specially concurs:
¶15 I concur in our opinion. Nonetheless, I write separately to express my specific agreement with former Justice Diane Barz’s dissent in Matter of Iverson (1990), 241 Mont. 140, 786 P.2d 1. Like Justice Barz, I believe that guidelines should be adopted to focus the analysis of the district courts in applying the “best interest” test in these sorts of cases. I agree with her that, without guidelines, courts nominally applying the best interest test may still subtly discriminate against the equal right of the child’s mother to bear her surname.
¶16 I start with the principle that under Article II, Section 4 of Montana’s Constitution the dignity of the human being is inviolable; that no person shall be denied equal protection of the laws; and that neither the state nor any person, firm, corporation or institution shall discriminate against any person on account of, among other things, sex. Clearly, this provision of Montana’s Constitution guarantees *332that a mother has as much right to have her child bear her surname as does a father and that a child has as much right to bear its mother’s surname as it does its father’s. Just as clearly, then, when it is incumbent on a court to decide whose surname a child shall bear, the judge’s decision must be grounded in something more than the paternalistic notion prevalent in our society that, all things being equal, a child should bear the surname of its father.
¶17 Unfortunately, as Justice Barz correctly observed, it is precisely this discriminatory perception that runs implicitly through our three prior cases that have considered this issue: Firman v. Firman (1980), 187 Mont. 465, 610 P.2d 178; Overton v. Overton (1983), 207 Mont. 292, 674 P.2d 1089; and Iverson. While use of the best interest test alone produced the correct result in favor of the mother in the case at bar, nonetheless, as we correctly note, in each of our three prior cases, by applying this test alone, the father always prevailed. In each of these decisions, I believe that use of the best interest test served as little more than a transparent justification for blindly applying our society’s custom of naming children after their fathers without any real consideration of the equal constitutional right of mothers to have their children bear their surname.
¶18 For example, in Firman, our first case to consider this issue, the father petitioned to require the children to use his surname. The children’s legal surname remained Firman, but, the children wanted to use the name of their stepfather, Hauser, with whom they were living, in school to avoid inquisitive peers. The trial court ruled that the children could use any surname they preferred. We reversed. Firman, 187 Mont. at 470, 610 P.2d at 181.
¶19 We stated that, at common law, a person could adopt any surname he might choose so long as the change was not made for fraudulent purposes and that, in this country, the child’s use of its father’s surname was primarily a matter of choice rather than law. Firman, 187 Mont. at 469, 610 P.2d at 181. Noting that there was no Montana statute on point, we then fell back on “general principles, the most important of which in any proceeding concerning the relationship of a father and his child is the best interest of the child.” This Court then went on to conclude that since the father and his children lived in the same community and had an abiding interest in each other, and, since the father consistently supported his children, the district court should “not permit an unnatural barrier to come between [the father] and the children.” Firman, 187 Mont. at 470, 610 P.2d at 181.
*333¶20 As Justice Barz perceptively observed: “In Firman... [t]he use of the words ‘unnatural barrier’ are in themselves language that suggests a preference for the father’s name.” Iverson, 241 Mont. at 145, 786 P.2d at 4 (Barz, J., dissenting). Moreover, and as Justice Barz also observed in Iverson, the “best interest” criteria we relied on in Firman to require the children to use the father’s surname — parent living in same community with children; parent supporting children; barrier posed by parent and children having different surnames — were equally applicable to the children’s mother.
¶21 In our next case, Overton, the child was born after the parties’ dissolution. The mother, Cynthia (Miller) (Overton) had two other illegitimate children with surnames Miller and, in giving that surname to her daughter at birth, she desired that all her children have the same last name to avoid confusion and embarrassment. The father, among other things, petitioned to change the child’s name to his and to place his name on the birth certificate. Ostensibly, the father’s petition was premised on his desire to enroll his daughter in an Indian tribe, although nothing in our opinion suggests that she could not be enrolled under the surname Miller. In any event, the trial court granted this petition and we affirmed. Overton, 207 Mont. at 296, 674 P.2d at 1091.
¶22 Citing Firman, but without analysis of what factors the trial court actually considered, we simply noted that nothing in the district court’s findings and conclusions stated that the father had a preference or natural right to have his daughter bear his surname; that the court’s use of the best interest test did “not involve the equality of the sexes;” and that the court’s findings and conclusions were not clearly erroneous. Again, the only perceptible rationale for our decision was that best interests equate with society’s convention that children bear the surname of their father and not that of their mother.
¶23 In Iverson, the district court’s denial of the unwed mother’s petition to change her child’s surname from that of the father’s — a decision we affirmed on appeal — was based upon facts that the father acknowledged paternity, paid child support and made plans to seek visitation rights. Iverson, 241 Mont. at 142-43, 786 P.2d at 2. As noted by Justice Barz:
These three factors, however, do not even touch upon the child’s best interest. Instead, these factors merely reinforce traditional notions regarding the “proper” surname for a child. When viewed from a different perspective, these three factors could also be used *334to justify changing the child’s surname to that of the mother’s, as the mother has acknowledged maternity, she more than likely pays over $100 per month in supporting the child, and she has assumed the day to day responsibility and care for the child.
Iverson, 241 Mont at 143, 786 P.2d at 3 (Barz, J., dissenting). Once again, application of the best interest test alone was merely a guise for implementing our societal preference for preserving the male’s lineage through use of the father’s surname — precisely the rationale argued by Workman in the instant case.
¶24 Justice Barz’s citation to Application of Rossell by Yacono (N. J. Super. Ct. 1984), 481 A.2d 602, eloquently summarizes the problem:
The emergence of women as equals of men in our society may be our most significant revolution. The acceptance of that emergence is grudgingly slow; it is an acceptance which the courts must not impede. Names, as this case clearly illustrates, are intimately involved with the status of women. Rules of law for changing names cannot be premised upon unacceptable theories of inequality. The right of a mother to have the child bear her name must be recognized as equal to that of the father.
Rossell, 481 A.2d at 605.
¶25 I agree with Justice Barz: “While the courts are not outwardly and perhaps not even knowingly contributing to this subtle form of discrimination against women, the fact remains that the absence of guidelines in these type of cases only act to impede women’s status in society.” Iverson, 241 Mont. at 145, 786 P.2d at 4 (Barz, J., dissenting).
¶26 I would adopt in future cases of this sort the guidelines suggested by Justice Barz in her dissent. Specifically, trial courts should be directed to consider and to make findings of fact as to the following in determining whether the best interests of the child are served in being named after one parent or the other. These factors include:
1. the child’s surname preference, if any;
2. the length of time the child has had the surname;
3. the impact of the requested name change on both the mother-child and father-child relationships;
4. any misconduct by either parent that would make that parent’s surname possibly deleterious;
5. the child’s age;
6. the child’s embarrassment or discomfort when bearing a surname other than the family the child is presently living with;
*3357. the effect a surname may have on easing relations with a new family; and
8. if the child has siblings, the child’s relationship to those siblings and the impact on the child of having a surname different from the sibling’s surname.
¶27 Again, as noted by Justice Barz, “[t]hese factors address more directly a child’s best interests when confronted with a name change than the father’s magnanimous acknowledgment of paternity, his ability to follow a court order of paying $100 per month to help support the child, and his plans to seek visitation rights with the child.” Iverson, 241 Mont. at 144, 786 P.2d at 3 (Barz, J., dissenting).
¶28 Just as importantly, applying these guidelines in determining best interest will go a long way toward guaranteeing that each parent’s and the child’s rights under Article II, Section 4 of Montana’s Constitution are protected and toward preventing the subtle discrimination against women that is inherent in our society’s paternalistic convention of preferring the father’s surname to that of the mother’s.
JUSTICE REGNIER concurs in the foregoing special concurrence.