directed at a union stating, "Do not strike," is essentially the same as one
stating, "Continue working"). Rather, it is the underlying nature of the injunction—specifically, whether it
9
In contrast, where the contemnor is enjoined to perform a specific act, promises of future compliance
are neither necessary nor relevant—the contemnor can avoid sanctions by (and only by) performing the
commanded act.
23
is commanding an act that the law requires or proscribing an act that the law forbids—that determines
whether it can be enforced through coercive sanctions.
In sum, if an injunction commands the performance of a specific act (such as shutting down a paper
mill), then all three types of sanctions are available to the court. If, however, an injunction forbids the
performance of an act (such as sexually harassing an employee), then only punitive and compensatory
sanctions are available to the court.
C.
The types of contempt sanctions available for violation of an injunction determine the effectiveness
of the injunctive relief being given to the plaintiff. Specifically, as I discuss in this section, injunctions that
are enforceable only through punitive and compensatory sanctions provide relief to a plaintiff that is—at
best—duplicative of the relief available through an action for damages.10 Only injunctions enforceable
through coercive sanctions provide a form of relief that is unique to equity. They are therefore the only type
of injunctions that courts should enter, on the basis of the rule that injunctions should not be granted where
the plaintiff has an adequate remedy at law. See Weaver v. Florida Power & Light Co., 172 F.3d 771, 773
(11th Cir.1999).
Punitive sanctions provide essentially no relief to the plaintiff—as discussed above, the purpose of
punitive sanctions is to vindicate the court's authority, not to benefit a party to a lawsuit. Any benefit to the
plaintiff from such a sanction is incidental and indirect. For instance, in the sexual harassment hypothetical
in part I.B, supra, assume that the court chose to impose a punitive sanction—such as a fine of $10,000
against the employer, payable to the court. This fine would do nothing to affect the harassment that had
already occurred; at this point, the harassment is a "done deal" and the court cannot undo it. In addition, the
fine would do nothing to compensate the plaintiff for the harm caused by the harassment. The only benefit
10
This is not to say that punitive and compensatory sanctions should never be used to enforce
injunctions. Some examples of their proper use will be discussed in part I.E, infra.
24
provided to the plaintiff from the fine would be a deterrent: Because of the imposition of the fine, the
employer might be less inclined to harass the plaintiff in the future. This deterrent, however, is equally
available to the plaintiff through an action for damages: If, instead of seeking an injunction and then calling
for a show cause hearing at which the employer was assessed punitive sanctions, the plaintiff had simply
brought a damages action after the harassment occurred, the employer would be equally deterred.
(Furthermore, the plaintiff would receive compensation for the harm caused, unlike in the injunction
scenario.) In sum, every benefit that the plaintiff gets from an injunction enforced by punitive sanctions
would be equally available in an action for damages.
Compensatory sanctions merely imitate the relief that would be provided in a damages action. For
instance, returning to the sexual harassment example, assume that the court chose to impose a compensatory
sanction on the employer. The court, after hearing argument from both parties, determined that the damage
to the plaintiff from the harassment was roughly $5,000, and ordered the employer to pay that amount to the
plaintiff. The fine does not affect the prior harassment (it is again a "done deal"), but compensates the
plaintiff for the harm she has suffered. In this situation, the relief provided to the plaintiff imitates that which
would be provided in a damages action—in terms of both compensation to the plaintiff and as a future
deterrent to the employer. Again, as with punitive sanctions, every benefit that the plaintiff gets from an
injunction enforced by compensatory sanctions would be equally available from an action for damages.
Coercive sanctions, in contrast, provide meaningful and unique relief to the plaintiff. For instance,
using the paper mill hypothetical from part I.B, supra, assume that the court chose to impose a fine of $100
per day on the defendant until he shut down the paper mill. The defendant is now subject to an
ever-increasing pressure to take the action that the plaintiff seeks—a pressure that would not be available
through an ordinary damages action. There is of course still no guarantee that the defendant will shut down
the mill, but, because of the injunction, the plaintiff is able to exert greater pressure on the defendant to do
so than would be possible in the absence of the injunction.
25
These observations lead to the conclusion that where an injunction is enforceable only through
punitive or compensatory contempt sanctions,11 and not through coercive contempt sanctions, the injunctive
remedy being given to the plaintiff is no better than the remedy he could have obtained in an after-the-fact
action for damages. Therefore, the plaintiff necessarily has an adequate remedy at law—or at least a remedy
at law that is no less adequate than the injunctive remedy.12 Consequently, the principle that an injunction
will not be entered where the plaintiff has an adequate remedy at law forbids the entering of an injunction
under such circumstances.
D.
In addition to violating equitable principles, an injunction that is enforceable only through punitive
or compensatory sanctions may also violate the Constitution. Specifically, such an injunction has the
potential to run afoul of the constitutional doctrine of separation of powers.
11
As discussed in part I.B, supra, injunctions are enforceable only through punitive or compensatory
contempt sanctions when they forbid the performance of an act (or command the performance of an
ongoing duty).
12
An injunction enforceable only through punitive or compensatory sanctions does give a plaintiff one
benefit that a damages action cannot provide: an ex ante declaration of the rights of the parties. For
instance, consider a case in which the defendant is preparing to remove some trees from a plot of land.
The plaintiff, asserting that the land is his, seeks an injunction (based on the law of trespass) forbidding
the defendant from removing the trees. The plaintiff succeeds and the injunction is issued. The
defendant, having previously believed that the land was his, may now be persuaded to change his
behavior. Thus, although the injunction would not be enforceable through coercive contempt sanctions
(because it forbids the performance of an act), it would nevertheless have provided the plaintiff with
meaningful relief in the form of an ex ante declaration of rights. If, however, this is the only form of
relief being provided to the plaintiff, then the appropriate remedial vehicle is a declaratory judgment, not
an injunction. See 28 U.S.C. § 2201 (1994).
The distinction is not merely a formal one: Injunctions, unlike declaratory judgments,
implicate the court's contempt powers and thus subject the enjoined party to sanctions should he
disobey. Declaratory judgments therefore do not raise the same separation-of-powers concerns as
injunctions, as discussed in part I.D, infra.
26
An injunction forbidding the performance of a particular act must be based on a conclusion that the
act forbidden, if performed, would constitute a violation of the law. Otherwise, the court would be enjoining
the performance of a perfectly legal act, which the court is without authority to do.
If the law on which the injunction is based is legislatively created, then the legislature is likely also
to have created rules regarding the means by which the law should be enforced and the appropriate sanction
for a violation of the law. For instance, the harassing behavior of the hypothetical CEO in part I.B, supra,
is illegal as a result of Section 703 of Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a)(1)
(1994). The procedure for enforcing Title VII is set forth in 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-5 (1994). Under that section,
an employee alleging a Title VII violation must first file a charge with the Equal Employment Opportunity
Commission ("EEOC"). If the EEOC decides not to bring a civil action against the employer, it must notify
the aggrieved employee, who then has ninety days in which to bring a civil action on her own. See 42 U.S.C.
§ 2000e-5(f)(1). If the action is successful, the types of relief available to the employee are set forth in 42
U.S.C. § 2000e-5(g).13
Once the employee obtains an injunction that orders the employer to cease the harassment, however,
she can completely circumvent the procedure prescribed by Congress. No notice to the EEOC is necessary;
the employee need only request a show cause hearing from the court. If the employer is held in contempt,
the court can respond with compensatory or punitive sanctions. See supra part I.B. If the court imposes
compensatory sanctions, the limitations on relief found in 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-5(g) will be inapplicable.
13
Section 2000e-5(g) specifically authorizes injunctive relief for violations of Title VII. This provision
could conceivably be read as congressional authorization of injunctive relief regardless of whether the
plaintiff has an adequate remedy at law. The more reasonable reading of the provision is that it means
merely that injunctive relief is allowed when the traditional equitable requirements are met—including
the absence of an adequate remedy at law. See Sanchez v. Philip Morris Inc., 774 F.Supp. 626, 630-31
(W.D.Okla.1991) (denying an injunction in a Title VII case on the ground that the plaintiff's legal
remedies are adequate); cf. Hecht Co. v. Bowles, 321 U.S. 321, 329-30, 64 S.Ct. 587, 591-92, 88 L.Ed.
754 (1944) (holding, in regard to a similar provision in the Emergency Price Control Act, that the
traditional rules of equity still apply to the granting of injunctions). Even if I am mistaken in this view,
however, this means merely that Title VII is an exception to the general rule (much like securities law, see
infra note 18) and takes nothing away from the broader point being made in the text.
27
Furthermore, the employer will have no means of raising many of the defenses that would be available in an
ordinary civil action, such as laches. If the court imposes punitive sanctions, it will have effectively made
criminal conduct that Congress has not deemed criminal (in light of the absence of statutory criminal
punishments for violations of Title VII). Even if Congress had done so, the enforcement of the criminal law
would be a matter for the executive branch, not the judicial branch.14 Thus, regardless of whether the
injunction is enforced through compensatory or punitive sanctions, the court has intruded on the province of
the legislative and executive branches by altering the congressionally-created procedures and remedies for
sexual harassment.15
In sum, an injunction enforceable only through punitive or compensatory sanctions constitutes an
individualized criminal or civil law (respectively). This new law is duplicative of the existing law but with
a different enforcement mechanism—contempt proceedings—and thus creates an opportunity to use different
procedures and to impose different sanctions from those contemplated by the legislature under the
circumstances. Therefore, where the action being enjoined is a violation of statutory law, the entry of an
injunction implicates the constitutional doctrine of separation of powers. See Wilder v. Virginia Hosp. Ass'n,
496 U.S. 498, 508 n. 9, 110 S.Ct. 2510, 2517 n. 9, 110 L.Ed.2d 455 (1990) (noting that separation of powers
requires "that Congress rather than the courts controls the availability of remedies for violations of statutes");
cf. NLRB v. Express Pub. Co., 312 U.S. 426, 435, 61 S.Ct. 693, 699, 85 L.Ed. 930 (1941) (noting that, except
where a specific violation has been found, "Congress did not contemplate that the courts should, by contempt
proceedings, try alleged violations of the National Labor Relations Act").
E.
14
This is one of the reasons for the equitable principle that equity will not enjoin the commission of a
crime. See 11A Charles Alan Wright et al., Federal Practice and Procedure § 2942, at 70-71 (2d
ed.1995).
15
The court could avoid this problem only by conducting a contempt proceeding that, in every relevant
way, duplicated a criminal or civil trial.
28
In light of all I have just said, a few caveats are in order. First, I am not saying that punitive and
compensatory contempt sanctions are never appropriate means for enforcing an injunction. For instance, if
a party is enjoined to produce certain documents and then destroys those documents, coercive sanctions
would no longer be available. Under those circumstances, a punitive contempt sanction would be an
important means of vindicating the court's authority. The injunction nevertheless would have been
appropriately entered, because coercive sanctions were a viable option at the time the injunction was entered
and thus the injunction provided meaningful relief to the adverse party.
Second, a court may enter an injunction that is not enforceable through coercive contempt sanctions
when the court enters the injunction in aid of its jurisdiction. For instance, if a government official is
enjoined to perform a certain act, and another individual tries to prevent the official from performing the act,
the court could issue an injunction commanding the individual to cease his interference. Such an injunction
would be appropriate despite not being enforceable through coercive sanctions, because the injunction was
not entered as a form of relief for a party to a lawsuit, and thus there is no issue as to whether that party would
have an adequate remedy at law. Cf. 18 U.S.C. § 1509 (1994) (authorizing injunctive relief against persons
who forcefully interfere with the performance of duties under a court order, regardless of whether the conduct
enjoined is also independently criminal).
Finally, I am not denying the importance of the injunction in modern jurisprudence. The principles
outlined above would have permitted, for instance, the use of the injunction in school desegregation cases.
In such cases, the defendants were enjoined to undertake a specific, albeit complex, act: Create a unitary
school system. Theoretically, the defendants could have been jailed until such time as they complied with
29
the court's mandate.16 Once the commanded act had been done, however, the court's mandate would have
been fully obeyed and any contempt would have been purged.
F.
In conclusion, when a party seeks an injunction to create criminal and/or civil liability via the court's
contempt powers, rather than to coerce an adverse party into taking an action required of it, that party is using
the legal device of an injunction for a purpose for which it was not designed.17 See Hecht Co. v. Bowles, 321
U.S. 321, 329, 64 S.Ct. 587, 592, 88 L.Ed. 754 (1944) ("The historical injunctive process was designed to
deter, not to punish."). Such an injunction provides no relief for the plaintiff (or at least no relief that could
not be obtained at law), and intrudes into areas constitutionally reserved for the legislative and executive
branches. Therefore, when a court is faced with a request for injunctive relief, it should consider how the
requested injunction is to be enforced. If the injunction cannot be enforced using coercive sanctions, then
it should not be entered.18
16
The more common approach was to require school districts to submit to the court a plan for creating
a unitary school system; if the plan was approved by the court, the court would retain jurisdiction to see
if implementation of the plan succeeded in fulfilling the court's mandate. See, e.g., Brown v. Board of
Educ. of Topeka, Kan., 139 F.Supp. 468, 470 (D.Kan.1955). When various obstacles prevented
fulfillment of the mandate—for instance, outside interference or obstinacy by certain officials—courts
often issued injunctions in aid of their jurisdiction (sometimes enforceable only through punitive
contempt sanctions, as discussed supra ) to ensure compliance with their initial orders.
17
Indeed, if such an action were taken by a plaintiff deliberately, it would likely amount to the tort of
abuse of process. Cf. Dykes v. Hosemann, 776 F.2d 942, 950 (11th Cir.1985) (Tjoflat, J., concurring in
part and dissenting in part).
18
An exception that proves the rule can be found in the area of securities law. Most SEC enforcement
actions are resolved by injunctions (entered pursuant to consent decrees) that order the defendant
essentially to do nothing more than obey the securities laws. See, e.g., SEC v. Clifton, 700 F.2d 744, 746
(D.C.Cir.1983). These injunctions allow the SEC to punish repeat offenders without having to bring a
separate lawsuit for each offense; instead, the commission needs only to request a show cause hearing to
obtain sanctions against the offender. See id. at 748. This practice is permissible, however, only because
Congress has specifically authorized it in the Securities Act of 1933. See 15 U.S.C. § 77t(b) (1994); SEC
v. Jones, 85 F.2d 17, 17 (2d Cir.1936) (noting that, because of the Securities Act, the SEC need not allege
the absence of an adequate remedy at law when seeking injunctive relief). This specific congressional
authorization suggests that such a practice would be impermissible if not so authorized.
30
II.
The appellants in this case challenge two sets of provisions in the injunction entered by the district
court. The first set of injunctive provisions enjoins the members of the DeKalb County Board of Education
and the employees of the DeKalb County school system (such as principals and teachers) not to permit
students to engage in various forms of religious activity.19 For instance, the defendants were enjoined from
"permitting ... vocal prayer; Bible and religious devotional or scriptural readings; distribution of religious
materials, texts, or announcements; and discussions of a devotional/inspirational nature" in the DeKalb
County schools. The defendants were also enjoined from "permitting ... prayers, invocations, benedictions,
or devotional messages at graduation or commencement exercises." Similar provisions were included in
regard to public-address systems and school-sponsored assemblies and events.
These provisions, for the reasons outlined in part I, were entered in error. It is clear that the
provisions are not enforceable through coercive sanctions. For instance, assume that a DeKalb County school
principal violates the injunction by "permitting" a student prayer at graduation.20 Plaintiff Jesse Chandler is
present at the graduation, and, after hearing the prayer, obtains a show cause hearing from the district court.21
19
The members of the DeKalb County Board of Education (and their successors in office) are the
defendants in the lawsuit. The injunction extends to the employees of the school system on the ground
that they are "in active concert and participation with" the defendants.
20
In addition to the problems with the injunction outlined above, the injunction's command that the
defendants not "permit" certain activity is too vague to satisfy the requirements of Fed.R.Civ.P. 65(d).
See American Red Cross v. Palm Beach Blood Bank, Inc., 143 F.3d 1407, 1411 (11th Cir.1998); Hughey
v. JMS Dev. Corp., 78 F.3d 1523, 1531 (11th Cir.1996). What exactly does it mean, for instance, for a
principal to "permit" a prayer at a school's graduation? Does it mean merely that if he is aware that a
student speaker is going to pray, then he must ask the student not to do so? Must he prevent the student
from speaking altogether once he is aware that the student is inclined to pray? If a student speaker
surprises the principal with a prayer at graduation, must he, at once, rush on stage and attempt physically
to remove the student from the microphone? This vagueness makes it impossible for the defendants to
know exactly what the injunction requires of them.
21
The only plaintiffs in the case against the DeKalb County Board of Education are Michael Chandler
and his son Jesse, a seventh-grade student in the DeKalb County school system. Michael Chandler
appeared as "next friend" for his son.
31
At the hearing, the court holds the principal in contempt. In this situation, the harm sought to be prevented
by the injunction—namely, the violation of Chandler's Establishment Clause rights22—would already have
occurred, and the court could do no more than punish the principal for his contempt or attempt to compensate
Chandler for the harm caused. The only form of coercive relief imaginable under the circumstances would
consist of fining or imprisoning the principal until such time as the district court was convinced (presumably
on the basis of nothing other than the principal's sincere-sounding promises) that he would not repeat the
offense; even then, the coercive sanctions would not have provided Chandler with any relief because the
harm would still be fully accomplished. Cf. Gompers, 221 U.S. at 442, 31 S.Ct. at 498. Thus, only punitive
or compensatory sanctions would be available.
Insofar as the injunction would be enforced via punitive contempt sanctions, it would provide no
direct relief to Chandler. The only benefit it would bring to Chandler would be a deterrent to the principal,
one which would be equally available in an action for damages under 42 U.S.C. § 1983 (1994). Thus, the
injunction, if enforced by punitive contempt sanctions, gives Chandler no better relief than that which he
could obtain at law.
Furthermore, enforcing the injunction with punitive contempt sanctions would raise a
separation-of-powers problem. A necessary prerequisite for the issuance of the injunction was the district
court's conclusion that the behavior to be enjoined—for instance, permitting a prayer at graduation—would
constitute a violation of Chandler's constitutional rights. Therefore, punitive sanctions in response to a
violation of the injunction would in essence be punishment for violating Chandler's constitutional rights. The
legislature, however, has already prescribed the appropriate criminal punishments for violations of
constitutional rights in 18 U.S.C. § 242 (1994), which states that whoever, under color of law, "willfully
subjects any person ... to the deprivation of any rights, privileges, or immunities secured or protected by the
22
I seriously doubt, in light of the majority's analysis, that a principal who permits a prayer, without
more, has violated a student's Establishment Clause rights. For purposes of my analysis, however, I will
assume the correctness of the district court's conclusion to the contrary.
32
Constitution or laws of the United States ..., shall be fined under this title or imprisoned not more than one
year, or both."23 The enforcement of this provision is the job of the executive branch, meaning that Congress
has determined that the United States Attorney, not the judiciary, is to determine whether the principal should
be prosecuted. In such a prosecution, the full panoply of constitutional protections would apply, rather than
the limited set that has been held to apply to the imposition of criminal contempt sanctions. See supra note
4. Furthermore, in a criminal prosecution, the principal could raise the defense, based on the "fair warning"
requirement of the Due Process Clause, that section 242 does not clearly prohibit "permitting" a prayer at
graduation. See United States v. Lanier, 520 U.S. 259, 267, 117 S.Ct. 1219, 1225, 137 L.Ed.2d 432 (1997)
(discussing, in the context of a section 242 prosecution, the constitutional requirement that the statute under
which the defendant is prosecuted must have "made it reasonably clear at the relevant time that the
defendant's conduct was criminal"). Such a defense would be unlikely to be available in a contempt hearing,
because the injunction—unlike the statute—explicitly prohibits this behavior. In sum, criminal sanctions
based on this injunction would constitute interference with the role of both the legislative and executive
branches.24
23
Conspiracies to violate this provision are outlawed by 18 U.S.C. § 241 (1994), which authorizes
fines and imprisonment of up to ten years. Thus, if the United States Attorney could demonstrate that the
principal conspired with, for instance, one or more members of the DeKalb County Board of Education to
permit the prayer, it could obtain convictions under section 241 in addition to section 242.
24
Congress has responded to this problem to some degree in 18 U.S.C. § 402 (1994), titled,
"Contempts constituting crimes." Under that section, where conduct constituting contempt of a district
court order also constitutes a crime under federal or state law, the alleged contemnor is entitled to a trial
by jury. Furthermore, the contemnor cannot be sentenced to more than six months imprisonment and
cannot be assessed a punitive fine of more than $1,000.
One could contend that this statute implicitly authorizes the sort of "end run" around
criminal procedure that I am attacking, and thus eliminates any separation-of-powers problem.
After all, why would Congress pass a law prescribing procedures and penalties for contempts
constituting crimes if it did not consider injunctions necessarily leading to such contempts (if
disobeyed) to be acceptable?
A look at the legislative history of section 402 dispels this contention. Section 402 was
passed in 1914 to prevent the abuse of labor injunctions. Congress was concerned that
33
Insofar as this injunction would be enforced via compensatory contempt sanctions, it would merely
be imitating the relief available to Chandler under 42 U.S.C. § 1983. Again, as with punitive sanctions, the
injunction would give Chandler no relief different from that which he could obtain at law.25
It would, however, provide that relief in a manner contrary to that which Congress contemplated in
enacting section 1983, again creating a separation-of-powers problem.26 For instance, in a section 1983
corporations were obtaining injunctions forbidding certain union activity; these injunctions were
then enforced through summary contempt proceedings. (The constitutional protections that are
now available in criminal contempt proceedings, see supra note 4, were not available at that
time.) The result was the imposition of penalties for violations of the criminal law, but without
the benefit of a jury trial. Section 402 was intended to minimize this problem. See United States
v. Pyle, 518 F.Supp. 139, 152 (E.D.Pa.1981) (discussing legislative history); 48 Cong. Rec. 8778
(1912) ("The courts have, under the guise of contempt of court, had men arrested and tried for
crimes without the intervention of a jury." (statement of Rep. Clayton)).
In light of this legislative history, it is difficult to read section 402 as Congress' stamp of
approval on injunctions enforceable only through punitive (or compensatory) sanctions. On the
contrary, section 402 arises out of disapproval of such injunctions. See id. at 8779 ("This bill is
to prevent a man or, say, a corporation, rich and powerful, getting out a blanket injunction at
midnight, broad as the canopy of heaven in its terms, and then oppressing the poor, humble
laborer." (statement of Rep. Clayton)). The fact that Congress chose to address the problem by
limiting the damage at the back end (when contempt sanctions are imposed) in no way implies
approval of the practice at the front end (when the injunction is issued). Cf. id. at 8798 (quoting
statement of Rep. Sabath that the bill is not as broad as it should be, but is a step in the right
direction).
Furthermore, had Congress intended so radical a move as to abolish completely the
longstanding equitable principle that equity will not enjoin a crime, see supra note 14, it surely
would have said something to indicate such an intent. Cf. Hecht Co. v. Bowles, 321 U.S. 321,
329, 64 S.Ct. 587, 591, 88 L.Ed. 754 (1944) ("We cannot but think that if Congress had intended
to make such a drastic departure from the traditions of equity practice, an unequivocal statement
of its purpose would have been made."). Nothing in the legislative history suggests that this is
the case.
25
The fact that exhaustion of state remedies is not required in section 1983 actions does not alter the
requirement that a plaintiff seeking injunctive relief on the basis of section 1983 must demonstrate the
absence of an adequate remedy at law. See Wallace v. Kern, 520 F.2d 400, 407 n. 13 (2d Cir.1975).
26
This problem might not arise if the alleged violation of Establishment Clause rights was caused by a
federal, rather than a state, official. Under those circumstances, the congressionally-created remedial
scheme of section 1983 would be inapplicable, and a judicially-created remedial scheme based on Bivens
v. Six Unknown Named Agents of Federal Bureau of Narcotics, 403 U.S. 388, 91 S.Ct. 1999, 29 L.Ed.2d
619 (1971), in which a cause of action is implied from the Constitution, would apply. (The
34
proceeding, the principal would be entitled to a trial by jury; this right is not guaranteed in a civil contempt
proceeding. Furthermore, in an ordinary section 1983 suit, the principal could respond to the complaint with
a motion to dismiss for failure to state a claim. If that failed, the principal could assert a defense of qualified
immunity, on the ground that liability for "permitting" a prayer at graduation is not clearly established by
Supreme Court or Eleventh Circuit precedent.27 Neither of these responses is generally available in a civil
contempt proceeding. Thus, unless the show cause hearing were in effect transformed into a new section
1983 suit—with a jury trial, the opportunity to raise defenses, and so forth—the court would be violating the
doctrine of separation of powers.
The second set of provisions challenged by the appellants, unlike the first set, was perfectly
appropriate for inclusion in an injunction. Those provisions relate to the district court's command that the
defendants (in conjunction with the plaintiffs) nominate three individuals, one of whom would serve as a
monitor for the purpose of ensuring compliance with the injunction. This is a discrete act that, if not taken,
could be compelled through coercive contempt sanctions (for instance, a fine of $100 for each day after the
deadline that the list of individuals was not submitted). It was therefore properly the subject of an
injunction.28
adequate-remedy-at-law problem would of course remain.) In this case, however, Congress has created a
remedial scheme for the constitutional violation (section 1983) and therefore, in the absence of a showing
that the congressional scheme is inadequate, the courts are to defer to Congress. See McCarthy v.
Madigan, 503 U.S. 140, 151, 112 S.Ct. 1081, 1090, 117 L.Ed.2d 291 (1992).
27
"[T]he qualified immunity test is simply the adaptation of the fair warning standard [from criminal
law] to give officials (and, ultimately, governments) the same protection from civil liability and its
consequences that individuals have traditionally possessed in the face of vague criminal statutes." Lanier,
520 U.S. at 270-71, 117 S.Ct. at 1227.
28
The unchallenged portions of the injunction are a mix of proper and improper provisions. For
instance, in addition to enjoining the defendants from "permitting" certain religious activities, it also
enjoins them from "aiding, abetting, commanding, counseling, inducing, ordering, procuring, or otherwise
participating in" those activities. Regardless of which gerund is chosen, these injunctive provisions still
forbid the performance of an act, and are therefore inappropriate. Other provisions, however, enjoin the
defendants to promulgate a written policy relating to religious activity in schools, to provide the Gideons
with a copy of the injunction, and to conduct a training session to instruct faculty and administrators
35
In conclusion, the first set of injunctive provisions challenged by the appellants are enforceable only
through punitive or compensatory contempt sanctions. They consequently raise all of the problems discussed
in part I, and therefore must be vacated. The second set of provisions, however, raise none of those problems,
and, for the reasons stated in the majority opinion, should be affirmed.
III.
The injunction is an important remedial tool, but also one that has been greatly abused. By using an
injunction as an alternative means of creating criminal and/or civil liability, courts ignore fundamental
equitable and constitutional principles. Certain injunctive provisions at issue in this appeal illustrate this
problem. I therefore concur in the majority opinion.
regarding the Establishment Clause and the Free Exercise Clause. These provisions command the
performance of specific acts, and are thus, at least in form, perfectly legitimate.
36