Michigan Supreme Court
Lansing, Michigan
Syllabus
Chief Justice: Justices:
Elizabeth T. Clement Brian K. Zahra
Bridget M. McCormack
David F. Viviano
Richard H. Bernstein
Megan K. Cavanagh
Elizabeth M. Welch
This syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been Reporter of Decisions:
prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. Kathryn L. Loomis
PEOPLE v GAFKEN
Docket No. 161835. Argued on application for leave to appeal October 13, 2022. Decided
December 29, 2022.
Theresa M. Gafken was convicted following a jury trial in the St. Clair Circuit Court of
second-degree murder, MCL 750.317. Defendant drove her vehicle at speeds exceeding 100 miles
per hour while fleeing the police; she ran a red light and collided with other vehicles, killing one
person and severely injuring several others. Defendant was originally charged with one count of
second-degree murder and two counts of operating a vehicle while intoxicated (OWI), MCL
257.625(5)(a). Before trial, defendant moved to be allowed to testify that she intended to pull over
when the police officer activated his overhead lights and that she did not do so because the
passenger sitting behind her, Michael Scandalito, thrust a gun into her ribs and threatened to kill
her if she stopped the car. In addition, defendant wanted to testify that Scandalito was on parole
and being sought for a parole violation and that he had committed aggravated assault against his
mother while using drugs. The prosecution opposed the motion, arguing that defendant should not
be allowed to introduce the evidence because it amounted to a duress defense, which was not
allowed. The court, Michael L. West, J., granted in part and denied in part the motion, concluding
that the evidence was not admissible with regard to the second-degree-murder charge but was
admissible with regard to the OWI charges. Following that ruling, the prosecution dismissed the
two OWI charges, after which defendant moved to allow a duress defense. The court denied the
motion, and the jury ultimately convicted defendant of second-degree murder. Defendant
appealed. In an unpublished per curiam opinion issued on June 18, 2020 (Docket No. 345954),
the Court of Appeals, MURRAY, C.J., and JANSEN and MARKEY, JJ., affirmed defendant’s
conviction and sentence. Defendant sought leave to appeal in the Supreme Court, and the Supreme
Court ordered and heard oral argument on whether to grant the application or take other action.
508 Mich 961 (2021).
In an opinion by Justice MCCORMACK, joined by Justices BERNSTEIN, CAVANAGH, and
WELCH, the Supreme Court, in lieu of granting leave to appeal, held:
A defendant charged with second-degree murder under a depraved-heart theory has a right
to raise the affirmative defense of duress. The elements of second-degree murder are: (1) a death,
(2) caused by an act of the defendant, (3) with malice, and (4) without justification or excuse.
Malice may be established in three ways: by showing (1) the intent to kill, (2) the intent to cause
great bodily harm, or (3) the intent to do an act in wanton and willful disregard of the likelihood
that the natural tendency of such behavior is to cause death or great bodily harm. Murder proved
using the third way of showing malice is commonly referred to as depraved-heart murder. A
defendant is constitutionally guaranteed the right to a meaningful opportunity to present a complete
defense, and duress is a common-law affirmative defense. The defense of duress does not negate
any offense element but, rather, excuses the offense. The rationale of the defense of duress is that,
for reasons of social policy, it is better that a person, faced with a choice of evils, choose to do the
lesser evil (violate the criminal law) in order to avoid a greater evil threatened by another person.
Historically, duress was not permitted as an affirmative defense to murder. However, People v
Reichard, 505 Mich 81 (2020), held that duress may be asserted as an affirmative defense to a
charge of felony murder if it is a defense to the underlying felony; the historical rationale that a
person should die themselves rather than murder an innocent person does not apply to felony
murder because the individual in the felony-murder context faces a choice between whether to
spare their own life or aid in a lesser felony (that is, one that does not include as an element the
killing of an innocent person). The historical rationale is also absent when depraved-heart murder
is charged because depraved-heart murder does not present the choice between sparing one’s own
life or taking the life of an innocent; rather, the choice presented is to lose one’s life or commit a
lesser felony than intentional murder. In this case, the prosecution charged defendant only under
a depraved-heart theory of murder. Because defendant alleged that she chose to do the lesser
evil—drive recklessly—the duress defense was available. The trial court’s order preventing
defendant from raising a duress defense to a second-degree murder charge that relied on a
depraved-heart theory of malice was error, and it was not harmless. The denial of the defense,
coupled with the trial court’s exclusion of any evidence that Scandalito threatened defendant,
effectively left defendant with no defense at all.
Court of Appeals judgment reversed; defendant’s conviction vacated; and case remanded
to the St. Clair Circuit Court.
Justice WELCH, joined by Justice BERNSTEIN, concurring, agreed with the majority that
duress is available as a common-law defense to second-degree murder when the accused is charged
and prosecuted under the depraved-heart theory of malice; however, she wrote separately for two
reasons. First, Justice WELCH believed it was important to acknowledge that Michigan’s
Constitution gives the Michigan Supreme Court the final say as to the common law of Michigan
regardless of the choices made by other jurisdictions. Recent scholarship has challenged
longstanding assumptions about the historical scope of the common-law duress defense in English
courts. Moreover, Michigan courts have no obligation to adopt all aspects of English common
law. Second, Justice WELCH wrote separately to draw attention to the fact that several questions
about the scope and contours of the duress defense as applied to depraved-heart murder were left
unresolved by the majority opinion, including who bears the burdens of proof and persuasion.
Also left unanswered was whether duress is a complete defense to an unintentional homicide or
whether it merely mitigates what would be second-degree murder down to manslaughter. The
Michigan Supreme Court will eventually need to provide answers to these questions if the
Legislature does not.
Chief Justice CLEMENT, dissenting, would have held that duress is not a defense to
depraved-heart murder and that because defendant waived the defense of duress in the trial court,
that issue should not have been addressed. Chief Justice CLEMENT disputed whether the choice to
act with the intent to create a very high risk of death or great bodily harm with the knowledge that
death or great bodily harm is the probable result, as depraved-heart murder requires, was
meaningfully different than a choice of taking the life of an innocent person. The common law,
as adopted by the Legislature, does not recognize a meaningful distinction between these forms of
malice. Keeping all other circumstances the same, a defendant with the intent to kill and a
defendant with the intent to create a very high risk of death or great bodily harm with the
knowledge that death or great bodily harm is the probable result will be found guilty of the same
crime: second-degree murder. That each form of malice results in second-degree murder reflects
a moral and legal judgment that the wanton and willful disregard of the risk of death or of great
bodily harm is just as depraved as the intent to kill or the intent to cause great bodily harm. The
majority incorrectly characterized depraved-heart murder as a “lesser felony” than intent-to-kill
murder because they are the same felony of second-degree murder, only brought under alternative
theories of malice. Chief Justice CLEMENT would not have differentiated among the theories of
malice regarding the availability of the duress defense as the majority did. Instead, she would have
concluded that, just as Michigan common law imposes the moral standard that a threatened person
cannot take a life to save their own, the same threatened person cannot act in a way that is nearly
certain to cause death or great bodily injury to save their own life.
Justice ZAHRA, joined by Justice VIVIANO, dissenting, emphasized that the long-
established principle that duress is not a defense to murder means that no forms of killing with
malice can or should be excused on the basis of duress. The majority rested its case on loose
language from scattered sources that duress is not a defense to “intentional murder”; these cases
at no point mentioned or discussed depraved-heart murder. The majority relied on the lack of more
extensive caselaw to support its position, but this lack of caselaw may demonstrate that few serious
jurists believed that a defendant could be acquitted of depraved-heart murder because of duress.
Regarding Reichard, it was incongruous, at best, to apply logic underlying the Court’s rejection of
felony murder as a common-law crime in toto to create a duress defense for a long-established
form of common-law murder—even more so when the primary case cited in favor of that defense
explicitly rejected it. All common-law murders are intentional. They all involve an intentional
act and either the intent to kill or the legal and moral equivalent to an intent to kill. For centuries,
Michigan law has recognized that there is no legal, social, or moral reason to treat differently
individuals who kill with the intent to cause death and those individuals who kill with the
intentional disregard for human life. The consequences of the majority’s decision will be that
murder defendants will have a strong incentive to describe their actions in terms of a conscious
disregard for death rather than an intent to kill; that difference could decide whether a defendant
is found guilty or acquitted, whereas before today’s decision the difference between those two
forms of intent in a second-degree murder prosecution was largely one of semantics. The majority
opinion will likely result in a sea change in the use of duress for homicide prosecutions. Finally,
defendant expressly waived the defense of duress in the trial court when she conceded that duress
is not a defense to depraved-heart murder; accordingly, defendant relinquished her right to such a
defense, and appellate review—let alone reversal—was inappropriate.
Justice VIVIANO, joined by Justice ZAHRA, dissenting, would have held that duress is
inapplicable to second-degree depraved-heart murder and that the Court should not have decided
this issue at all because defendant waived the issue. The Court made an imprudent mistake when
it ordered argument on the duress defense because defendant repeatedly conceded the issue in both
lower-court hearings and in several documents, including defendant’s briefing in the Court of
Appeals and application for leave to appeal in the Supreme Court. The majority’s conclusion that
the duress defense applies to depraved-heart murder hinged on the premise that the duress defense
is inapplicable only to intentional murders and that because depraved-heart murder is not an
intentional murder, the duress defense applies; this premise was incorrect and was based on loose
dicta that did not reflect any actual holding by any court. Depraved-heart murder is not an
intentional homicide in the traditional sense—it is not one in which the defendant actually intends
to kill. The majority used this lack of intent to kill—as well as misread the treatises cited in
Reichard and a few other cases—to distinguish depraved-heart murder from other types of murder
for purposes of the duress defense. None of the cases and sources the majority cited for support
even discussed or analyzed the matter, let alone decided whether duress applied to unintentional
murders. The courts that have addressed this issue disagree with the majority. Furthermore, there
was no persuasive rationale for recognizing duress as a defense to unintentional murders. The
malice necessary for depraved-heart murder—an implied malice arising from an actor’s disregard
for the high risk of death posed by the actor’s conduct—has long been viewed as equivalent to an
express malice consisting of an intent to kill. Malice is a holistic concept that, although it can be
classed as express or implied, is not subject to division into different degrees of culpability based
on whether the killing was intentional or unintentional. The presence of malice precludes any legal
excuse, including duress. Additionally, the inclusion of unintentional killings in the category of
murder reflects common moral intuitions and helps explain why depraved-heart murder is distinct
from felony murder in respect to the duress defense. Finally, the majority’s argument that
depraved-heart murder only creates a probability of killing an innocent as opposed to presenting a
defendant with a choice to kill or be killed—in other words, that creating the risk of death is less
blameworthy than intending to cause death—was flawed; the flaw in this argument was its
underlying assumption that depraved-heart murder is materially distinct from intentional murder
because the underlying conduct involves only the risk of death, whereas (presumably) the
intentional murder presents the certainty of death. Even the intentional-murder scenario is
unavoidably probabilistic. The rule that duress is inapplicable to attempted murder demonstrates
that the defense is inapplicable even when there is the mere risk of death, which is precisely the
situation with depraved-heart murder. Under the majority’s approach, defendants can invoke the
duress defense when their conduct creates a very high risk of death even though they were
threatened only with serious bodily harm; defendants thus can choose what seems to be the greater
evil and nonetheless invoke the defense.
Michigan Supreme Court
Lansing, Michigan
OPINION
Chief Justice: Justices:
Elizabeth T. Clement Brian K. Zahra
Bridget M. McCormack
David F. Viviano
Richard H. Bernstein
Megan K. Cavanagh
Elizabeth M. Welch
FILED December 29, 2022
STATE OF MICHIGAN
SUPREME COURT
PEOPLE OF THE STATE OF MICHIGAN,
Plaintiff-Appellee,
v No. 161835
THERESA MARIE GAFKEN,
Defendant-Appellant.
BEFORE THE ENTIRE BENCH
MCCORMACK, J.
Two terms ago, in People v Reichard, 505 Mich 81; 949 NW2d 64 (2020), this Court
unanimously held that duress may be asserted as an affirmative defense to felony murder
if it is a defense to the underlying felony. This case asks whether Reichard’s rationale
extends to allowing duress to be asserted as an affirmative defense to what is known as
depraved-heart second-degree murder. It does. We also conclude that the error in denying
the defense was not harmless, so we reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals and
remand this case to the St. Clair Circuit Court for further proceedings. 1
I. FACTS AND PROCEDURAL HISTORY
In April 2018, while fleeing from police, Theresa Gafken ran a red light at speeds
topping 100 miles per hour and collided with other vehicles, killing one person and causing
severe injuries to several others; Gafken was also injured. The prosecution charged her
with second-degree murder, MCL 750.317, and two counts of operating a vehicle while
intoxicated (OWI) causing serious impairment of a body function, MCL 257.625(5)(a).
Before trial, Gafken moved to allow certain testimony. Specifically, she asked to be
allowed to testify that she intended to pull over when the police officer activated his
overheard lights and that she didn’t do so because Michael Scandalito, who was sitting
behind her, then thrust a gun into her ribs and threatened to kill her if she stopped the car.
She also wanted to testify that Scandalito was on parole and being sought for a parole-
violation warrant and had committed aggravated assault against his mother while in a
methamphetamine rage. The prosecution opposed the motion, arguing that Gafken could
not assert a duress defense to murder and should not be allowed to introduce this evidence.
The trial court granted in part and denied in part the motion. The court held that the
evidence was not admissible on the homicide count but was admissible on the counts of
OWI causing serious impairment of a body function. The prosecution then dismissed the
two counts of OWI causing serious impairment of a body function.
1
In light of our holding, we decline to address the defendant’s argument about the jury
instruction on malice, Issue 2 in our order granting oral argument on the application. See
People v Gafken, 508 Mich 961, 962 (2021).
2
Gafken then moved to allow a duress defense. Following arguments, the trial court
denied her motion.
The jury convicted Gafken of second-degree murder. The Court of Appeals
affirmed her conviction and sentence in an unpublished opinion. People v Gafken,
unpublished per curiam opinion of the Court of Appeals, issued June 18, 2020 (Docket No.
345954). After directing the prosecutor to respond to Gafken’s application, People v
Gafken, 955 NW2d 900 (2021), we ordered oral argument on the application and asked the
parties to file supplemental briefs addressing these issues:
(1) whether the trial court erred in excluding evidence that the defendant was
threatened and of the defendant’s mental state at the time of the offense; (2)
whether the trial court erred in its instruction to the jury as to the intent
element of second-degree murder; and (3) whether any error was harmless.
[People v Gafken, 508 Mich 961, 962 (2021).]
II. ANALYSIS
Whether a common-law affirmative defense is available for a statutory crime is a
question of law that we review de novo. Reichard, 505 Mich at 85. This means that we
review the issue independently, without deference to the lower court. People v Jemison,
505 Mich 352, 360; 952 NW2d 394 (2020).
“The elements of second-degree murder are: (1) a death, (2) caused by an act of the
defendant, (3) with malice, and (4) without justification or excuse.” People v Goecke, 457
Mich 442, 463-464; 579 NW2d 868 (1998). Malice may be established in three ways: by
showing (1) the intent to kill, (2) the intent to cause great bodily harm, or (3) the intent to
do an act in wanton and willful disregard of the likelihood that the natural tendency of such
behavior is to cause death or great bodily harm. Id. at 464. Or, we also have held that the
3
third theory for proving malice can be shown by “the intent to create a very high risk of
death or great bodily harm with the knowledge that death or great bodily harm is the
probable result.” People v Dykhouse, 418 Mich 488, 495; 345 NW2d 150 (1984). The
prosecution charged Gafken only under the third theory of malice, commonly referred to
as depraved-heart murder. See, e.g., People v Aaron, 409 Mich 672, 714; 299 NW2d 304
(1980).
“Duress is a common-law affirmative defense.” People v Lemons, 454 Mich 234,
245; 562 NW2d 447 (1997). It does not negate any offense element but, rather, excuses
the offense. Id. at 246 n 15. “ ‘The rationale of the defense of duress is that, for reasons
of social policy, it is better that the defendant, faced with a choice of evils, choose to do
the lesser evil (violate the criminal law) in order to avoid the greater evil threatened by the
other person.’ ” Id., quoting 1 LaFave & Scott, Substantive Criminal Law, § 5.3, pp 614-
615.
In Reichard, we explained that “[h]istorically, duress was not permitted as an
affirmative defense to murder.” Reichard, 505 Mich at 88. Quoting Lord Matthew Hale
and William Blackstone, we identified why: “ ‘[T]hough a man be violently assaulted, and
hath no other possible means of escaping death, but by killing an innocent person; this fear
and force shall not acquit him of murder; for he ought rather to die himself, than escape by
the murder of an innocent.’ ” Id. at 92, quoting 4 Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws
of England, p *30, and citing 1 Hale, History of the Pleas of the Crown, p 51. But that
rationale did not apply to felony murder because “felony murder does not present that
choice. Instead, in the felony-murder context, the individual faces a choice between
4
whether to spare his or her own life or aid in a lesser felony (i.e., one that does not include
as an element the killing of an innocent).” Reichard, 505 Mich at 92.
The rationale for the no-duress-defense-for-murder rule is just as absent when
depraved-heart murder is charged. Depraved-heart murder does not present the choice
between sparing one’s own life or taking the life of an innocent. It is not kill or be killed.
Rather, the choice presented here is like the choice in Reichard: lose one’s life or commit
a lesser felony than intentional murder (here, reckless driving and fleeing from law
enforcement).
Although it has often been repeated that duress is not a defense to “homicide” or
“murder,” Reichard, 505 Mich at 89 n 18, we have recognized that this is an overly broad
statement of the rule, id. at 90 n 18. Instead, the no-duress-defense-for-murder rule has
been limited to cases of intentional murder historically. See, e.g., 2 LaFave, Substantive
Criminal Law (3d ed), Duress, § 9.7(b), p 100 (“[D]uress is no defense to the intentional
taking of life by the threatened person . . . .”); Cole v State, 221 So 3d 534, 543 n 4 (Fla,
2017) (stating that “ ‘duress is not a defense to intentional homicide’ ”), quoting Henry v
State, 613 So 2d 429, 432 n 6 (Fla, 1992); Commonwealth v Vasquez, 462 Mass 827, 835;
971 NE2d 783 (2012) (“The common law has steadfastly rejected duress as a defense to
intentional murder.”); Tully v State, 730 P2d 1206, 1210; 1986 OK CR 185 (Okla Crim
App, 1986) (noting that “common law recognized early on that duress should have no
application to the intentional taking of an innocent life by the threatened person”).
To be sure, some authority from other jurisdictions sounds in a broad rule—that
duress is not a defense to “murder” without qualification. See, e.g., People v Anderson, 28
Cal 4th 767, 780; 50 P3d 368 (2002) (“duress is not a defense to any form of murder”);
5
40 Am Jur 2d, Homicide § 107, p 721 (it is “generally held” that duress is not a defense to
murder and that “duress [does not] mitigate murder to manslaughter”). But generally, this
authority involves interpretation of a statute providing under what terms a duress defense
can be raised. Anderson, 28 Cal 4th at 773 (interpreting Cal Penal Code 26). Of course, a
state legislature may dictate the terms in which the duress defense may be raised. Because
our Legislature has not done so, we apply the common-law rule.
And we are aware of no court that has considered the issue of whether duress can
be raised as a defense to an unintentional homicide. Where courts have examined related
questions (although in dictum), they have recognized that duress is at least relevant when
the killing under duress isn’t intentional. See Anderson, 28 Cal 4th at 779-780 (“Although
duress is not an affirmative defense to murder, the circumstances of duress would certainly
be relevant to whether the evidence establishes the elements of implied malice murder.”);
id. at 795 (Kennard, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (“The majority’s
discussion appears to assume that murder necessarily involves a choice to take an innocent
life. Second degree murder, however, does not require an intent to kill.”). Indeed, the
concurrence/dissent in Anderson set forth a hypothetical with similar facts to those alleged
by Gafken here:
Imagine, for example, this scenario: Two armed robbers fleeing the
scene of a store robbery force their way into a car that is leaving the parking
lot. One robber holds a gun to the driver’s head, while the other places a gun
against the head of the driver’s wife. They order the driver to take off at high
speed and not to stop or slow down for stop signs or signal lights, threatening
immediate death to the driver and his wife. If the driver complies, and an
accident ensues resulting in the death of an innocent person, the driver could
be prosecuted for second degree murder on an implied malice theory, and,
under the majority’s construction of section 26, the driver could not assert
6
duress as a defense. I doubt that our Legislature intended to withhold the
defense of duress under these or similar circumstances. [Id.]
Understanding the foundation of the no-duress-defense-for-murder rule, we believe that
Hale and Blackstone would not have intended to withhold the duress defense on these facts.
Because Gafken alleges that she chose to do the lesser evil, a duress defense is available.
See Lemons, 454 Mich at 246.
The prosecution doesn’t offer many arguments to the contrary. Instead, it argues
that this Court should not allow a duress defense for depraved-heart murder because the
facts will make it very difficult for Gafken to succeed under a duress defense. But that
argument confuses whether the law permits a duress defense (our job) with whether the
defendant will be able to prevail on such a defense before a jury (not our job). A jury may
agree with the prosecution—Gafken has a right to find out. 2
A defendant is constitutionally guaranteed the right to a “meaningful opportunity to
present a complete defense.” Crane v Kentucky, 476 US 683, 690; 106 S Ct 2142; 90 L Ed
2d 636 (2012) (quotation marks and citation omitted). The trial court’s order preventing
Gafken from raising a duress defense to a second-degree murder charge that relied on a
depraved-heart theory of malice was error, and it was not harmless. The denial of the
defense, coupled with the trial court’s exclusion of any evidence that Scandalito threatened
Gafken, effectively left Gafken with no defense at all. The jury heard Gafken concede that
she engaged in the conduct leading to the victim’s death but was never able to consider
2
If we extend the duress defense to depraved-heart murder, as we have, the prosecution
and amicus Prosecuting Attorneys Association of Michigan encourage us to place the
burden of persuasion on Gafken to establish the defense by a preponderance of the
evidence. We decline to address the burden issue because it was not included in our order
granting oral argument on the application.
7
whether “the law excused [her] conduct . . . .” People v Leffew, 508 Mich 625, 656; 975
NW2d 896 (2022). Because the prosecution has not shown that this preserved
constitutional error was harmless beyond a reasonable doubt, we reverse. People v
Sammons, 505 Mich 31, 56; 949 NW2d 36 (2020).
III. CONCLUSION
A defendant charged with second-degree murder under a depraved-heart theory has
a right to raise the affirmative defense of duress. The defendant in this case was denied
her right to do so, and the error was not harmless. We therefore reverse the Court of
Appeals judgment, vacate Gafken’s conviction, and remand to the St. Clair Circuit Court
for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
Bridget M. McCormack
Richard H. Bernstein
Megan K. Cavanagh
Elizabeth M. Welch
8
STATE OF MICHIGAN
SUPREME COURT
PEOPLE OF THE STATE OF MICHIGAN,
Plaintiff-Appellee,
v No. 161835
THERESA MARIE GAFKEN,
Defendant-Appellant.
WELCH, J. (concurring).
I agree with the majority that duress is available as a common law defense to
second-degree murder when the accused is charged and prosecuted under the depraved
heart theory of malice. I write separately for two reasons. First, I believe it is important to
acknowledge that Michigan’s Constitution gives this Court the final say as to the common
law of Michigan, now and into the future, regardless of the choices made by other
jurisdictions. Moreover, recent scholarship challenges longstanding assumptions about the
historical scope of the common law duress defense in English courts. Secondly, although
I agree with the decision to recognize duress as a common law defense to unintentional
second-degree murder, the Court has left unresolved several questions about the scope and
contours of the defense. Whether a successful duress defense excuses all criminal liability
for an unintentional killing (such as depraved heart murder) is an open question. In short,
courts will continue to grapple with the obvious tension between the death of an innocent
bystander and allegations that the actions causing the death were the result of duress. And,
of course, the Legislature can address the scope of the duress defense if it so chooses.
I. COMMON LAW DURESS HAS A COMPLICATED HISTORY THAT DOES NOT
BIND THIS COURT
This Court has the constitutional authority and prerogative to provide the final say
on what the common law is in Michigan. See Placek v Sterling Hts, 405 Mich 638, 656;
275 NW2d 511 (1979) (“There is no question that both this Court and the Legislature have
the constitutional power to change the common law.”). 1 This Court has also recognized
that “in exercising our common-law authority, our role is not simply to ‘count heads’ but
to determine which common-law rules best serve the interests of Michigan citizens.” Stitt
v Holland Abundant Life Fellowship, 462 Mich 591, 607; 614 NW2d 88 (2000). It is also
well established that Michigan courts do not have an obligation to adopt all aspects of
English common law. See Perrin v Lepper, 34 Mich 292, 295 (1876) (“ ‘The common law
of England is not to be taken, in all respects, to be that of America. Our ancestors brought
with them its general principles and claimed it as their birthright; but they brought with
them and adopted only that portion which was applicable to their situation.’—Story, J., in
Van Ness v. Pacard, 2 Pet., 144[.]”). Today’s decision also is not the first time that this
Court has changed the course of Michigan common law in a significant way. See, e.g.,
Placek, 405 Mich at 650 (“We hold, in the interest of justice for all litigants in this state,
that the doctrine of comparative negligence hereby replaces the doctrine of contributory
1
See also Const 1963, art 3, § 7 (“The common law and the statute laws now in force, not
repugnant to this constitution, shall remain in force until they expire by their own
limitations, or are changed, amended or repealed.”); Const 1963, art 6, § 1 (“[T]he judicial
power of the state is vested exclusively in one court of justice which shall be divided into
one supreme court, one court of appeals, [and] one trial court of general jurisdiction . . . .”).
This Court has interpreted Const 1963, art 3, § 7 as authorizing “both judicial change and
legislative amendment or repeal.” Placek, 405 Mich at 657, citing Myers v Genesee Co
Auditor, 375 Mich 1, 7; 133 NW2d 190 (1965).
2
negligence and that the standards of comparative negligence are to be applied by the court
on remand for new trial in the instant case and on a limited retroactive basis.”). 2
Asking whether duress can serve as a defense to homicide is a deceptively complex
question. Historically, many American common law courts have held that duress is not a
defense to homicide, at least when the killing was intentional. See, e.g., State v
Nargashian, 26 RI 299, 301-304; 58 A 953 (1904) (holding that the trial court properly
2
I do not read the dissents as contesting this Court’s authority to define or change
Michigan’s common law. Rather, the dissents appear to be better understood as objecting
to the new common law path on which the majority has chosen to embark and as raising
concerns about the depth of the majority’s analysis. Further, I disagree with the dissents’
assertion that the duress-defense issue was waived by defendant, Theresa M. Gafken.
Justice VIVIANO argues that defendant waived the duress defense in the Court of Appeals.
Justice ZAHRA argues that defendant waived the duress defense in the trial court.
Defendant filed numerous pretrial motions concerning these issues. To the extent Justice
VIVIANO argues that this issue was waived or abandoned in the Court of Appeals,
defendant’s appellate attorney argued the following in the brief filed with the Court of
Appeals: “In the present case, the precluded evidence was not a means of claiming that Ms.
Gafken was innocent of homicide. That would clearly be prohibited by law. The only
issue at trial was whether Gafken was guilty of second-degree murder or involuntary
manslaughter.” (Emphasis omitted.) Appellate counsel’s focus on duress to negate malice
and the concession that allowing a common law duress defense to homicide was prohibited
by then-existing precedent may have been a tactical decision given the state of the law.
But it would be an unjust mistake for this Court to read appellate counsel’s argument as
waiving defendant’s ability to present defendant’s previously raised argument that the
common law duress defense to depraved heart murder should be permitted. As the majority
acknowledges, a defendant is entitled to a “ ‘meaningful opportunity to present a complete
defense.’ ” Quoting Crane v Kentucky, 476 US 683, 690; 106 S Ct 2142; 90 L Ed 2d 636
(2012). This Court has also repeatedly recognized that even when an issue is not preserved,
“this Court has inherent power to review an issue not raised in the trial court to prevent a
miscarriage of justice[.]” Walters v Nadell, 481 Mich 377, 387; 751 NW2d 431 (2008).
Given this Court’s conclusion that the common law duress defense is permitted when
defending against allegations of depraved heart murder, it would be unjust for this Court
to ignore defendant’s preserved issue merely because of a few sentences of her appellate
attorney’s argument in the Court of Appeals. Because the trial court did not permit
defendant to present a duress defense to the jury, it would be inappropriate for this Court
to opine on whether defendant can successfully assert the defense on remand.
3
rejected a duress jury instruction for an accomplice to an intentional killing). This Court
has previously recognized the historical basis for this American jurisprudential view to be
grounded, at least in part, in ancient treatises authored by Sir Matthew Hale and Sir William
Blackstone. See People v Reichard, 505 Mich 81, 88-89; 949 NW2d 64 (2020). Some
jurists who have looked at these legal texts have assumed or argued that, at least from a
historical perspective, duress cannot be a defense to any killing committed with malice.
In his dissent, Justice VIVIANO argues that there is not historical support for the path
the Court has taken today. For example, the dissent cites 1 Hale, History of the Pleas of
the Crown, p 51, and argues that
[s]ome of the older sources note that duress was also inapplicable to other
crimes not involving killing at all, including treason and robbery. From this,
it would appear that the more prevalent and longer-established version of the
rule is the broader one [i.e., that duress is unavailable as a defense to all
homicides]. [Post at 13-14.]
This might be a fairer critique if it was unquestionably true. But history—and the law—
can be shaped by one idea or viewpoint while ignoring others that existed at the time. Many
legal scholars writing on the subject of duress as a defense focused their attention on the
development of criminal law after Hale and Blackstone penned their seminal treatises.
Hale and Blackstone have been bestowed with a sage-like quality in American
jurisprudence as irrefutable sources of authority regarding English common law. Judges,
advocates, and scholars have been hesitant to question the premise of the legal assertions
penned by these jurists centuries ago. But recent scholarship raises questions about
many of these historical common law assumptions. See Elkington, The Historical
Development of Duress and the Unfounded Result of Denying Duress as a Defence to
4
Murder (Online First publication), J Crim L (2022), available at
[Click “PDF / ePub”]
(accessed December 5, 2022). Elkington examined “all reported duress cases and the
Statutes of the Realm, which significantly impacted on the development of the law, from
1266 (the first found recorded use of duress) until the end of the 19th century with the
landmark case of Dudley and Stephens.” Id. at 2 (citation omitted). She argues that at its
conception, “duress was created as a full defence for treason, including where the defendant
had killed,” and concludes that “the decision to deny use of the [duress] defence in [R v
Howe, (1987) AC 417 (appeal taken from Court of Appeal, Criminal Division)] cannot be
substantiated by reference to the defence’s historical development.” Id. For example,
Elkington notes the following:
Many of the initial cases where duress was used were where the
defendant had been involved in some form of civil war or rebellion. In Henry
III Statutes of the Realm 1266–67 the excuse of duress was used to mitigate
the punishments of those who had committed treason by assisting rebels in
the battle of Evesham. The ordinary punishment for bailiffs and officers of
the Earl of Leicester who had committed treason through actions amounting
to robbery and manslaughter, was a fine of as much as their lands were worth
for five years, but the punishment for those who acted through fear had the
lesser punishment of one year’s value of their land. This early reference to
duress sets no limits on what type of offence duress would act to mitigate,
although it is an early indication that acting under duress could be used to
mitigate the punishment for manslaughter in treason cases. [Id. at 3 (citations
omitted).]
These observations are directly contrary to the assertion that there is little historical basis
for duress serving as a defense to crimes of treason or homicide.
5
Elkington further noted that peacetime English courts eventually rejected duress as
a defense to murder in 1838 in the case of R v Tyler, 3 id. at 7, but she questions the historical
and doctrinal basis for this change in course considering prior precedent, id. Of course,
Elkington’s work, standing alone, is unlikely to resolve hundreds of years of debate among
legal scholars. 4 But her research suggests that at least some of the assumptions made by
American courts about English common law are premised on an inaccurate—or at least
incomplete—account of the historical record. Perhaps Hale and Blackstone did not have
all the relevant information or perhaps they chose one historical narrative given the
preferred public opinion, moral narrative, or political climate of the times. Elkington
observes that by the time Hale was writing in the eighteenth century, he “made the point
that the law is different in times of war to times of peace; stating that duress would not be
a defence to treason, murder[,] or robbery in times of peace, but could be (a defence to
treason) in times of war or rebellion.” Id. at 5-6. She notes, however, that such an argument
“seems . . . illogical if the threat was immediate and so no protection could be sought even
in times of peace[.]” Id. at 6. It is entirely possible that rather than simply documenting
verbatim previous legal determinations, Hale and Blackstone were doing what many
3
R v Tyler, 173 Eng Rep 643; 8 C & P 616 (1838).
4
Elkington is not the first scholar to question or analyze the pragmatic and philosophical
bases for prohibiting duress as a defense to murder. See, e.g., Mulroy, The Duress
Defense’s Uncharted Terrain: Applying it to Murder, Felony Murder, and the Mentally
Retarded Defendant, 43 San Diego L Rev 159, 173-180 (2006) (advocating for a more
flexible approach to the duress defense); Dressler, Exegesis of the Law of Duress:
Justifying the Excuse and Searching for its Proper Limits, 62 Cal L Rev 1331, 1368-1375
(1989) (discussing line-drawing considerations for duress and the idea of coerced
homicides).
6
advocates and legal scholars do today: making subtle arguments for what they thought the
common law should be. And while learned legal scholars and their treatises provide
beneficial context and background, the words of Hale and Blackstone do not dictate
Michigan’s common law today.
II. THE COURT’S DECISION TODAY LEAVES MANY QUESTIONS
UNANSWERED
The Court’s decision today recognizes the existence of a duress defense for
unintentional second-degree murder. Many questions remain. Some the Court has
expressly declined to reach today, such as who bears the burdens of proof and persuasion
as to the duress defense. Other questions also remain unanswered. One particularly thorny
question is whether duress is a complete defense to an unintentional homicide, or whether
it merely mitigates what would be second-degree murder down to manslaughter. This
question warrants some illumination.
A. STATE LAW STATUTORY AND COMMON LAW REGARDING THE DURESS
DEFENSE IS NOT UNIFORM ACROSS THE COUNTRY
There is a lack of consensus among state jurisdictions as to whether and to what
extent duress can excuse a homicide. Section 2.09 of the Model Penal Code provides that
duress is a complete affirmative defense to any crime unless the “actor recklessly placed
himself in a situation in which it was probable that he would be subject to duress” or if the
actor does so negligently if negligence would be enough to “establish culpability for the
offense charged.” Model Penal Code, § 2.09(2) (1985). But model codes are not the law
unless adopted, usually through the legislative process.
7
In terms of legislation, as the majority and dissenting opinions acknowledge, states
have taken a variety of approaches toward the duress defense. Twelve states have enacted
statutes that appear to mirror, if not explicitly adopt, § 2.09 of the Model Penal Code,
including its carveout. 5 Nine additional states have adopted statutes that appear to allow
duress as a complete or partial defense to one or more forms of nonintentional homicide. 6
Ten other states have enacted statutes that appear to foreclose the duress defense for all
intentional or reckless killings, if not for all forms of homicide. 7 Concerning the latter two
5
See Alaska Stat 11.81.440; Ark Code Ann 5-2-208; Conn Gen Stat 53a-14; Del Code Ann
tit 11, § 431; Haw Rev Stat 702-231; NY Penal Law 40.00; ND Cent Code 12.1-05-10; 18
Pa Cons Stat 309; SD Codified Laws 22-5-1; Tenn Code Ann 39-11-504; Tex Penal Code
Ann 8.05; Utah Code Ann 76-2-302.
6
See Colo Rev Stat 18-1-708 (making duress available for all offenses other than “class 1”
felonies, which includes some but not all forms of homicide); Idaho Code 18-201 (making
the duress defense available for all offenses that are not “punishable with death”); Ky Rev
Stat Ann 501.090 (allowing duress as a defense to all crimes except “intentional
homicide”); Me Stat, tit 17-A, § 103-A (excluding homicides that are committed
“intentionally or knowingly” from the duress defense); Minn Stat 609.08 and Minn Stat
609.20(3) (providing that a successful duress defense mitigates an intentional or
unintentional killing to manslaughter in the first degree); Mont Code Ann 45-2-212
(making duress available as a defense to all crimes except those punishable by death, such
as deliberate homicide under Mont Code Ann 45-5-102); NJ Stat Ann 2C:2-9(b) (“In a
prosecution for murder, the [duress] defense is only available to reduce the degree of the
crime to manslaughter.”); Nev Rev Stat 194.010(8) (making duress available as a defense
to all crimes except those punishable by death, such as first-degree murder); Wis Stat
939.46 (allowing a duress defense to most crimes, but “if the prosecution is for first-degree
intentional homicide, the degree of the crime is reduced to 2nd-degree intentional
homicide”).
7
See Ala Code 13A-3-30(d) (excluding all forms of murder and killings under aggravated
circumstances from the duress defense); Ariz Rev Stat Ann 13-412 (defining duress as a
justification defense, but excluding “offenses involving homicide or serious physical
injury”); Ga Code Ann 16-3-26 (making duress available as a defense for all crimes except
“murder”); Ind Code 35-41-3-8 (excluding from duress defense crimes “against the person
as defined in” Ind Code 35-42, which includes all forms of homicide, battery, kidnapping,
human trafficking, sex crimes, and robbery); Iowa Code 704-10 (allowing a duress defense
8
groups, nearly all state legislatures have adopted the carveout provision from the Model
Penal Code that precludes the defense if the actors intentionally or recklessly put
themselves in a position to be placed under duress. Declaring that someone could
potentially be excused, in full or in part, for causing the death of another person to save
their own life is an unenviable quagmire on many levels. The lack of uniformity among
states that have taken legislative action illustrates that such line-drawing is fraught with
difficulty.
In common law jurisdictions, the law is equally unsettled. No court appears to have
resolved the precise question that was presented to this Court—whether the common law
duress defense is available to refute allegations of unintentional homicide premised on a
criminal recklessness theory of malice (also known as depraved heart murder in Michigan).
With respect to the courts that have addressed duress in the context of homicide
accusations, nearly every case involved an intentional killing, and to the extent that
unintentional killings have been discussed, it has generally been in dicta. 8 For example, in
for all crimes except “an act by which one intentionally or recklessly causes physical injury
to another”); Kan Stat Ann 21-5206 (allowing a duress defense for all crimes except murder
or voluntary manslaughter); La Stat Ann 14:18 (defining duress as a justification defense
but excluding “murder”); Mo Rev Stat 562.071 (making duress available for all crimes
except “murder”); Or Rev Stat 161.270 (making duress available for all offenses other than
“murder”); Wash Rev Code 9A.16.060(2) (making duress available as a defense for all
crimes except “murder, manslaughter, or homicide by abuse”).
8
See, e.g., Driggers v State, 917 So 2d 329, 331 (Fla App, 2005) (in an appeal by the
defendant who was charged with intentional second-degree murder but was convicted of
voluntary manslaughter as a lesser included offense, the trial court observed that “[t]he
courts generally agree that duress is not a defense to homicide”); People v Serrano, 286 Ill
App 3d 485, 491; 676 NE2d 1011 (1997) (in an appeal arising from convictions of felony
murder, the court noted that duress may be raised as a defense to felony murder but not to
other forms of homicide); Commonwealth v Vasquez, 462 Mass 827, 835; 971 NE2d 783
(2012) (in an appeal from convictions of intentional first-degree murder, the court held,
9
People v Anderson, 28 Cal 4th 767, 780; 50 P3d 368 (2002), the California Supreme Court
held that Cal Penal Code 26 did not create a statutory right to a duress defense and that at
common law, “duress is not a defense to any form of murder.” The court also rejected
arguments that duress could reduce murder to manslaughter. However, Anderson, id. at
784, acknowledged, and the court reaffirmed in People v Powell, 6 Cal 5th 136, 164; 425
P3d 1006 (2018), that duress may be raised as a defense to felony murder if it is a defense
to the underlying felony. Notably, Anderson was not a case concerning allegations of an
“we hereby reject duress as a defense to deliberately premeditated murder, murder
committed with extreme atrocity or cruelty, and murder in the second degree”); Johnson v
State, 290 So 3d 1232, 1242 (Miss, 2020) (in an appeal from a conviction of first-degree
murder under an accomplice-liability theory, the court noted that “[l]ongstanding
Mississippi law holds that duress is not a legal defense to murder”) (quotation marks and
citation omitted; alteration in original); Long v State, 74 P3d 105, 108; 2003 OK CR 14
(Okla Crim App, 2003) (in an appeal from a conviction of first-degree intentional murder,
the court noted that “duress is not a defense to the intentional taking of an innocent life by
a threatened person”); State v Smarr, 146 NC App 44, 54; 551 SE2d 881 (2001) (in an
appeal from a conviction for intentional second-degree murder, the court noted that duress
is not applicable to murder); State v Finnell, 101 NM 732, 737; 688 P2d 769 (1984) (in an
appeal from a conviction for first-degree intentional murder, the court noted that duress is
not a defense to homicide); State v Fuller, 203 Neb 233, 243; 278 NW2d 756 (1979) (in an
appeal from a conviction of first-degree intentional murder, the court noted that “[d]uress
or compulsion is no excuse to a charge of homicide”), rev’d in part on other grounds;
rehearing denied, 204 Neb 196 (1979); State v Nargashian, 26 RI 299, 304; 58 A 953
(1904) (in an appeal from a conviction of intentional murder as an accomplice, the court
held that “fear induced by one person is no defense to a defendant who kills another under
its influence”); Arnold v Commonwealth, 37 Va App 781, 788; 560 SE2d 915 (2002) (in
an appeal from a conviction of second-degree murder, the court acknowledged that duress
is a defense to felony murder when the murder is committed by a co-actor but suggested
that it is not available for other forms of murder); State v Rocheville, 310 SC 20, 26; 425
SE2d 32 (1993) (in an appeal from convictions of armed robbery, kidnapping, and murder,
the court noted that duress is not a complete defense to intentional murder and that it also
cannot mitigate the crime to voluntary manslaughter); James v State, 357 P3d 101, 106;
2015 WY 83 (2015) (in an appeal from a conviction for aiding and abetting a robbery, the
court noted that “[i]n Wyoming, duress has been recognized as a defense to criminal
charges, other than a charge of taking the life of an innocent person”).
10
unintentional homicide. Rather the homicide allegations in that case arose from a brutal
group beating that eventually led to the victim being bludgeoned to death and disposed of
in a ravine. Anderson, 28 Cal 4th at 770-771. Thus, any commentary in Anderson
concerning the nonapplicability of the common law duress defense to an unintentional
homicide was dicta.
B. THE POSSIBILITY OF AN IMPERFECT DEFENSE
The majority opinion today does not answer the question of whether duress is a
complete defense to allegations of unintentional second-degree murder. Some state
legislatures have recognized duress as a mitigating defense. See NJ Stat Ann 2C:2-9(b)
(“In a prosecution for murder, the [duress] defense is only available to reduce the degree
of the crime to manslaughter.”). The possibility of an imperfect or mitigating defense to
homicide has also been discussed by leading scholars:
One who is coerced by another person, or forced by the pressure of
natural physical circumstances (e.g., thirst, starvation) into committing what
is otherwise a crime, may have in some circumstances a complete defense to
the crime, but not if the crime in question consists of intentionally killing
another human being. Thus one who, not in self-defense or defense of
another, kills an innocent third person to save himself or to save another is
guilty of a crime. But it is arguable that his crime should be manslaughter
rather than murder, on the theory that the pressure upon him, although not
enough to justify his act, should serve at least to mitigate it to something less
than murder. Some of the latest state criminal codes so provide. [2 LaFave,
Substantive Criminal Law (3d ed, 2018), § 15.3(c), p 705 (citations
omitted).]
The Court of Special Appeals of Maryland followed the mitigation path outlined by
LaFave in Wentworth v State, 29 Md App 110, 118; 349 A2d 421 (1975). Wentworth was
charged with second-degree murder as an accomplice to an intentional murder committed
11
by her husband. The issue the court considered was whether the defendant’s charges could
be reduced to voluntary manslaughter in light of strong evidence that the defendant had
little choice or ability to escape from her husband during or after the killing. Id. at 112-
113, 116. The Wentworth court recognized that “[w]hatever the psychological reality may
be, the law, as a matter of social policy, has declared that the defense of duress may not
extend to the taking of an innocent person’s life.” Id. at 118. Despite this, the court found
compelling LaFave’s & Scott’s treatise (albeit an older edition) and other authorities, and
it held that “an ‘imperfect’ defense of duress may not exculpate a defendant in an unlawful
homicide case but may supply that mitigation necessary to lower the degree of guilt from
murder to manslaughter[.]” Id. at 121. Similar logic might be applicable to depraved heart
murder given that a death was not intentional but was a natural and probable consequence
of the accused’s reckless conduct.
Similarly, in the felony-murder context, this Court’s decision in Reichard did not
recognize duress as a complete defense to the killing. Reichard, 505 Mich at 88-89.
Rather, the Court held that the prosecution could “proceed against the defendant on the
lesser included offense of second-degree murder if the evidence supported that charge. In
other words, the defendant’s duress defense to the underlying felony would only prevent
the enhancement of second-degree murder to first-degree murder.” Id. at 95-96 (citation
omitted). Under Reichard, a successful duress defense to accusations of felony murder
does not excuse the accused from the risk of punishment for the crime if the conduct could
be prosecuted as second-degree murder. Stated differently, a prosecution could move
forward if there is evidence that a human death occurred, because of the actions of the
12
accused (or an accomplice), with malice, and without a proper justification or excuse. See
People v Goecke, 457 Mich 442, 463-464; 579 NW2d 868 (1998).
It is also worth noting that voluntary manslaughter in Michigan operates similarly
to an imperfect defense. All the elements of intentional second-degree murder are present:
(1) a death, (2) caused by the defendant’s act, (3) with malice (under an intent to kill or
intent to cause great bodily harm theory), and (4) without justification. But in contrast to
second-degree murder based on a depraved heart theory of malice, a conviction of
manslaughter is appropriate if the killing occurred “in the heat of passion, the passion was
caused by adequate provocation, and there was not a lapse of time during which a
reasonable person could control his passions.” People v Mendoza, 468 Mich 527, 535; 664
NW2d 685 (2003). Conversely, “[i]nvoluntary manslaughter is the unintentional killing of
another, without malice, during the commission of an unlawful act not amounting to a
felony and not naturally tending to cause great bodily harm; or during the commission of
some lawful act, negligently performed; or in the negligent omission to perform a legal
duty.” Id. at 536. “[B]oth forms of manslaughter are necessarily included lesser offenses
of murder. . . . Consequently, when a defendant is charged with murder, an instruction for
voluntary and involuntary manslaughter must be given if supported by a rational view of
the evidence.” Id. at 541.
This, of course, logically leads to questions about the drawing of lines and whether
there are limits to the scope of a duress defense when raised in the face of an innocent life
having been lost. If a successful duress defense is raised to felony murder under
Reichard—which, assuming the evidence exists, requires that first-degree murder charges
be reduced to second-degree murder—does the same defense now apply to the
13
second-degree murder charge? If so, could those charges hold water? And what about the
defendant in this case? If she is successful in her attempt to raise a duress defense on
remand, could the jury still find her guilty of the lesser included offense of manslaughter?
The Court need not answer these questions today, but such questions loom and will need
to be considered.
III. CONCLUSION
I join the majority today in recognizing that someone accused of unintentional
second-degree murder (also known as depraved heart murder) can, in theory, raise a
common law duress defense. But the Court’s ruling today does not explicitly foreclose or
endorse the possibility of being convicted of the lesser included offense of manslaughter
after a successful duress defense has been asserted. Nor has the Court addressed who bears
the burden of proof or persuasion for such a defense. In the absence of action from the
Legislature, this Court will need to provide the answers.
Elizabeth M. Welch
Richard H. Bernstein
14
STATE OF MICHIGAN
SUPREME COURT
PEOPLE OF THE STATE OF MICHIGAN,
Plaintiff-Appellee,
v No. 161835
THERESA MARIE GAFKEN,
Defendant-Appellant.
CLEMENT, C.J. (dissenting).
I respectfully dissent from the majority’s opinion recognizing duress as an
affirmative defense to depraved-heart murder. Because I believe that the Court of Appeals
reached the correct result below, I would instead affirm.
Duress is an affirmative defense which excuses a defendant’s culpability for a crime
under the theory that “it is better that the defendant, faced with a choice of evils, choose to
do the lesser evil (violate the criminal law) in order to avoid the greater evil threatened by
the other person.” People v Lemons, 454 Mich 234, 246; 562 NW2d 447 (1997), quoting
1 LaFave & Scott, Substantive Criminal Law, § 5.3, pp 614-615 (quotation marks omitted).
This defense is not without limitation: a defendant asserting duress as a defense must
satisfy various requirements regarding the extent of the threat, the timeliness of the threat,
and the reasonableness of the defendant’s reaction. See People v Luther, 394 Mich 619,
623; 232 NW2d 184 (1975). Further, and most relevant to the issue at hand, defendants
facing charges of murder have historically been prohibited from asserting a duress defense.
See People v Reichard, 505 Mich 81, 88-89; 949 NW2d 64 (2020). Early common-law
commentators remarked that the logical premise underlying duress—that the law should
encourage a threatened person to choose the lesser of two evils—should not be applied to
the commission of murder, reasoning that a threatened individual “ought rather to die
himself, than escape by the murder of an innocent.” 4 Blackstone, Commentaries on the
Laws of England, p *30. See also 1 Hale, History of the Pleas of the Crown, p 51 (“[I]f a
man be desperately assaulted, and in peril of death, and cannot otherwise escape, unless to
satisfy his assailant’s fury he will kill an innocent person then present, the fear and actual
force will not acquit him of the crime and punishment of murder, if he commit the fact; for
he ought rather to die himself, than kill an innocent[.]”).
Relying on this historical commentary, our Court of Appeals initially recognized a
blanket prohibition of the duress defense as to all homicide crimes in People v Dittis, 157
Mich App 38, 40; 403 NW2d 94 (1987), overruled by Reichard, 505 Mich at 90 n 18.
However, in so doing, the Dittis Court did not engage in a thorough analysis of the
common-law restrictions on the duress defense; it instead summarily concluded that “[a]t
common law duress is not a defense to homicide.” Dittis, 157 Mich App at 40-41.
Unexplained was whether the prohibition of duress applied to all homicide-related charges,
only murder charges, or only certain types of murder charges. Subsequent caselaw cited
Dittis for its broad prohibition, and that caselaw, too, failed to engage in a thorough review
of this principle. See, e.g., People v Henderson, 306 Mich App 1, 5; 854 NW2d 234 (2014),
overruled by Reichard, 505 Mich 81; People v Gimotty, 216 Mich App 254, 257; 549
NW2d 39 (1996), overruled by Reichard, 505 Mich 81; People v Travis, 182 Mich App
389, 392; 451 NW2d 641 (1990), overruled by Reichard, 505 Mich 81.
2
Recently, this Court examined the duress prohibition in People v Reichard and
concluded that duress should be available to a defendant accused of first-degree felony
murder. Reichard, 505 Mich at 83. To prove first-degree felony murder, a prosecutor must
demonstrate that the defendant committed second-degree murder during the course of a
felony enumerated in MCL 750.316(1)(b); essentially, the commission of the felony
elevates what otherwise would have been a second-degree-murder charge to a first-degree-
murder charge. See People v Aaron, 409 Mich 672, 734; 299 NW2d 304 (1980). In
Reichard, this Court reflected on the historical justification for the duress prohibition—that
a threatened person should choose death over the murder of an innocent person—and
concluded that it did not apply with equal force to felony murder because the threatened
person is not presented with that same choice. Reichard, 505 Mich at 92. “Instead, in the
felony-murder context, the individual faces a choice between whether to spare his or her
own life or aid in a lesser felony (i.e., one that does not include as an element the killing of
an innocent).” Id. This Court further reasoned that prohibiting the use of duress as a
defense to a felony-murder charge would be illogical where, had the second-degree murder
and the felony been charged separately, the defendant would have been able to assert duress
as a defense against the felony charge. Id. at 93. In sum, this Court concluded that duress
is an available defense to first-degree felony murder because it can negate the enumerated
felony that operates to elevate the murder from second degree to first degree. Id. at 95.
Importantly, this Court did not conclude that duress would completely excuse the killing
at hand, noting that a successful duress defense in the felony-murder context would still
allow the prosecutor “to proceed against the defendant on the lesser included offense of
second-degree murder if the evidence supported that charge.” Id. at 95-96. In recognizing
3
that duress should be available in the context of felony murder, this Court also expressly
overruled Dittis to the extent that it applied to crimes beyond the first-degree-murder
charge at issue in Dittis. Id. at 90 n 18.
Today, the majority concludes that the rationale expressed in Reichard regarding
felony murder is also applicable to depraved-heart murder. 1 Depraved-heart murder is a
colloquial term for a second-degree-murder charge brought under a specific theory of
malice. “The elements of second-degree murder are: (1) a death, (2) caused by an act of
the defendant, (3) with malice, and (4) without justification or excuse.” People v Goecke,
457 Mich 442, 463-464; 579 NW2d 868 (1998). The prosecution may establish malice by
proving that the defendant had one of three intents: “the intent to kill, the intent to inflict
great bodily harm, or the intent to create a very high risk of death or great bodily harm with
the knowledge that death or great bodily harm is the probable result.” People v Dykhouse,
418 Mich 488, 495; 345 NW2d 150 (1984). 2 A second-degree-murder charge brought
under this third and final theory of malice is what is known as depraved-heart murder. See
Aaron, 409 Mich at 714.
The majority reasons that
[t]he rationale for the no-duress-defense-for-murder rule is just as absent
when depraved-heart murder is charged. Depraved-heart murder does not
1
I agree with my dissenting colleagues that defendant waived this issue below and that,
accordingly, this Court should not have addressed it. See People v Carter, 462 Mich 206,
215; 612 NW2d 144 (2000).
2
The third form has also been phrased as the “wanton and willful disregard of the
likelihood that the natural tendency of a person’s behavior is to cause death or great bodily
harm.” Aaron, 409 Mich at 728.
4
present the choice between sparing one’s own life or taking the life of an
innocent. It is not kill or be killed. Rather, the choice presented here is like
the choice in Reichard: lose one’s life or commit a lesser felony than
intentional murder (here, reckless driving and fleeing from law enforcement).
* * *
. . . Because Gafken alleges that she chose to do the lesser evil, a
duress defense is available. See Lemons, 454 Mich at 246.
I disagree with this rationale. Specifically, I dispute whether the choice to act with “the
intent to create a very high risk of death or great bodily harm with the knowledge that death
or great bodily harm is the probable result,” Dykhouse, 418 Mich at 495, as depraved-heart
murder requires, is meaningfully different than a choice of “taking the life of an innocent.”
Certainly, our common law (as adopted by the Legislature) does not see a meaningful
distinction between these forms of malice. Keeping all other circumstances the same, a
defendant with the intent to kill and a defendant with the intent to create a very high risk
of death or great bodily harm with the knowledge that death or great bodily harm is the
probable result will be found guilty of the same crime: second-degree murder. 3 That each
form of malice results in second-degree murder reflects a moral and legal judgment that
the wanton and willful disregard of the risk of death or of great bodily harm is just as
depraved as the intent to kill or the intent to cause great bodily harm. For example, a
3
Of course, first-degree murder also requires a finding of malice. First-degree murder is
typically distinguished from second-degree murder in that it also requires a showing of
premeditation and deliberation. MCL 750.316(1). Accordingly, if the circumstances at
hand include premeditation and deliberation, the defendant with the intent to kill and the
defendant with the intent to create a very high risk of death or great bodily harm with
knowledge that death or great bodily harm will result will both be found guilty of first-
degree murder.
5
defendant who, without premeditation or deliberation, shoots a firearm at a specific person
in a mall intending to kill the victim is considered as depraved as the defendant who shoots
a firearm into a crowd at the mall without the intent to kill but with the knowledge that
doing so will very likely result in a person’s death or great bodily harm, and both will be
found guilty of the same crime. The majority is thus incorrect to characterize depraved-
heart murder as a “lesser felony” than intent-to-kill murder because they are instead
actually the same felony of second-degree murder, only brought under alternative theories
of malice. 4
A threatened person who has committed depraved-heart murder has engaged in the
same prohibited choice described by Blackstone: to commit murder rather than lose one’s
own life. I would not differentiate among the theories of malice regarding the availability
of the duress defense as the majority now does. Instead, I would conclude that, just as our
common law imposes the moral standard that a threatened person cannot take a life to save
their own, the same threatened person cannot act in a way that is nearly certain to cause
death or great bodily injury to save their own life. The law has consistently treated these
forms of malice the same, and I see no reason in either the majority opinion or the caselaw
4
To the extent that the majority relies on Reichard for its conclusion, I would emphasize
that in Reichard, this Court held only that duress was a defense to first-degree murder
insofar as duress applied to the underlying felony; this Court did not hold that duress could
excuse second-degree murder. Reichard, 505 Mich at 95-96. In fact, this Court explicitly
explained that a successful duress defense as to a first-degree felony-murder charge would
still allow the prosecution to pursue a second-degree-murder charge. Id.
6
it cites 5 to differentiate between these forms of malice such that duress should be prohibited
for a murder charge brought under one theory of malice and not the other. 6 Therefore, I
dissent.
Elizabeth T. Clement
5
I agree with my dissenting colleagues that the caselaw the majority cites does not
demonstrate that duress has historically been proscribed as a defense only when an intent-
to-kill murder has been charged, nor does this caselaw demonstrate that duress is
contemporarily proscribed as a defense against only intent-to-kill murder charges in most
of our sister states.
6
I would also note that the majority’s new rule poses practical difficulties for future
prosecutions. Even when a prosecutor proceeds under an intent-to-kill or intent-to-cause-
great-bodily-injury theory of malice, a defendant could choose to argue that their intent
instead reflected depraved-heart murder. Under this theory of the case, the duress defense
would become available to the defendant. Accordingly, even when the prosecutor’s theory
of malice is “intentional,” it is likely that the duress defense would be available to the
defendant despite that all appear to agree that “intentional” killings are not subject to the
duress defense. Although the jury in such a case could be instructed to consider the duress
defense only as to the depraved-heart theory of malice, given the practical difficulty of
proving a defendant’s subjective intent to kill, the most likely conclusion is that the jury
will prefer to assess a defendant’s actions under the more easily proven depraved-heart
theory of malice—which will also now allow consideration of a duress defense. In sum,
duress defenses are likely to now become available in most second-degree-murder
prosecutions. While this does not mean that every second-degree-murder defendant will
have a successful duress defense, it does mean that the scope of the majority’s new rule is
broader than it appears at first glance.
7
STATE OF MICHIGAN
SUPREME COURT
PEOPLE OF THE STATE OF MICHIGAN,
Plaintiff-Appellee,
v No. 161835
THERESA MARIE GAFKEN,
Defendant-Appellant.
ZAHRA, J. (dissenting).
The majority opinion reverses a murder conviction on the basis of a duress defense
that defendant expressly waived at trial and failed to raise on appeal. 1 More astounding
1
When defendant, Theresa M. Gafken, initially sought to introduce evidence of Michael
Scandalito’s threat at the trial level, defendant conceded that duress is not a defense to
depraved-heart murder. In response to the prosecution’s argument that defendant was
attempting to introduce a duress defense, defendant recognized that while her case was not
one “where the defense of duress can be asserted,” she claimed the evidence could
nonetheless negate “the requisite state of mind.” At a hearing, defendant reiterated that she
was “without [a] duress defense . . . .” Defendant continued, explaining that she merely
intended to introduce the evidence to negate intent, not to create a duress defense. The
prosecution and the circuit court relied on this concession to understand and analyze
defendant’s request to admit evidence, ultimately concluding that the evidence would serve
as a “backdoor way to get to a duress defense.” Defendant’s explicit and unambiguous
concession of the issue, which served to benefit defendant’s legal position, constituted
waiver. See People v Kowalski, 489 Mich 488, 503-505; 803 NW2d 200 (2011)
(explaining that a defense attorney’s repeated statement that he had “no objection” to jury
instructions constituted “waiver,” leaving “no error to review”); People v Traver, 502 Mich
23, 40-41; 917 NW2d 260 (2018) (holding that a defense attorney’s statement that he was
“satisfied” with the circuit court’s actions constituted a waiver of the argument that the
court failed to provide an oral instruction); United States v Walker, 615 F3d 728, 733
than the Court’s disregard for longstanding principles of preservation is that the duress
defense adopted in the majority opinion has never before been successfully embraced in
American jurisprudence. Never. This case is a striking display of judicial overreach,
accomplished through a short, cursory opinion, in which ipse dixit stands in the place of
sound legal reasoning.
(CA 6, 2010) (reasoning that a defense counsel’s statement that he “ ‘does not dispute’ ” a
legal position constituted “waiver,” not just forfeiture).
Only after defendant had lost these arguments and the circuit court had ruled in the
prosecution’s favor did defendant change her position and argue that a duress defense was
proper. By that time, the argument had been finally and irrevocably waived. See People
v Carter, 462 Mich 206, 215; 612 NW2d 144 (2000) (explaining that a waived right is
“ ‘relinquish[ed]’ ”) (citations omitted); United States v Saucedo, 226 F3d 782, 787 (CA 6,
2000) (reasoning that a waived argument is “forever foreclosed”); 28 Am Jur 2d, Estoppel
& Waiver, § 186, p 651 (“It is well settled that a waiver once made is irrevocable even in
the absence of consideration or of any change in position of the party in whose favor the
waiver operates.”); 31 CJS, Estoppel & Waiver, § 93, pp 442-443 (“A waiver when once
made cannot be recalled, revived, expunged, or revoked, nor can the right waived be
reclaimed, at least not without the consent of the adversary.”). Recognizing that it had
already resolved the issue, the circuit court denied defendant’s request. On appeal,
defendant returned to her initial position that duress is not a valid defense to a charge of
depraved-heart murder. See, e.g., Defendant’s Brief on Appeal (May 19, 2019) at 26
(arguing that the trial court could have given a jury instruction that stated “duress was not
a viable defense”); Defendant’s Application for Leave to Appeal in the Michigan Supreme
Court (August 11, 2020) at 23 (same).
Given defendant’s waiver, appellate review, let alone reversal, is inappropriate.
Carter, 462 Mich at 215. But even if the Court used the more lenient “plain error” standard
for untimely and unpreserved claims, reversal is not warranted. People v Carines, 460
Mich 750, 763; 597 NW2d 130 (1999). Declining to accept a defense that has never before
been recognized in Michigan, or anywhere else in this country, is a paradigmatic example
of a challenge falling outside the plain-error standard. People v Allen, 507 Mich 597, 614;
968 NW2d 532 (2021) (stating that an error is “plain” only when it is “not subject to
reasonable dispute”) (quotation marks and citations omitted).
2
The majority rests its case on loose language from scattered sources that duress is
not a defense to “intentional murder.” 2 The cases relied upon by the majority at no point
mention or discuss depraved-heart murder, and many held in favor of the prosecution and
precluded a duress defense. 3 Unsurprisingly, whenever courts and other legal sources have
directly addressed whether duress is available for any form of killing with malice, including
depraved-heart murder, they have unambiguously rejected the majority’s position. 4 Yet
2
See ante at 5 (majority opinion).
3
See People v Reichard, 505 Mich 81, 88, 95-96; 949 NW2d 64 (2020) (stating that, at
common law, “duress was not permitted as an affirmative defense to murder”; holding that
duress could apply to lesser crimes in felony-murder prosecutions; and reasoning that the
prosecution would, despite the existence of duress, “still be able to proceed against the
defendant on the . . . offense of second-degree murder”); Cole v State, 221 So 3d 534, 543
n 4 (Fla, 2017) (concluding that trial counsel was not ineffective for failing to investigate
a duress defense for charges of kidnapping, robbery, and first-degree murder and noting in
passing that a duress defense was not applicable to the murder charges); Commonwealth v
Vasquez, 462 Mass 827, 834-835; 971 NE2d 783 (2012) (rejecting the defense of duress
for a murder based on “extreme atrocity or cruelty,” which includes murder by depraved
heart, and reasoning that “the duress defense for any form of murder would . . . encourage
killing”); Tully v State, 730 P2d 1206, 1210; 1986 OK CR 185 (Okla Crim App, 1986)
(explaining that the logic of duress did not apply to a felony-murder charge because “the
harm contemplated” by committing robbery, on its own, was not greater than “murder of
an innocent”—not mentioning or discussing killings with malice, such as depraved-heart
murder).
4
See, e.g., Sanders v State, 942 So 2d 156, 161 (Miss, 2006) (rejecting a duress defense
for a depraved-heart murder conviction, reasoning that “duress is not a legal defense to
murder”); People v Anderson, 28 Cal 4th 767, 774, 780; 50 P3d 368 (2002) (examining a
statute that “adopted the common law” and concluding that “duress is not a defense to any
form of murder,” including murders with implied malice such as depraved-heart murder);
State v Rumble, 680 SW2d 939, 941-943 (Mo, 1984) (reasoning that, by adopting the
common law, “duress is not a defense to the crime of murder—any murder,” which
included “depraved-heart murder”); 40 CJS, Homicide, § 181, p 629 (“The rule
encompasses denial of the defense to all forms of murder” given that “duress cannot, as a
matter of law, negate . . . malice[.]”).
3
the majority relies on the lack of more extensive caselaw to support its position. 5 Instead,
it may demonstrate that few serious jurists, before today, believed that a defendant could
be acquitted of depraved-heart murder because of duress.
Moreover, the phrase “intentional murder,” as used in the majority opinion, is an
unhelpful pleonasm. All common-law murders are intentional. They all involve an
intentional act. And they all either involve the intent to kill or the legal and moral
equivalent to an intent to kill, otherwise described as “malice.” 6 For centuries, our law has
recognized that there is no legal, social, or moral reason to treat differently individuals who
kill with intent to cause death and those individuals who kill with intentional disregard for
human life. 7 In fact, depraved-heart murders can be and often are more reprehensible, and
5
See ante at 6-7 (majority opinion).
6
See People v Dykhouse, 418 Mich 488, 495; 345 NW2d 150 (1984) (explaining that
second-degree murder can be proved equally by “one of three possible intents: the intent
to kill, the intent to inflict great bodily harm, or the intent to create a very high risk of death
or great bodily harm with the knowledge that death or great bodily harm is the probable
result”) (emphasis added); People v Potter, 5 Mich 1, 7 (1858) (“[A]t the common law, if
a mortal blow was malicious,” such as with “a reckless disregard of the safety or lives of
others, the killing would be murder, and would be punishable in the same manner as though
perpetrated with the deliberate design of taking the life of the victim.”); see also People v
Goecke, 457 Mich 442, 467; 579 NW2d 868 (1998) (reasoning that depraved-heart murder
requires the “intent to do an act,” is a “general intent crime,” and is “constructively with a
malicious intention”) (quotation marks and citation omitted); 21 Am Jur 2d, Criminal Law,
§ 113, p 230 (explaining the basic principle of criminal law that “general intent” requires
“proof that the person acted intentionally” as opposed to “accident, mistake, carelessness,
or absent-mindedness”).
7
See note 6 of this opinion; Coke, The Third Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England
(6th ed), p 57 (“If a man knowing that many people come in the street from a sermon, throw
a stone over a wall, intending only to fear them, or to give them a light hurt, and thereupon
one is killed, this is murder[.]”); Robinson v State, 307 Md 738, 744-745; 517 A2d 94
(1986) (“The common law treats [the depraved-heart] state of mind as just as blameworthy,
4
more deleterious to our social fabric, than intent-to-kill murders. Yet the majority now
gives depraved-heart murderers the benefit of a duress defense, and thus an unprecedented
path to complete exoneration. 8
The majority cites People v Reichard, 505 Mich 81; 949 NW2d 64 (2020), in
support of its decision. 9 A complete analysis of that case and surrounding caselaw suggests
otherwise. In Michigan, “[w]hat was known at common law as the crime of murder . . . is
now known under our statutory scheme as the crime of second-degree murder . . . .” 10
However, because felony murder requires only the “intent to commit a [lesser] felony,” as
compared to the “man-endangering-state-of-mind” of malice, Michigan has never
recognized a common-law “felony murder.” 11
A similar logic underlay this Court’s decision in Reichard. 12 The Court in Reichard
permitted a duress defense against statutory felony-murder charges. 13 The Court did so
just as anti-social and, therefore, just as truly murderous as the specific intents to kill and
to harm.”) (quotation marks and citation omitted); accord Goecke, 457 Mich at 466-467.
8
See People v Luther, 394 Mich 619, 622; 232 NW2d 184 (1975) (explaining that, if
proven, “[a] successful duress defense excuses the defendant from criminal
responsibility”).
9
See ante at 4-5 (majority opinion).
10
Dykhouse, 418 Mich at 495, citing MCL 750.317.
11
People v Aaron, 409 Mich 672, 723, 727-728; 299 NW2d 304 (1980) (quotation marks
and citation omitted); see also People v Pavlic, 227 Mich 562, 565-566; 199 NW 373
(1924) (reasoning that an individual who merely commits a felony and thereby
“unintentionally causes the death of another” is “not guilty of murder”).
12
Reichard, 505 Mich 81.
13
MCL 750.316(1)(b).
5
because the underlying felony in felony murder “does not include as an element the killing
of an innocent,” let alone malice; duress could negate the underlying felony only, which
failed to constitute murder. And despite the applicability of duress to the underlying
felony, the Court in Reichard confirmed that the prosecution “would still be able to proceed
against the defendant on the lesser included offense of second-degree [common-law]
murder if the evidence supported that charge.” 14 Second-degree murder includes depraved-
heart murder. 15
It is incongruous, at best, to apply logic underlying this Court’s rejection of felony
murder as a common-law crime in toto to create a duress defense for a long-established
form of common-law murder. Even more so when the primary case cited in favor of that
defense explicitly rejected it. Reviewing other sources, it is apparent that the occasional
use of the term “intentional murder” in the law of duress is designed primarily to
distinguish between crimes lacking the elements of death and malice, i.e., lesser included
offenses in “felony murder” prosecutions, and crimes that include both elements, i.e.,
Michigan’s second-degree murder. 16
14
Reichard, 505 Mich at 92, 95-96.
15
See Dykhouse, 418 Mich at 495.
16
See, e.g., 2 LaFave, Substantive Criminal Law (3d ed, 2017), § 9.7(b), pp 98, 100
(explaining that the common-law rule provides “duress cannot excuse murder” but
reasoning that “intentional killing[s]” is more precise “since duress may excuse the
underlying felony for what would otherwise be a felony murder” given the “unexpected[]”
nature of felony murder; not mentioning depraved-heart murder whatsoever); Tully, 730
P2d at 1210 (reasoning that duress can be used to excuse felony murder because the
defendant committed only a “lesser crime,” “the harm contemplated by the defendant” in
the case, robbery, was not equal to “murder of an innocent,” and the common-law doctrine
6
The consequences of the Court’s actions are disconcerting. After today’s ruling,
murder defendants will have a strong incentive to describe their actions in terms of a
conscious disregard for death rather than an intent to kill. Criminal defendants have
expansive rights to present defenses and request jury instructions that fit their theory of the
case. 17 Defendants may very well argue their actions fit within depraved-heart murder,
even if they are charged with intent-to-kill murder. And once a depraved-heart theory is
admitted, the majority opinion will allow a duress defense. It will be very difficult, if not
impossible, for prosecutors or trial courts to discount a state of mind alleged by a defendant.
Intentionally acting to kill another individual and intentionally acting with conscious
disregard for another individual’s life can facially exhibit little difference. “Yes, I
intentionally shot at her knowing she was there, but I did not intend to kill her.” Before
today’s decision, the difference between those two forms of intent in a second-degree
did not apply), citing LaFave, § 9.7(b) (quotation marks and citations omitted; emphasis
added).
17
“When a defendant requests a jury instruction on a theory or defense that is supported
by the evidence, the trial court must give the instruction.” People v Riddle, 467 Mich 116,
124; 649 NW2d 30 (2002); compare People v Mills, 450 Mich 61, 82; 537 NW2d 909
(1995) (concluding that a requested instruction is not appropriate when “the record is
devoid of any evidence supporting [the] jury instruction”), with People v Dupree, 486 Mich
693, 712; 788 NW2d 399 (2010) (holding that a trial court improperly refused a requested
instruction when the defendant “satisfie[d] the initial burden of producing some evidence”
supporting the instruction); 40A Am Jur 2d, Homicide (2019), § 463, p 358 (“Where there
is any evidence tending, in an appreciable degree, to support a particular theory of a case,
the court may give instructions to the jury presenting the theory to them, and it has been
held that the defendant is entitled to have charges given if there is any evidence as a
foundation therefor, regardless of the weakness, insufficiency, inconsistency, or doubtful
credibility of the proof.”).
7
murder prosecution would be largely one of semantics. After today, however, the
difference could decide whether a defendant is found guilty or acquitted.
Further, it is hard to see how the majority opinion will be limited to depraved-heart
murders. Murders involving the intent to cause grievous bodily harm similarly lack an
intent to cause death, or as the majority describes it, “intentional murder.” 18 More than
likely, the majority opinion will result in a sea change in the use of duress for homicide
prosecutions.
The long-established principle that “duress is not a defense to murder” means
exactly what it says. 19 This instinctive logic, passed down through generations of jurists,
18
See Dykhouse, 418 Mich at 495. At common law, the differences between depraved-
heart murder and murder with intent to cause great bodily harm were minimal, if not
nonexistent. See 4 Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of England, pp **199-200
(stating that tying a boy “to a horse’s tail” to “drag[] him along the park,” causing death,
was murder, as was “beat[ing] another in a cruel and usual manner . . . though he did not
intend his death”).
19
Blackstone, p *30 (stating that the “fear and force” underlying duress “shall not acquit
him of murder”) (emphasis added), citing 1 Hale, History of the Pleas of the Crown, p 51;
Reichard, 505 Mich at 88, 95 (stating that, at the common law, “duress was not permitted
as an affirmative defense to murder” and duress could not prevent a prosecution for
“second-degree murder”); 40 Am Jur 2d (2019), Homicide, § 107, p 721 (“It is generally
held that neither duress, coercion, nor compulsion are defenses to murder.”); 40 CJS,
Homicide, § 181, p 629 (“The rule encompasses denial of the defense to all forms of
murder” given that “duress cannot, as a matter of law, negate the [element of] malice[.]”);
40 ALR2d 90, § 2.2, p 148 (“Defense of duress is not applicable to murder.”); People v
Dittis, 157 Mich App 38, 41; 403 NW2d 94 (1987) (“[D]uress is never a defense to
murder[.]”), quoting People v Young, 120 Mich App 645, 653; 327 NW2d 329 (1982)
(BEASLEY, J., dissenting on other grounds), overruled by Reichard, 505 Mich at 90 n 18,
to the extent Dittis’s holding has been interpreted broadly as duress not being allowed as a
defense to any “homicide.”; West v Bell, 550 F3d 542, 555 (CA 6, 2008) (“[D]uress is
never a defense to murder.”); United States v LaFleur, 971 F2d 200, 205 (CA 9, 1991)
(explaining, while interpreting the federal murder statute, that “the common law rejected
duress as a defense to murder”), citing, in part, Arp v State, 97 Ala 5; 12 So 301 (1893);
8
remains as powerful today as it did in centuries past: no forms of killing with malice can
or should be excused on the basis of duress. Because the majority reverses a murder
conviction on the basis of a duress defense never previously recognized in the history of
this country, and does so despite the fact that defendant waived the issue, I respectfully
dissent.
Brian K. Zahra
David F. Viviano
United States v Buchanan, 529 F2d 1148, 1153 (CA 7, 1975) (“[C]oercion is not a defense
to murder.”), citing RI Recreation Ctr v Aetna Cas & Surety, 177 F2d 603 (CA 1, 1949).
9
STATE OF MICHIGAN
SUPREME COURT
PEOPLE OF THE STATE OF MICHIGAN,
Plaintiff-Appellee,
v No. 161835
THERESA MARIE GAFKEN,
Defendant-Appellant.
VIVIANO, J. (dissenting).
In a little over seven brisk pages, the majority comes to a conclusion that, as far as
I can tell, has not been reached by any other common-law court: that the duress defense
applies to depraved-heart murder. The few courts to have directly opined on the issue have,
albeit in dicta, stated that the defense is inapplicable to this form of murder. And many
courts and commentators have more broadly stated that duress does not apply to any charge
of murder. None of this deters the majority, which ignores many of the relevant materials
and misreads others. The resulting analysis is as flawed as it is cursory. The majority
postures its case as a simple extension of People v Reichard, 505 Mich 81; 949 NW2d 64
(2020). But nothing in the holding or logic of Reichard supports the majority’s result.
Worse still, the majority reaches its result despite the fact that defendant, Theresa M.
Gafken, conceded this very issue below. Therefore, the Court should not have decided this
issue at all. But as it has done so, I would hold that duress is inapplicable to second-degree
depraved-heart murder and therefore dissent.
I
In April 2018, a police officer saw a white Camaro, driven by defendant, speeding
at around 50 to 60 miles per hour (mph) in a 25-mph zone. The officer activated his siren,
and while defendant initially put on the Camaro’s turn signal and slowed down, defendant
then abruptly turned onto a second street and sped away from the officer. The officer was
driving at around 90 mph, but defendant still pulled away from him. During the chase,
defendant swerved between traffic lanes. Defendant eventually crashed after running a red
light, sideswiping a truck and ramming into a Jeep. The driver of the Jeep was killed on
impact. Data from the Camaro indicated that it was traveling at about 117 mph
immediately before the accident in a 35-mph zone. There was no evidence of braking on
the road. Defendant and the two other men who were in the Camaro sustained serious
injuries.
Defendant was arrested and charged with second-degree murder. The officers’
investigation revealed that defendant’s blood contained tetrahydrocannabinol (THC),
which is the main psychoactive substance found in cannabis, and that her driver’s license
was suspended. After her arrest, defendant stated that the men had asked for a ride and
acted suspiciously. She intended to pull over. The next thing she remembered was sitting
in the car after the accident.
Prior to trial, defendant filed a motion in limine to allow testimony that she acted
out of fear for her life based on the actions of the other men in the car. Specifically, she
wanted to testify that one of the men, Michael Scandalito, who was being sought for a
parole violation—and for whom defendant knew an arrest warrant had been issued—had
thrust a hard object into her ribs, which defendant believed to be a gun. Believing she
2
would be killed, defendant then sped away from the police. Defendant also requested that
she be allowed to present evidence that this act triggered her post-traumatic stress disorder.
The trial court noted that defendant wanted to establish either a duress defense or a
diminished-capacity defense but rejected duress as inapplicable to second-degree murder
and diminished capacity as not recognized in this state. The jury convicted defendant of
second-degree murder.
Defendant appealed in the Court of Appeals, which held that the trial court did not
err by excluding the evidence of duress. The Court noted that while Reichard had
disapproved of a broad rule that “duress is not a defense to homicide,” Reichard also “could
be construed as suggesting that the Michigan Supreme Court would be open to allowing a
duress defense . . . perhaps to even a charge of second-degree murder that is pursued solely
on the malice prong regarding the creation of a very high risk of death or engaging in
wanton and willful conduct.” People v Gafken, unpublished per curiam opinion of the
Court of Appeals, issued June 18, 2020 (Docket No. 345954), p 5 (quotation marks and
citation omitted). However, because Reichard limited its own holding to felony murder,
not second-degree murder, People v Henderson, 306 Mich App 1; 854 NW2d 234 (2014),
overruled in part on other grounds by Reichard, 505 Mich 81, remained good law on this
specific point, and defendant could not argue a duress defense. Gafken, unpub op at 5.
Thereafter, defendant sought leave to appeal in this Court. We ordered argument
on the application to address, among other things, “whether the trial court erred in
excluding evidence that the defendant was threatened and of the defendant’s mental state
at the time of the offense[.]” People v Gafken, 508 Mich 961, 962 (2021).
3
II
A
As an initial matter, the majority should not have reached the question of whether
duress applies. “Michigan has long recognized the importance of preserving issues for
appellate review.” People v Carines, 460 Mich 750, 762; 597 NW2d 130 (1999). “ ‘In
our adversary system, in both civil and criminal cases, in the first instance and on appeal,
we follow the principle of party presentation. That is, we rely on the parties to frame the
issues for decision and assign to courts the role of neutral arbiter of matters the parties
present.’ ” Mich Gun Owners, Inc v Ann Arbor Pub Sch, 502 Mich 695, 709-710; 918
NW2d 756 (2018), quoting Greenlaw v United States, 554 US 237, 243; 128 S Ct 2559;
171 L Ed 2d 399 (2008). Accordingly, unpreserved issues are generally not reviewed. See
Napier v Jacobs, 429 Mich 222, 227; 414 NW2d 862 (1987). And this would seem
especially true if the party had, at some point in the proceedings, conceded the issue. Cf.
Mich Gun Owners, Inc, 502 Mich at 709 (noting that the party had stated in this Court that
it was not providing argument on the issue). As we recently explained, reviving
unpreserved claims sends a bad signal to parties. Id. at 710 n 9 (“Granting leave to appeal
under the circumstances presented would send a message that we should and do decline to
send: Abandon an issue in your application for leave to appeal? And definitively distance
yourself from that legal theory at oral argument? Worry not! The Court will revive the
theory for you and give you free rein to try again after hearing oral argument on that
application.”).
4
In the present case, this Court did order argument on the duress defense. But that
was an imprudent mistake. In defendant’s briefing in the Court of Appeals, defendant
waived the duress defense, admitting that it was unavailable:
In the present case, the precluded evidence was not a means of claiming that
Ms. Gafken was innocent of homicide. That would clearly be prohibited by
law. The only issue at trial was whether Gafken was guilty of second-degree
murder or involuntary manslaughter. Clearly the disputed testimony was not
intended to, nor could it, operate as a defense to homicide.
She included this exact same language in her application in this Court. Further, defendant
argued that, to avoid any possible confusion by the jurors, the trial court could have given
a jury instruction stating that “duress was not a viable defense to . . . second degree
murder . . . .” Thus, as opposed to arguing that duress was a defense to murder, defendant
claimed that evidence of Scandalito’s threat could be used to negate the element of intent.
By nevertheless taking up the duress-defense issue and deciding it in defendant’s favor, the
Court has acted improperly. 1
1
It is true that the preservation requirement is not an absolute rule and that we sometimes
address unpreserved issues. See Klooster v Charlevoix, 488 Mich 289, 310; 795 NW2d
578 (2011). But that occurs, generally, when deciding the unpreserved issue is
“ ‘ “necessary to a proper determination of a case . . . .” ’ ” Id. (citation omitted). It is not
clear to me how the applicability of the defense here was necessary to deciding the case.
Indeed, the majority does not purport to decide the issue in order to resolve defendant’s
underlying argument—it decides the issue and does not opine on the argument defendant
presented. And while the Court of Appeals below did address the duress defense, its
decision was unpublished and thus not binding. Moreover, it would have been simple
enough to vacate the lower court’s discussion of the issue. Justice WELCH’s concurrence
complains that “it would be unjust” to ignore this issue “merely because of a few sentences
of her appellate attorney’s argument in the Court of Appeals.” Of course, that is exactly
how preservation works—clients generally are held to the representations and choices of
their attorneys in court. See People v Carter, 462 Mich 206, 218; 612 NW2d 144 (2000)
5
B
1
Because the majority reaches the merits of this waived issue, however, I will do so
as well to point out the flaws in its analysis. The majority’s conclusion hinges on the
premise that the duress defense is inapplicable only to intentional murders. Because (as
discussed more below) second-degree murder under a depraved-heart theory is not an
intentional murder, the duress defense applies, according to the majority. The majority’s
premise is simply incorrect and, not surprisingly, is based on loose dicta that does not
reflect any actual holding by any court.
To understand the fulcrum of the majority’s opinion, it is important first to examine
the elements of second-degree murder: “ ‘(1) a death, (2) caused by an act of the defendant,
(3) with malice, and (4) without justification or excuse.’ ” People v Wafer, 509 Mich 31,
40; ___ NW2d ___ (2022) (citation omitted). All forms of murder require malice. Maher
v People, 10 Mich 212, 218 (1862). For second-degree murder, there are three types of
malice: (1) “the intent to kill,” (2) “the intent to cause great bodily harm,” and (3) “the
intent to do an act in wanton and willful disregard of the likelihood that the natural tendency
of such behavior is to cause death or great bodily harm.” People v Goecke, 457 Mich 442,
464; 579 NW2d 868 (1998). We have also defined the third type of malice as “the intent
to create a very high risk of death or great bodily harm with the knowledge that death or
great bodily harm is the probable result.” People v Dykhouse, 418 Mich 488, 495; 345
(noting that although there are certain rights an attorney cannot waive, a defendant is bound
by many of his or her attorney’s decisions).
6
NW2d 150 (1984). 2 As is clear, an intentional act is a necessary element of depraved-heart
murder. It simply does not require the specific intent to kill.
When this third type of malice is at issue, the offense is known as “depraved-heart
murder.” See Goecke, 457 Mich at 464 & n 24. As described by LaFave, this form of
murder encompasses “[e]xtremely negligent conduct, which creates what a reasonable man
would realize to be not only an unjustifiable but also a very high degree of risk of death or
serious bodily injury to another or to others—though unaccompanied by any intent to kill
or do serious bodily injury—and which actually causes the death of another . . . .”
2 LaFave, Substantive Criminal Law (3d ed, October 2022 update), § 14.4. The Model
Penal Code explains it as homicide that “is committed recklessly under circumstances
manifesting extreme indifference to the value of human life.” Model Penal Code,
§ 210.2(1)(b) (2021). New York’s top court has described it as follows:
[D]epraved indifference is best understood as an utter disregard for the value
of human life—a willingness to act not because one intends harm, but
because one simply doesn’t care whether grievous harm results or not.
Reflecting wickedness, evil or inhumanity, as manifested by brutal, heinous
and despicable acts, depraved indifference is embodied in conduct that is “so
wanton, so deficient in a moral sense of concern, so devoid of regard of the
life or lives of others, and so blameworthy” as to render the actor as culpable
as one whose conscious objective is to kill. Quintessential examples are
firing into a crowd; driving an automobile along a crowded sidewalk at high
speed; opening the lion’s cage at the zoo; placing a time bomb in a public
place; poisoning a well from which people are accustomed to draw water;
opening a drawbridge as a train is about to pass over it and dropping stones
2
For purposes of the discussion of the duress defense, it is irrelevant which definition
applies.
7
from an overpass onto a busy highway. [People v Suarez, 6 NY3d 202, 214;
844 NE2d 721 (2005) (citations omitted).][3]
See also Maher, 10 Mich at 219 (“[T]he act must be prompted by, or the circumstances
indicate that it sprung from, a wicked, depraved or malignant mind—a mind which, even
in its habitual condition and when excited by no provocation which would be liable to give
undue control to passion in ordinary men, is cruel, wanton or malignant, reckless of human
life, or regardless of social duty.”).
Because this form of malice “may be established even absent an actual intent to
cause a particular result,” it is a general-intent crime. Goecke, 457 Mich at 466. In essence,
the “malice is implied when the circumstances attending the killing demonstrate an
abandoned and malignant heart,” i.e., “ ‘when the defendant does an act with a high
probability that it will result in death and does it with a base antisocial motive and with
wanton disregard for human life.’ ” Id. at 467, quoting People v Fuller, 86 Cal App 3d
3
It is worth noting that numerous treatises stretching back to the English common law also
provide as an example of depraved-heart malice the reckless driving of vehicles or horses—
the historical antecedent of the conduct defendant was found guilty of here. See 1 East, A
Treatise of the Pleas of the Crown, p 231 (“Thus, if a person, breaking in an unruly horse,
wilfully ride him among a crowd of persons, the probable danger being great and apparent,
and death ensue from the viciousness of the animal, it is murder.”); 1 Hale, History of the
Pleas of the Crown, p 476 (“A. drives his cart carelessly, and it runs over a child in the
street, if A. have seen the child, and yet drives on upon him, it is murder[.]”); Foster, A
Report of Some Proceedings (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1762), p 263 (“A person driving a
cart or other carriage happeneth to kill. If he saw or had timely notice of the mischief likely
to ensue, and yet drove on, it will be murder. For it was wilfully and deliberately done.
Here is the heart regardless of social duty . . . .”) (capitalization altered); see also Coke,
The Third Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England (London: Rawlins, 1680), p 57
(explaining under the English common law that “[i]f a man knowing that many people
come in the street from a sermon, throw a stone over a wall, intending only to fear them,
or to give them a light hurt, and thereupon one is killed, this is murder”).
8
618, 628; 150 Cal Rptr 515 (1978). Depraved-heart murder therefore is not an intentional
homicide in the traditional sense—it is not one in which the defendant actually intends to
kill. 4
The majority uses the lack of intent to kill to distinguish depraved-heart murder
from other types of murder for purposes of the duress defense. A duress defense applies
to excuse a defendant of a crime when the defendant can show:
“A) The threatening conduct was sufficient to create in the mind of a
reasonable person the fear of death or serious bodily harm;
B) The conduct in fact caused such fear of death or serious bodily
harm in the mind of the defendant;
C) The fear or duress was operating upon the mind of the defendant
at the time of the alleged act; and
D) The defendant committed the act to avoid the threatened harm.”
[Reichard, 505 Mich at 88 (quotation marks and citation omitted).]
In Reichard, 505 Mich at 88, we explained the longstanding common-law rule that “duress
was not permitted as an affirmative defense to murder.” Mirroring the common law, our
reference to murder there was not qualified, and elsewhere we “note[d] that several
4
See Suarez, 6 NY3d at 226 (Graffeo, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (“There
is a readily understandable distinction between intentional and depraved indifference [i.e.,
heart] murders—the killer’s state of mind. As we have recognized, a person can act
intentionally by having the conscious objective to cause death, or recklessly by
disregarding a known risk of death, but cannot act with both mental states simultaneously
with regard to the same result. . . . Intentional and depraved indifference murder are also
distinguishable because once the jury determines that a homicide was committed
purposefully, ‘the depravity of the circumstances under which the intentional homicide is
committed is simply irrelevant.’ This is so because an intentional killing is, by its very
nature, ‘ “wanton . . . deficient in [ ] moral sense . . . [and] devoid of regard of the life or
lives of others.” ’ ”) (citations omitted).
9
treatises state more precisely that duress is not an affirmative defense to murder or
intentional homicide, as opposed to homicide generally.” Id. at 90 n 18 (emphasis added).
But we specifically declined to address whether duress applied only to “any form of
homicide . . . .” Id.
2
To the extent we implied any answer to the present question in Reichard, it was in
the negative, i.e., that duress would not apply to second-degree murder. Reichard
explained that the application of duress to first-degree felony murder simply negated the
aggravator element of MCL 750.316(1)(b), which elevates a second-degree murder to first-
degree murder. Id. at 95. But, importantly, we stated that “[w]ith the aggravator element
negated, a prosecutor would still be able to proceed against the defendant on the lesser
included offense of second-degree murder if the evidence supported that charge.” Id. at
95-96. “In other words,” we concluded, “the defendant’s duress defense to the underlying
felony would only prevent the enhancement of second-degree murder to first-degree
murder.” Id. at 96. Addressing this language, federal courts after Reichard have continued
to apply pre-Reichard caselaw from our Court of Appeals holding that duress is
inapplicable to second-degree murder. See Baker v Brewer, opinion of the United States
District Court for the Eastern District of Michigan, issued May 5, 2021 (Case No. 2:15-
CV-11629), p 8 (noting that Reichard stated that duress would only stop enhancement of a
second-degree-murder charge to a first-degree charge and concluding that “[b]ecause
petitioner was charged with, and convicted of, second-degree murder, duress was an
10
unavailable defense in [the] case”), citing People v Dittis, 157 Mich App 38, 40; 403 NW2d
94 (1987).
Nevertheless, the majority misreads the treatises cited in Reichard and a few other
cases to suggest that duress is inapplicable only to intent-to-kill murders. But this facile
use of the sources is seriously flawed, as the majority seems to recognize when it states
that “we are aware of no court that has considered the issue of whether duress can be raised
as a defense to an unintentional homicide.” Indeed, all the cases and sources the majority
cites for support do not even discuss or analyze the matter, let alone decide whether duress
applies to unintentional murders. For example, the court in Cole v State, 221 So 3d 534,
543 n 4 (Fla, 2017), observed in a footnote that “duress is not a defense to intentional
homicide,” but the opinion does not address at all the applicability of the defense to any
form of homicide, much less murders in which the defendant lacks an intent to kill.
(Quotation marks and citation omitted.) The charges in that case involved premeditated
first-degree murder and felony murder. Id. In rejecting the defendant’s assertion that his
trial counsel was ineffective for developing a duress defense, the court examined the
strategic merits of pursuing such a defense based on the facts in that case and the effect of
failing to pursue the defense. Id. at 543-544. The opinion has absolutely nothing to do
with the issue we face here.
Or consider the majority’s truncated quotation of a leading treatise, 2 LaFave,
Substantive Criminal Law (3d ed, October 2022 update), § 9.7(b). The full discussion
states:
But the case law in the absence of statute has generally held that duress
cannot excuse murder—or, as it is better expressed (since duress may excuse
the underlying felony for what would otherwise be a felony murder), duress
11
cannot excuse the intentional killing of (or attempt to kill) an innocent third
person. [Id.]
The author’s limitation to intentional killings was obviously not intended to address all
forms of murder, but instead felony murder. Again, as the majority notes, no court has
addressed this issue, and thus none of the citations in the treatise supports the proposition
that duress can apply to unintentional killings. 5
The majority then limply asserts that other authorities suggesting a broader rule—
“that duress is not a defense to ‘murder’ without qualification”—“generally . . . involve[]
interpretation of a statute providing under what terms a duress defense can be raised.” This
is incorrect. Neither of the two common-law treatises (which were not addressing statutes)
quoted in Reichard contained the narrower rule—both suggest duress was inapplicable to
5
Indeed, the treatise cites two cases, one of which is Commonwealth v Vasquez, 462 Mass
827, 835; 971 NE2d 783 (2012). As discussed below, see note 9 of this opinion, Vasquez
indicates that duress is inapplicable even to forms of murder that lack an intent to kill. The
other cited case, Arp v State, 97 Ala 5; 12 So 301 (1893), did not state that the duress
defense is inapplicable only to intent-to-kill murders and did not address murders lacking
an intent to kill.
Perhaps in a mark of what little thought has gone into the present question, some
authorities have interchangeably used both broad and narrow phrasing of the rule, i.e., they
say both that duress is not a defense to murder and it is not a defense to intentional murder
or homicide. See 40 CJS, Homicide (November 2022 update), § 181 (“Generally,
duress . . . is not a defense to a charge of homicide. . . . The rationale for denying the
defense of duress to an intentional killing is premised on the theory that one should risk or
sacrifice one’s own life rather than take the life of an innocent person. The rule
encompasses denial of the defense to all forms of murder, including homicides resulting
from an intent to do grievous bodily harm, as well as an actual intent to kill and seems to
include all other offenses where an intent to kill is an essential element.”); see also Wright
v State, 402 So 2d 493, 498 (Fla App, 1981) (quoting caselaw articulating the broad rule
pertaining to all homicides and then adopting the narrow rule focused on intentional
homicides). Of course, all murders involve intentional acts, and the specific intent to kill
is legally equivalent to the intent required for depraved-heart murder.
12
all killings, which is supported by English caselaw as well. 6 And numerous courts and
other commentators (none of them addressing direct language in statutes) from early in the
common law until the present likewise express the broader rule. 7 Some of the older sources
6
See Reichard, 505 Mich at 88-89 (“ ‘[I]f a man be desperately assaulted, and in peril of
death, and cannot otherwise escape, unless to satisfy his assailant’s fury he will kill an
innocent person then present, the fear and actual force will not acquit him of the crime and
punishment of murder, if he commit the fact; for he ought rather to die himself, than kill
an innocent[.]’ ”) (alteration in original), quoting 1 Hale at 51; Reichard, 505 Mich at 89
(“ ‘Another species of compulsion or necessity is what our law calls duress per minas; or
threats and menaces, which induce a fear of death or other bodily harm, and which take
away for that reason the guilt of many crimes and misdemeanors; at least before the human
tribunal. . . . This however seems only, or at least principally, to hold as to positive crimes,
so created by the laws of society; and which therefore society may excuse; but not as to
natural offences, so declared by the law of God, wherein human magistrates are only the
executioners of divine punishment. And therefore though a man be violently assaulted,
and hath no other possible means of escaping death, but by killing an innocent person; this
fear and force shall not acquit him of murder; for he ought rather to die himself, than escape
by the murder of an innocent.’ ”), quoting 4 Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of
England, p *30. Lord Hale’s treatise more clearly articulated the broader rule. See 1 Hale
at 51 (“If a man be menaced with death, unless he will commit an act of treason, murder,
or robbery, the fear of death does not excuse him, if he commit the act[.]”) (emphasis
added). Citing these treatises and other cases from the English common law, Lord Griffiths
in the House of Lords in 1987—then England’s highest court—observed that “[f]or
centuries it was accepted that English criminal law did not allow duress as a defence to
murder.” R v Howe [1987] AC 417 (HL).
7
See Annachamy v Holder, 733 F3d 254, 260 n 6 (CA 9, 2013) (“Duress does not excuse
murder or even reduce murder to manslaughter. . . . And in many jurisdictions, duress does
not excuse attempted murder or aiding and abetting murder either.”), overruled on other
grounds by Abdisalan v Holder, 774 F3d 517 (CA 9, 2015) (en banc); Sanders v State, 942
So 2d 156, 161 (Miss, 2006) (“[L]ongstanding Mississippi law holds that duress is not a
legal defense to murder.”); 40 Am Jur 2d (November 2022 update), Homicide, § 107 (“It
is generally held that neither duress, coercion, nor compulsion are defenses to murder; nor
does duress mitigate murder to manslaughter.”); Mulroy, The Duress Defense’s
Unchartered Terrain: Applying It to Murder, Felony Murder, and the Mentally Retarded
Defendant, 43 San Diego L Rev 159, 172 (2006) (“The general common-law rule is that
duress cannot be a defense to murder.”); Reed, Duress and Provocation as Excuses to
Murder: Salutary Lessons from Recent Anglo-American Jurisprudence, 6 J Transnat’l L &
13
note that duress was also inapplicable to other crimes not involving killing at all, including
treason and robbery. 8 From this, it would appear that the more prevalent and longer-
established version of the rule is the broader one. 9
Pol’y 51, 58 (1996) (“The virtually unassailable position of Anglo-American common law
has been that duress never excuses murder and that the threatened individual ought to die
himself rather than escape by killing another human being.”); Dressler, Exegesis of the Law
of Duress: Justifying the Excuse and Searching for its Proper Limits, 62 S Cal L Rev 1331,
1343 (1989) (“[T]here is considerable authority or dictum for the proposition that the
defense [of duress] may not be pleaded in murder prosecutions.”); Snowden, Second
Degree Murder, Malice, and Manslaughter in Nebraska: New Juice for an Old Cup, 76
Neb L Rev 399, 445 (1997) (“Nebraska and most jurisdictions do not recognize duress in
a homicide case.”); cf. 1 Wharton’s Criminal Law (16th ed, September 2022 update),
§ 15:9 (“At common law and by statute in many states, a defendant is not allowed to take
the life of an innocent third person even when he is ordered to do so under a threat of instant
death. . . . In prohibiting the duress defense in murder cases, the law demands heroic
sacrifice on the part of the individual . . . .”) (citations omitted); 1 East at 225 (citing Hale
and writing that duress “is no legal excuse” for homicide if another had exerted “moral
force” and made threats against a defendant “in order to compel him to kill” another).
The highest court in Massachusetts—one of the states that the majority cites as
adopting the narrow rule, which is incorrect for many reasons, as discussed below—has
more recently articulated the broad rule, citing the very case the majority here cites as
adopting the narrow rule. See Commonwealth v Concepcion, 487 Mass 77, 94; 164 NE3d
842 (2021) (“The defendant is correct: duress is not a defense to murder.”), citing Vasquez,
462 Mass at 835.
8
See, e.g., 1 Hale at 51.
9
Justice WELCH’s concurrence questions the accuracy of Lord Hale and Lord Blackstone’s
pronouncements on this matter, which have formed the basis for centuries of common-law
jurisprudence. One would think that to mount such an attack, not only must there be
convincing support for the historical assertion but also some rationale for overturning the
last four centuries of law. The concurrence provides nothing of the sort. Instead, it cites a
lone article, Elkington, The Historical Development of Duress and the Unfounded Result
of Denying Duress as a Defence to Murder (Online First publication), J Crim L (2022),
available at [Click
“PDF / ePub”] (accessed December 12, 2022), which addresses the historical use of duress
as a defense for treason in the context of war and rebellion, including in cases in which the
defendant had killed. The scholar infers from this use of the defense that the defense would
14
The majority is further incorrect that no courts have considered this issue. To be
sure, the caselaw on this issue is sparse, and the relevant comments are arguably dicta. But
the courts that have addressed the issue disagree with the majority. In People v Anderson,
28 Cal 4th 767; 50 P3d 368 (2002), the Supreme Court of California rejected the argument
that duress could apply to first-degree murder. The concurring and dissenting opinions,
the Anderson majority observed, argued that “duress especially should be a defense to
implied-malice second degree murder. It evokes the image of an innocent person who is
forced at gunpoint by fleeing armed robbers to drive recklessly, and who is then charged
with murder when a fatal accident ensues.” Id. at 779. The court ruled out duress in these
circumstances, however. It stated, “Accepting the duress defense for any form of murder
would . . . encourage killing.” Id. at 778. And, later in the opinion, the court made the
scope of its pronouncement even clearer: “we conclude that duress is not a defense to any
apply in cases of intentional killings. But treason and murder are different offenses, and
nowhere does the scholar cite a historical case in which the defense was applied to the latter
crime. Murder involves malice, which is a concept not at all mentioned by the scholar or
apparently germane to treason. As explained above and below, malice for murder
represents an express or implied intent to take a life. “The essence of high treason,” by
contrast, “was a treacherous usurpation of or challenge to the king’s royal authority . . . .”
Baker, An Introduction to English History (4th ed, 2002), p 526. The gravamen of the
crimes are clearly different, even if death sometimes ensues during the commission of
treason. Moreover, there are practical and political problems attending the prosecutions of
treason post-rebellion that put further distance between the crimes. Many legal scholars
over the centuries have questioned whether treason should be applied after armed
rebellions. See Nicoletti, Secession on Trial: The Treason Prosecution of Jefferson Davis
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 2017), pp 261-265. In short, it is one thing to
speculate on history in an academic article—it is another altogether to rely on the
speculations when formulating the law for our state.
15
form of murder.” Id. at 780. 10 This has been repeated in numerous subsequent cases. See,
e.g., People v Hinton, 37 Cal 4th 839, 882; 126 P3d 981 (2006) (“ ‘[D]uress is not a defense
to any murder . . . .’ ”), quoting People v Maury, 30 Cal 4th 342, 421; 68 P3d 1 (2003).
The majority here cites Anderson, but only partially, eliding its most relevant parts.
Instead of a full and candid discussion of the case, the majority notes only Anderson’s
suggestion that evidence of duress might still be relevant to determine whether the
defendant acted with the requisite mens rea for murder. The majority therefore provides a
misleading portrait of Anderson by failing to acknowledge that opinion’s entire discussion
of the very issue we are deciding here.
The majority also appears to distinguish Anderson on the basis that it involved a
duress defense enshrined in a statute. See Anderson, 28 Cal 4th at 773, discussing Cal
Penal Code, § 26. But the court held that the statute simply adopted the common-law
defense of duress at the time of enactment. Id. at 774, 780. Significantly, the court noted
that the common-law defense during that period was applicable to all murders. Id.
Although at the time, all murder convictions were punishable by death, the court rejected
the argument that the legislature meant to prohibit use of the duress defense only for
murders subject to the death penalty. Id. at 774-775. 11
The majority also mistakenly relies on Commonwealth v Vasquez, 462 Mass 827,
835; 971 NE2d 783 (2012), to support its narrow view of the rule. Vasquez actually
10
Because the charge at issue in Anderson was first-degree murder, the court’s comments
on other forms of murder were arguably dicta.
11
The court reached this conclusion even though the statute itself only excluded from the
defense a “crime . . . punishable with death . . . .” Cal Penal Code, § 26.
16
discussed almost the precise issue before our Court and reached a conclusion far different
than the majority’s. The court stated, “[W]e hereby reject duress as a defense to
deliberately premeditated murder, murder committed with extreme atrocity or cruelty, and
murder in the second degree . . . .” Id. Under Massachusetts law, malice for second-degree
murder requires an intent to harm, although not necessarily to kill. See Commonwealth v
Estremera, 383 Mass 382, 394-395; 419 NE2d 835 (1981) (“The malice aforethought
necessary for second degree murder requires a finding that the defendant intended to inflict
injury on the victim without legal excuse or palliation. . . . Although the defendant need
not have intended to kill the victim, at the very least he must have intended ‘to do an act
creating a plain and strong likelihood that death or grievous harm will follow.’ ”) (citation
omitted). This is similar to our depraved-heart murder to the extent that neither requires
an intent to kill.
In a similar manner, first-degree murder in Massachusetts under an “extreme
atrocity or cruelty” theory requires proof of malice aforethought and that the murder was
committed with extreme atrocity or cruelty. Commonwealth v Szlachta, 463 Mass 37, 45;
971 NE2d 1281 (2012). Under Massachusetts law, malice is supplied not only by intent to
kill, but also by an intent “ ‘to cause grievous bodily harm, or to do an act which, in the
circumstances known to the defendant, a reasonable person would have known created a
plain and strong likelihood that death would follow.’ ” Id. at 45-46 (citation omitted). No
other intent is necessary. Id. at 47. Thus, it appears that a murder “with extreme atrocity
or cruelty” can lack the intent to kill. This form of murder was at issue because two of the
defendants were convicted of it. As a result, Vasquez’s ruling that duress is inapplicable
17
to these forms of murder would seem to preclude use of the defense even in cases involving
unintentional killings. 12
It appears that the duress defense has been extended to the present circumstances
only by statutes and model statutes. But in many states, the statutes have not extended the
defense to depraved-heart murder. 13 And other states that allow the defense to apply to
12
The court did note, however, that it had statutory authority in certain murder cases to
“direct the entry of a verdict of a lesser degree of guilt” based on “any other reason that
justice may require . . . .” Mass Gen Laws, ch 278, § 33E. The court observed that this
authority might be invoked in these circumstances. Vasquez, 462 Mass at 835.
13
See, e.g., Ala Code 13A-3-30 (“The defense [of duress] provided by this section is
unavailable in a prosecution for (1) murder; or (2) any killing of another under aggravated
circumstances”); Colo Rev Stat 18-1-708 (excluding the duress defense for Class 1
felonies, which under Colo Rev Stat 18-3-102(1)(d) contains a provision analogous to
depraved-heart murder: “[u]nder circumstances evidencing an attitude of universal malice
manifesting extreme indifference to the value of human life generally, he knowingly
engages in conduct which creates a grave risk of death to a person, or persons, other than
himself, and thereby causes the death of another”); Ga Code Ann 16-3-26 (excluding
duress from all murder offenses); Iowa Code 704.10 (excluding any offense pertaining to
“an act by which one intentionally or recklessly causes physical injury to another”); Kan
Stat Ann 21-5206(a) (excluding from the scope of the defense murder and voluntary
manslaughter); La Stat Ann 14:18(6) (excluding murder); Mo Rev Stat 562.071(2)
(excluding murder); Or Rev Stat 161.270(1) (excluding murder); Wash Rev Code
9A.16.060(2) (excluding “murder, manslaughter, [and] homicide by abuse”).
An Arizona court applied such a statute in State v Perez-Perez, unpublished
memorandum decision of the Arizona Court of Appeals, issued January 5, 2010 (Case No.
1 CA-CR 08-0689), p 1, in which the defendant drove away from the police, who were
attempting to conduct a traffic stop—the pursuit ended in an accident that caused the death
of another driver. The defendant claimed that a passenger in his car forced him to flee at
gunpoint. Id. The defendant was charged with first-degree felony murder and second-
degree murder; the jury was also given instructions on manslaughter. Id. The defendant
was found guilty of second-degree murder. In Arizona, this offense is committed “when,
‘[u]nder circumstances manifesting extreme indifference to human life, the person
recklessly engages in conduct that creates a grave risk of death and thereby causes the death
of another person.’ ” Id. (citation omitted). This resembles our crime of depraved-heart
murder. The defendant challenged a jury instruction that duress was not an excuse to this
18
this form of murder limit its effect: duress is not a full defense but only reduces certain
homicide charges to second-degree murder or manslaughter. Minn Stat 609.20 (allowing
the reduction to manslaughter for intentional killings); NJ Stat Ann 2C:2-9 (allowing the
reduction to manslaughter in all cases of murder); Wis Stat 939.46(1) (allowing reduction
of first-degree intentional homicide to second-degree intentional homicide). Other states
would appear to allow the defense in the present circumstances. 14
None of these statutes offers a firm ground for analogy here, not the least because
they are the products of legislative rather than judicial action and thus their rationale is
sometimes more opaque. The Model Penal Code (the MPC), for example, allows the
defense for any charge when there exists “the use of, or a threat to use, unlawful force
against his person or the person of another, that a person of reasonable firmness in his
situation would have been unable to resist.” Model Penal Code, § 2.09(1) (2021). It is not
allowed when, among other things, “the actor recklessly placed himself in a situation in
which it was probable that he would be subject to duress.” Model Penal Code, § 2.09(2)
(2021). But the MPC goes much further than defendant is asking for here, and it is directly
contrary to our law. Yet, it also contains a key restriction on use of the defense that the
charge. The appellate court upheld the instruction, noting that under statutory law, duress
was not a defense to any homicide. Id. at 2, citing Ariz Rev Stat Ann 13-412(C) (“The
defense provided by subsection A [duress] is unavailable for offenses involving homicide
or serious physical injury.”).
14
Some states simply exclude the duress defense for crimes punishable by death. See, e.g.,
Idaho Code 18-201(4); Mont Code Ann 45-5-102(2), citing Mont Code Ann 56-18-222;
Nev Rev Stat 194.010(8). Arguably by excluding the defense from certain crimes, an
implication arises that it would be allowed for other crimes.
19
majority has not seen fit to craft here: that defendants not be reckless in placing themselves
into positions that might involve duress. The majority appears to reject by silence this
prudent and reasonable limitation on the defense.
3
Perhaps lost in the majority’s quibbling about the phrasing of the rule is any
persuasive rationale for recognizing duress as a defense to unintentional murders. I do not
see one.
Most importantly, the malice necessary for depraved-heart murder—which, as
explained above, is an implied malice arising from an actor’s disregard for the high risk of
death posed by his or her conduct—has long been viewed as equivalent to an express
malice consisting of an intent to kill. As one scholar described the development of this
view, the concept of “malice aforethought . . . originally may have meant more or less what
it sounds like—a deliberate, planned killing.” Michaels, Acceptance: The Missing Mental
State, 71 S Cal L Rev 953, 1003 (1998). But soon, the concept of malice was extended
beyond that limited category to killings marked by recklessness or an intent to do great
bodily harm. Moreland, The Law of Homicide (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Co, 1952),
pp 13-15. Courts “concluded [these] killings that perhaps could not literally be described
as including malice aforethought were nonetheless bad enough to ‘deserve the extreme
penalty’ . . . .” Acceptance, 71 S Cal L Rev at 1003 (citation omitted).
With regard to depraved-heart murder, the process was straightforward.
Misadventure had long been an established defense to homicide. Law of Homicide, p 14.
It provided a defense for many unintentional homicides. But Lord Coke established two
20
limitations on the defense, which had the effect of extending the murder offense to
situations that would encompass depraved-heart murder. Id. at 14-15. 15 For the
misadventure defense, the killing had to occur while the defendant was engaged in a lawful
act and without evil intent. Id. at 14-15, 256; see also Black’s Law Dictionary (11th ed)
(defining “misadventure” as “[h]omicide committed accidentally by a person doing a
lawful act and having no intent to injure”). Thus, Lord Coke explained, “If a man knowing
that many people come in the street from a Sermon, throw a stone over a wall, intending
only to fear them, or to give them a light hurt, and thereupon one is killed, this is murder[.]”
Coke, The Third Part of the Institutes of the Laws of England (London: Rawlins, 1680),
p 57. This was because “he had an ill intent, though that intent extended not to death, and
though he knew not the party slain.” Id.
Accordingly, “[s]ome killings that were not purposeful or knowing . . . were added
to the murder category under the rubric of ‘implied’ malice, including a category of
‘depraved heart’ murders, and were treated the same as knowing killings.” Acceptance, 71
S Cal L Rev at 1003 (citations omitted); see also Michaels, “Rationales” of Criminal Law
Then and Now: For a Judgmental Descriptivism, 100 Colum L Rev 54, 75-76 (2000)
(“Depraved heart murder was a residual category designed to capture reckless killings that
were as deserving of punishment as intentional murders.”); Snowden, Second Degree
Murder, Malice, and Manslaughter in Nebraska: New Juice for an Old Cup, 76 Neb L Rev
15
There were earlier cases that also helped lay the groundwork for the rise of implied
malice. See Binder, The Origins of American Felony Murder Rules, 57 Stan L Rev 59, 76-
80 (2004); Second Degree Murder, Malice, and Manslaughter in Nebraska, 76 Neb L Rev
at 407-408.
21
399, 407-408 (1997) (noting that the category of implied malice “fit[] the older types of
murders (that were not premeditated) under the ‘with malice aforethought’ requirement”
and that this reflected the moral sentiments of the courts). This was the common law that
was received by the United States upon independence. Acceptance, 71 S Cal L Rev at
1003; see generally Const 1963, art 3, § 7 (“The common law and the statute laws now in
force, not repugnant to this constitution, shall remain in force until they expire by their own
limitations, or are changed, amended or repealed.”). This remained true even when in the
eighteenth century some jurisdictions began dividing murder into degrees, and it was part
of the common law incorporated into the law of the United States upon independence.
Acceptance, 71 S Cal L Rev at 1004 n 183.
The principle underlying this extension was that the malice necessary for depraved-
heart murder was equivalent to that necessary for intent-to-kill murders. After Coke’s
treatise, “[l]ater writers in texts and decisions state[d] that such an individual has a
‘depraved mind and a heart devoid of social duty’ and should be guilty of murder equally
with the felon who kills intentionally.” Law of Homicide, p 15 (citation omitted). In one
notable treatise, Sir James Fitzjames Stephen similarly explained that “malice means
nothing but wickedness . . . .” 3 Stephen, A History of the Criminal Law of England, p 56.
Thus, he noted, malice included “reckless indifference as to whether bodily injury was
caused or not,” because “[a]s far as wickedness goes it is difficult to suggest any distinction
worth taking between an intention to inflict bodily injury, and reckless indifference whether
it is inflicted or not.” Id. at 55-56. Others concluded similarly, including the framers of
the MPC, who stated that the MPC’s analogous provision for reckless homicide “reflects
the judgment that there is a kind of reckless homicide that cannot fairly be distinguished in
22
grading terms from homicides committed purposely or knowingly.” Model Penal Code,
§ 210.2, comment 4 (1980); see also id., comment 2 (“It seems clear . . . that some
‘depraved mind’ murders can properly be regarded as exhibiting the same disregard for the
value of human life as intentional homicide and hence as deserving the same serious
sanctions.”); Hawley, The Criminal Law (Detroit: Collector Publishing Co, 1896), p 139
(“[B]y implied malice is meant that evil and malignant purpose, or state of mind, which
prompts the act resulting in death in a case where there is no evidence of express malice
toward the deceased. . . . In truth, the distinction between express and implied malice is of
little value, and is more likely to confuse the mind than to lead to a clearer understanding
of the crime of murder.”). 16
Courts, including ours, have likewise adopted this logic. In discussing the
differences between manslaughter and second-degree murder, we stated:
It is not necessary in all cases that one held for murder must have
intended to take the life of the person he slays by his wrongful act. It is not
always necessary that he must have intended a personal injury to such person.
But it is necessary that the intent with which he acted shall be equivalent in
legal character to a criminal purpose aimed against life. [Wellar v People,
30 Mich 16, 19 (1874) (emphasis added).]
The highest court in Maryland similarly emphasized that the culpability involved in
depraved-heart murder was as great as that involved in intentional murders:
“ ‘It [“depraved heart” murder] is the form [of murder] that establishes
that the wilful doing of a dangerous and reckless act with wanton indifference
to the consequences and perils involved, is just as blameworthy, and just as
16
In regard to the MPC, it is worth repeating that it allows the duress defense to all murders,
perhaps reflecting the above comments that deny a meaningful difference between
depraved-heart murder and intentional killings.
23
worthy of punishment, when the harmful result ensues, as is the express
intent to kill itself. This highly blameworthy state of mind is not one of mere
negligence. . . . It is not merely one even of gross criminal negligence. . . .
It involves rather the deliberate perpetration of a knowingly dangerous act
with reckless and wanton unconcern and indifference as to whether anyone
is harmed or not. The common law treats such a state of mind as just as
blameworthy, just as anti-social and, therefore, just as truly murderous as the
specific intents to kill and to harm.’ ” [Robinson v State, 307 Md 738, 744-
745; 517 A2d 94 (1986) (citation omitted).]
Cf. Mayes v People, 106 Ill 306, 313-314 (1883) (“[I]t was utterly immaterial whether
plaintiff in error intended the glass should strike his wife, his mother-in-law, or his child,
or whether he had any specific intent, but acted solely from general malicious recklessness,
disregarding any and all consequences. It is sufficient that he manifested a reckless,
murderous disposition,—in the language of the old books, ‘A heart void of social duty, and
fatally bent on mischief.’ A strong man who will violently throw a tin quart measure at his
daughter—a tender child—or a heavy beer glass in a direction that he must know will
probably cause it to hit his wife, sufficiently manifests malice in general to render his act
murderous when death is the consequence of it. He may have intended some other result,
but he is responsible for the actual result.”).
Malice, therefore, was a holistic concept that, although it could be classed as express
or implied, was not subject to division into different degrees of culpability based on
whether the killing was intentional or unintentional. Cf. 3 Holdsworth, A History of
English Law, p 259 (“This expression ‘malice aforethought’ gradually comes to be the
description of the worst form of felonious homicide; and, from the latter part of the
fourteenth century, homicide of this kind comes to be known by the name of murder[.]”).
One writer accordingly defined malice without regard to intent to kill, noting that such an
intent is not implied by malice. Hughes, A Treatise on Criminal Law and Procedure, p 72
24
(“[Malice] does not imply ill-will or hatred, but, on the other hand, is something more than
mere criminal intent. It does not, however, imply deliberation, nor does it imply intent to
kill.”). At the most basic level, “ ‘malice in murder means knowledge of such
circumstances that according to common experience there is a plain and strong likelihood
that death will follow the contemplated act . . . .’ ” Id., quoting Commonwealth v Chance,
174 Mass 245, 252; 54 NE 551 (1899). Accordingly, for centuries, malice was seen as
“not so much malevolence to the individual in particular, as an evil design in general, the
dictate of a wicked, depraved and malignant heart.” Hughes, p 73. 17
17
See also 1 Michie, A Treatise on the Law of Homicide, § 11(2), pp 77-78 (“[M]alice as
essential to the crime of murder has a more extended meaning, and is, or better say is
characterized and manifested by, the intentional doing of a wrongful act towards another
without legal excuse or justification, which may probably result in depriving such person
of his life, and is not confined to an intention to take away the life of such person.”)
(citations omitted); 1 East at 214-215 (“[T]he sense of [the] word malice is not only
confined to a particular ill-will to the deceased, but is intended to denote, as Mr. Justice
Foster expresses it, an action flowing from a wicked and corrupt motive, a thing done malo
animo, where the act has been attended with such circumstances as carry in them the plain
indications of an heart regardless of social duty and fatally bent upon mischief.”); A Report
of Some Proceedings, p 256 (“When the law maketh use of the term malice aforethought
as descriptive of the crime of murder, it is not to be understood in that narrow restrained
sense to which the modern use of the word malice is apt to lead one, a principle of
malevolence to particulars. For the law by the term malice in this instance meaneth that
the fact hath been attended with such circumstances as are the ordinary symptoms of a
wicked, depraved, malignant spirit.”) (capitalization altered); cf. 4 Blackstone,
Commentaries on the Laws of England, p *197 (“If a man . . . does such an act, of which
the probable consequence may be, and eventually is, death; such killing may be murder,
although no stroke be struck by himself, and no killing may be primarily intended[.]”).
Even those who have suggested that the concept of malice has shifted from “an
underlying evil motive” to a “specific immediate intent” nonetheless recognize that malice
extends to the intent “not to kill or even to injure, but to do some act with cause to know
that it unwarrantably endangers human life . . . .” Sayre, Mens Rea, 45 Harv L Rev 974,
1019 n 184 (1932).
25
Under this reasoning, the presence of malice was seen as precluding any legal
excuse, of which duress is an example. See People v Luther, 394 Mich 619, 622; 232
NW2d 184 (1975) (explaining that “[a] successful duress defense excuses the defendant
from criminal responsibility”). One treatise quoted a 1484 decision in which the court
stated that “ ‘in the legal acceptation it [i.e., malice] imports a wickedness which includes
a circumstance attending an act that cuts off all excuse.’ ” 3 Stephen at 72 (citation
omitted). Caselaw from this state has similarly linked implied malice—such as that under
depraved-heart murder—to an intent to kill and explained that such malice is not
susceptible to legal excuses. In People v Potter, 5 Mich 1, 9 (1858), we stated:
But, malice aforethought is as much an essential ingredient of murder in the
second degree, as in that of the first. Without this, the killing would be only
manslaughter, if criminal at all. Now, malice aforethought is either express
or implied, and there can be no case of murder in the first degree, except
when committed in the perpetration, or attempt to perpetrate, arson, rape,
robbery, burglary, . . . when there does not exist express malice; while, in
case of murder in the second degree, the malice is generally, if not
universally, implied.
As the Court of Appeals has observed of this reasoning, first-degree murder usually
requires an actual intent to kill, “while in second-degree murder [which includes depraved-
heart murder] frequently there is no actual intent to kill and, therefore, generally, if not
universally, the intent to kill is implied.” People v Morrin, 31 Mich App 301, 327 n 39;
187 NW2d 434 (1971), citing Potter, 5 Mich at 9.
The function of this malice, as noted above, is to preclude legal excuses. The Court
of Appeals has stated that “ ‘[m]alice aforethought is the intention to kill, actual or implied,
under circumstances which do not constitute excuse or justification or mitigate the degree
of the offense to manslaughter.’ ” People v Goodard, 82 Mich App 424, 430; 266 NW2d
26
832 (1978), quoting Morrin, 31 Mich App at 310-311. Thus, the malice necessary for
depraved-heart murder prevents the resort to the duress defense. This conclusion reflects
the historical understanding of implied malice, which has always been considered
equivalent to express malice and which is not subject to the duress defense. 18
4
The inclusion of unintentional killings in the category of murder reflects common
moral intuitions and helps explain why depraved-heart murder is distinct from felony
murder in respect to the duress defense. One scholar has explained that “there is no reason
why unintentional killings, specifically depraved-heart killings, should inevitably be
considered less culpable than, or only as culpable as, intentional ones.” Dressler,
Rethinking Criminal Homicide Statutes: Giving Juries More Discretion, 47 Texas Tech L
Rev 89, 97 (2014) (emphasis omitted). “Critically,” he stated, “our generally shared moral
intuition is that someone who demonstrates, by his homicidal act, ‘wickedness, evil or
18
It is true, of course, that our statutes have separated murder into first and second degrees,
with depraved-heart murder falling within the latter category. But this division, originally
arising from Pennsylvania in the 1790s, reflected the fact that murder was punishable by
death. See Potter, 5 Mich at 6-7. The distinction was drawn to separate punishments, not
the basic definition of murder. Id. at 7 (“ ‘No objection was taken to the common law
distinctions [of the types of crimes that all fell within the category of murder]. The general
feeling was, that it was proper that they should remain. The question was one of
punishment, not of definition.’ ”) (citation omitted); see also Nye v People, 35 Mich 16, 19
(1876) (“In dividing murder into degrees, its common-law qualities are not changed, but
(except in special cases) the division is chiefly between cases where the malice
aforethought is deliberate and where it is not.”). Thus, the division of murder into different
degrees stems from the sentiment that some types of murder are deserving of greater
punishment. It does not indicate that the underlying malice of second-degree murder is of
a different nature, such that it would be susceptible to the duress defense.
27
inhumanity,’ or whose conduct is ‘wanton [and] deficient in a moral sense of concern’ for
others, not only should be convicted of murder, but deserves to be treated as more culpable
than some, perhaps many, intentional killers.” Id. at 96 (citation omitted; alteration in
original). As an example, consider two killings, one in which, on a whim, a person throws
a child off a bridge, and another in which a son “carefully plans the mercy death of his
ailing, pain-ridden, terminally ill father.” Id. at 93. The latter killing is planned and
premeditated, whereas in the former, the defendant might not specifically intend any harm.
Yet, “one can easily understand how a jury, if permitted to do so, could find the merciful
son less culpable than the baby killer.” Id. at 97.
This line of reasoning further serves to distinguish depraved-heart murder from
felony murder, which we addressed in Reichard. As noted above, under MCL
750.316(1)(b), felony murder occurs when a murder is “committed in the perpetration of,
or attempt to perpetrate,” various specified crimes, such as kidnapping, torture, a major
controlled substance offense, and unlawful imprisonment. This Court has observed that
felony murder can cover “an accidental killing occurring during the perpetration of a
felony,” which involves less culpability than second-degree murder or even an involuntary
manslaughter. People v Aaron, 409 Mich 672, 708-709; 299 NW2d 304 (1980). A leading
treatise, similarly, has noted that “the risk of death may be much less for felony murder
than is required for depraved-heart murder . . . .” 2 LaFave, § 14.5(e). Indeed, “ ‘ “[t]he
felony-murder rule applies whether a felon kills the victim intentionally, recklessly,
negligently, or accidentally and unforeseeably.” ’ ” Binder, The Origins of American
Felony Murder Rules, 57 Stan L Rev 59, 61 (2004) (citations omitted). In this regard, it is
noteworthy that felony murder exists in this state by virtue of statute, this Court having
28
abolished common-law felony murder because we found “that the malice necessary for a
felony-murder conviction cannot be inferred from the intent to commit the underlying
felony alone.” People v Dumas, 454 Mich 390, 397-398; 563 NW2d 31 (1997). As a
result, it makes sense that duress could apply to felony murder but not to depraved-heart
murder.
5
The last, thin rationale offered to support the result today is that the purpose of the
duress defense is inapplicable to killings in which the defendant lacked an intent to kill.
The majority supposes that, unlike with intentional murder, depraved-heart murder does
not present the defendant with a choice to kill or be killed. Rather, it presents the defendant
with the choice of creating the risk of killing someone or being killed. In other words, the
depraved-heart-murder scenario only creates a probability of killing an innocent. The
suggestion is that creating the risk of death is less blameworthy than intending to cause
death.
The flaw in this argument is its underlying assumption that depraved-heart murder
is materially distinct from intentional murder because the underlying conduct involves only
the risk of death, whereas (presumably) the intentional murder presents the certainty of
death. This is clearly wrong. Even the intentional-murder scenario is unavoidably
probabilistic. Consider that, ex ante, the defendant cannot know with certainty whether his
coercer will actually kill him or a loved one. It is only a probability. And, ex ante, even if
29
the defendant intends to kill the innocent third person, there is only a risk of death—the
defendant might botch the job. 19
In this respect, it is noteworthy that even when a coerced defendant fails to murder
an intended target and is charged with attempted murder, the common law would not allow
that defendant to use the duress defense. See Annachamy v Holder, 733 F3d 254, 260 n 6
(CA 9, 2013) (noting that the duress defense is not available in many jurisdictions for
“attempted murder or aiding and abetting murder”), overruled on other grounds by
Abdisalan v Holder, 774 F3d 517 (CA 9, 2015) (en banc); Cawthon v State, 382 So 2d 796,
797 (Fla App, 1980) (rejecting the duress defense in an attempted-murder charge and
stating that the defense had never been available in Florida for such charges). As the Court
of Appeals has stated, “Given that a defendant may not justify homicide with a claim of
duress, it logically follows that a defendant cannot justify conduct intended to kill simply
because he or she failed in the effort.” Henderson, 306 Mich App at 7, overruled in part
on other grounds by Reichard, 505 Mich at 89 n 18. The rule that duress is inapplicable to
attempted murder demonstrates that the defense is inapplicable even when there is the mere
risk of death, which is precisely the situation with depraved-heart murder. Further, to be
charged with depraved-heart murder, someone must have actually died. Thus, while both
forms of murder include aspects of risk and both result in death, the majority gives a
19
The only possible difference between intentional and depraved-heart murder, then, is
that arguably the risk of death to the innocent third person is marginally higher in the former
than the latter. Perhaps someone who intends to kill is more likely to do so than someone
who creates a high risk of killing. This is a difference, if at all, in degree rather than in
kind. And it is not the sort of difference susceptible to drawing bright lines, as it involves
rough estimates of unquantifiable intuitions.
30
windfall to the defendants who can demonstrate that they consciously disregarded the
others’ lives as opposed to possessing an intent to kill.
There is a further flaw in the majority’s reasoning on this point. For the duress
offense to apply, defendants themselves need not face the threat of death. Rather, duress
applies when the coercion takes the form of the threat of death or serious bodily injury.
Reichard, 505 Mich at 88. In light of the fact, as described above, that the defendant cannot
know ex ante whether he would be killed or seriously harmed, the choice facing the
defendant is the risk of death or serious bodily harm versus compliance with the coercer’s
demands. The majority’s implicit lesser-evil reasoning—i.e., that the defendant’s creation
of the mere risk of killing another is a lesser evil than being killed—breaks down here. For
example, under the majority’s approach, defendants can invoke the duress defense when
their conduct creates a “very high risk of death” even though they were threatened only
with serious bodily harm. Defendants thus can choose what seems to be the greater evil
and nonetheless invoke the defense.
III
For the reasons discussed above, I disagree with the majority’s conclusion in this
case, which the majority only reaches by disregarding defendant’s waiver of the issue in
the lower court. The majority’s conclusion rests on scraps of dicta from cases and sources
that were not considering the issue presented here. The only courts that have addressed the
matter have rejected the majority’s approach. In doing so, those courts better reflect the
history of depraved-heart murder. Though this form of murder does not require an intent
to kill, the malice needed for a conviction has always been viewed as equivalent to such an
31
intent. And there is no other reason in law or logic to treat it differently for purposes of the
duress defense. Certainly, the majority has not offered any such reasons. I therefore
dissent. 20
David F. Viviano
Brian K. Zahra
20
Our order granting argument on the application also requested briefing on “whether the
trial court erred in its instruction to the jury as to the intent element of second-degree
murder[.]” Gafken, 508 Mich at 962. The majority does not address this issue, and neither
would I. Defendant has raised in this Court, for the first time, arguments concerning
whether the standard for malice is objective or subjective. As amicus, the Prosecuting
Attorneys Association of Michigan, contends, we should not address this complicated and
unresolved question when it was not preserved below. At the very least, additional briefing
would be required.
32