Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 1 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
United States Court of Appeals
for the Fifth Circuit United States Court of Appeals
Fifth Circuit
FILED
March 2, 2023
No. 21-11001
Lyle W. Cayce
Clerk
United States of America,
Plaintiff—Appellee,
versus
Zackey Rahimi,
Defendant—Appellant.
Appeal from the United States District Court
for the Northern District of Texas
USDC No. 4:21-CR-83-1
Before Jones, Ho, and Wilson, Circuit Judges.
Cory T. Wilson, Circuit Judge:
Our prior panel opinion, United States v. Rahimi, 59 F.4th 163 (5th Cir.
2023), is WITHDRAWN and the following opinion is SUBSTITUTED
therefor:
The question presented in this case is not whether prohibiting the
possession of firearms by someone subject to a domestic violence restraining
order is a laudable policy goal. The question is whether 18 U.S.C.
§ 922(g)(8), a specific statute that does so, is constitutional under the Second
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 2 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
Amendment of the United States Constitution. In the light of N.Y. State Rifle
& Pistol Ass’n, Inc. v. Bruen, 142 S. Ct. 2111 (2022), it is not.
Zackey Rahimi levies a facial challenge to § 922(g)(8). The district
court and a prior panel upheld the statute, applying this court’s pre-Bruen
precedent. See United States v. Rahimi, No. 21-11001, 2022 WL 2070392 at
*1 n.1 (5th Cir. June 8, 2022). Rahimi filed a petition for rehearing en banc;
while that petition was pending, the Supreme Court decided Bruen. The
prior panel withdrew its opinion and requested supplemental briefing on the
impact of that case on this one. Considering the issue afresh, we conclude
that Bruen requires us to re-evaluate our Second Amendment jurisprudence
and that under Bruen, § 922(g)(8) fails to pass constitutional muster. We
therefore reverse the district court’s ruling to the contrary and vacate
Rahimi’s conviction.
I.
Between December 2020 and January 2021, Rahimi was involved in
five shootings in and around Arlington, Texas.1 On December 1, after selling
narcotics to an individual, he fired multiple shots into that individual’s
residence. The following day, Rahimi was involved in a car accident. He
exited his vehicle, shot at the other driver, and fled the scene. He returned
to the scene in a different vehicle and shot at the other driver’s car. On
December 22, Rahimi shot at a constable’s vehicle. On January 7, Rahimi
fired multiple shots in the air after his friend’s credit card was declined at a
Whataburger restaurant.
Officers in the Arlington Police Department identified Rahimi as a
suspect in the shootings and obtained a warrant to search his home. Officers
1
The facts are drawn from the Pre-Sentence Report, which the district court
adopted, and the factual resume, to which Rahimi stipulated.
2
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 3 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
executed the warrant and found a rifle and a pistol. Rahimi admitted that he
possessed the firearms. He also admitted that he was subject to an agreed
civil protective order entered February 5, 2020, by a Tarrant County state
district court after Rahimi’s alleged assault of his ex-girlfriend. The
protective order prohibited Rahimi from, inter alia, “[c]ommitting family
violence,” “[g]oing to or within 200 yards of the residence or place of
employment” of his ex-girlfriend, and “[e]ngaging in conduct . . . including
following the person, that is reasonably likely to harass, annoy, alarm, abuse,
torment, or embarrass” either his ex-girlfriend or a member of her family or
household. The order also expressly prohibited Rahimi from possessing a
firearm.2
A federal grand jury indicted Rahimi for possessing a firearm while
under a domestic violence restraining order in violation of 18 U.S.C.
§ 922(g)(8), which provides:
It shall be unlawful for any person[] who is subject to a court
order that[:] (A) was issued after a hearing of which such
person received actual notice, and at which such person had an
opportunity to participate; (B) restrains such person from
harassing, stalking, or threatening an intimate partner of such
person or child of such intimate partner or person, or engaging
in other conduct that would place an intimate partner in
reasonable fear of bodily injury to the partner or child; and
(C)(i) includes a finding that such person represents a credible
threat to the physical safety of such intimate partner or child;
or (ii) by its terms explicitly prohibits the use, attempted use,
2
The validity of the underlying protective order, and Rahimi’s breach of it, are not
before us, though the order’s underlying prohibitions, e.g., restraining Rahimi from
committing family violence, from using or threatening use of physical force, from following,
harassing, annoying, abusing, or tormenting his ex-girlfriend, and from going within 200
yards of his ex-girlfriend or her family (including their child), are plainly lawful and
enforceable.
3
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 4 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
or threatened use of physical force against such intimate
partner or child that would reasonably be expected to cause
bodily injury . . . to . . . possess in or affecting commerce, any
firearm or ammunition . . . .
Rahimi moved to dismiss the indictment on the ground that § 922(g)(8) is
unconstitutional, but he acknowledged that United States v. McGinnis, 956
F.3d 747 (5th Cir. 2020), foreclosed his argument.3 The district court denied
Rahimi’s motion, and he pled guilty.
On appeal, Rahimi renewed his constitutional challenge to
§ 922(g)(8).4 Rahimi again acknowledged that his argument was foreclosed,
and a prior panel of this court agreed. See Rahimi, 2022 WL 2070392 at *1
n.1. But after Bruen, the prior panel withdrew its opinion, ordered
supplemental briefing, and ordered the clerk to expedite this case for oral
argument before another panel of the court. Rahimi now contends that Bruen
overrules our precedent and that under Bruen, § 922(g)(8) is
unconstitutional. We agree on both points.
II.
Under the rule of orderliness, one panel of the Fifth Circuit “‘may not
overturn another panel’s decision, absent an intervening change in the law,
such as by a statutory amendment, or the Supreme Court, or our en banc
court.’” In re Bonvillian Marine Serv., Inc., 19 F.4th 787, 792 (5th Cir. 2021)
3
The Government urged Rahimi’s argument was also foreclosed by United States
v. Emerson, 270 F.3d 203 (5th Cir. 2001).
4
Rahimi also asserted that the district court erred when it ordered his federal
sentence to run consecutively to sentences for his state crimes because the underlying
conduct of the state sentences was relevant conduct for the purposes of U.S.S.G. § 1B1.3.
The prior panel affirmed the district court. Because we conclude that § 922(g)(8) is
unconstitutional and vacate Rahimi’s sentence, we do not further address the sentencing
issue here.
4
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 5 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
(quoting Jacobs v. Nat’l Drug Intel. Ctr., 548 F.3d 375, 378 (5th Cir. 2008)).
The Supreme Court need not expressly overrule our precedent. “Rather, a
latter panel must simply determine that a former panel’s decision has fallen
unequivocally out of step with some intervening change in the law.” Id.
“One situation in which this may naturally occur is where an intervening
Supreme Court decision fundamentally changes the focus of the relevant
analysis.” Id. (internal quotation marks and alterations omitted). That is the
case here, as the Government concedes.
In Emerson, we held that the Second Amendment guarantees an
individual right to keep and bear arms—the first circuit expressly to do so.
270 F.3d at 260. But we also concluded that § 922(g)(8) was constitutional
as applied to the defendant there. Id. at 263. “Emerson first considered the
scope of the Second Amendment right ‘as historically understood,’ and then
determined—presumably by applying some form of means-end scrutiny sub
silentio—that § 922(g)(8) [was] ‘narrowly tailored’ to the goal of minimizing
‘the threat of lawless violence.’” McGinnis, 956 F.3d at 755 (quoting
Emerson, 270 F.3d at 264).
After D.C. v. Heller, 554 U.S. 570 (2008), courts coalesced around a
similar “two-step inquiry for analyzing laws that might impact the Second
Amendment.” McGinnis, 956 F.3d at 753 (internal quotation marks
omitted). First, we “ask[ed] whether the conduct at issue [fell] within the
scope of the Second Amendment right.” Id. at 754 (internal quotation marks
omitted). If the conduct fell outside the scope of the Second Amendment
right, then the challenged law was constitutional. Id. But if the conduct fell
within the scope of the right, then we proceeded to the second step of the
analysis, which applied either intermediate or strict scrutiny. Id. at 754, 757
(expressly applying means-end scrutiny). In McGinnis, this court upheld
§ 922(g)(8) using this two-step framework. The initial panel in this case did
likewise, citing McGinnis. Rahimi, 2022 WL 2070392 at *1 n.1.
5
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 6 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
Enter Bruen. Expounding on Heller, the Supreme Court held that
“[w]hen the Second Amendment’s plain text covers an individual’s conduct,
the Constitution presumptively protects that conduct.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at
2129–30. In that context, the Government bears the burden of “justify[ing]
its regulation by demonstrating that it is consistent with the Nation’s
historical tradition of firearm regulation.” Id. at 2130. Put another way, “the
[G]overnment must affirmatively prove that its firearms regulation is part of
the historical tradition that delimits the outer bounds of the right to keep and
bear arms.” Id. at 2127. In the course of its explication, the Court expressly
repudiated the circuit courts’ means-end scrutiny—the second step
embodied in Emerson and applied in McGinnis. Id. at 2128–30. To the extent
that the Court did not overtly overrule Emerson and McGinnis—it did not cite
those cases but discussed other circuits’ similar precedent—Bruen clearly
“fundamentally change[d]” our analysis of laws that implicate the Second
Amendment, Bonvillian Marine, 19 F.4th at 792, rendering our prior
precedent obsolete.
III.
Our review of Rahimi’s facial challenge to § 922(g)(8) is de novo. See
United States v. Bailey, 115 F.3d 1222, 1225 (5th Cir. 1997). First, the court
addresses the Government’s argument that Rahimi is not among those
citizens entitled to the Second Amendment’s protections. Concluding he is,
we then turn to whether § 922(g)(8) passes muster under Bruen’s standard.5
5
The Government also argues that because Bruen endorsed “shall-issue” licensing
schemes, and Texas’s shall-issue licensing scheme (since modified to allow “constitutional
carry,” see 2021 Tex. Sess. Law Serv. Ch. 809 (West)) included the requirement that an
applicant not be under a domestic violence restraining order, it follows that § 922(g)(8) is
constitutional. Of course, the Bruen Court did not rule on the constitutionality of 43
specific state licensing regimes because that was not the issue before the Court. See Bruen,
6
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 7 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
A.
According to the Government, Heller and Bruen add a gloss on the
Second Amendment that restricts its applicability to only “law-abiding,
responsible citizens,” Heller, 554 U.S. at 635, and “ordinary, law-abiding
citizens,” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2122. Because Rahimi is neither responsible
nor law-abiding, as evidenced by his conduct and by the domestic violence
restraining order issued against him, he falls outside the ambit of the Second
Amendment. Therefore, argues the Government, § 922(g)(8) is
constitutional as applied to Rahimi.
The Second Amendment provides, simply enough:
A well regulated Militia, being necessary to the security of a
free State, the right of the people to keep and bear Arms, shall
not be infringed.
U.S. Const. amend. II. Heller explained that the words “the people” in
the Second Amendment have been interpreted throughout the Constitution
to “unambiguously refer[] to all members of the political community, not an
unspecified subset.” 554 U.S. at 580. Further, “the people” “refer[] to a
class of persons who are part of a national community or who have otherwise
developed sufficient connection with this country to be considered part of
that community.” Id. (citing United States v. Verdugo–Urquidez, 494 U.S.
259, 265 (1990)). For those reasons, the Heller Court began its analysis with
the “strong presumption that the Second Amendment right is exercised
individually and belongs to all Americans,” id. at 581, and then confirmed
that presumption, id. at 595. Heller’s exposition of “the people” strongly
142 S. Ct. at 2138 n.9. Rather, the Court merely blessed the general concept of shall-issue
regimes. Id.
7
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 8 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
indicates that Rahimi is included in “the people” and thus within the Second
Amendment’s scope.
To be sure, as the Government argues, Heller and Bruen also refer to
“law-abiding, responsible citizens” in discussing the amendment’s scope
(Bruen adds “ordinary, law-abiding citizens”). And there is some debate
over the extent to which the Court’s “law-abiding” qualifier constricts the
Second Amendment’s reach. Compare Kanter v. Barr, 919 F.3d 437, 451–53
(7th Cir. 2019) (Barrett, J. dissenting), abrogated by Bruen, 142 S. Ct. 2111,
with Binderup v. Att’y Gen., 836 F.3d 336, 357 (3d Cir. 2016) (en banc)
(Hardiman, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgments). As
summarized by now-Justice Barrett, “one [approach] uses history and
tradition to identify the scope of the right, and the other uses that same body
of evidence to identify the scope of the legislature’s power to take it away.”
Kanter, 919 F.3d at 452 (Barrett, J., dissenting). The Government’s
argument that Rahimi falls outside the community covered by the Second
Amendment rests on the first approach. But it runs headlong into Heller and
Bruen, which we read to espouse the second one.
That reading, in turn, leads us to conclude that, in context, Heller
simply uses “law-abiding, responsible citizens” as shorthand in explaining
that its holding (that the amendment codifies an individual right to keep and
bear arms) should not “be taken to cast doubt on longstanding prohibitions
on the possession of firearms by felons and the mentally ill, or laws forbidding
the carrying of firearms in sensitive places such as schools and government
buildings . . . .” 554 U.S. at 626–27; accord Range v. Attorney Gen., 53 F.4th
262, 266 (3d Cir. 2022) (upholding 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(1), which prohibits
firearm possession by convicted felons, because “the people” categorically
“excludes those who have demonstrated disregard for the rule of law through
the commission of felony and felony-equivalent offenses”), reh’g en banc
granted, opinion vacated, 56 F.4th 992 (3d Cir. 2023). In other words, Heller’s
8
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 9 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
reference to “law-abiding, responsible” citizens meant to exclude from the
Court’s discussion groups that have historically been stripped of their
Second Amendment rights, i.e., groups whose disarmament the Founders
“presumptively” tolerated or would have tolerated. See 554 U.S. at 627, n.26
(“We identify these presumptively lawful regulatory measures only as
examples; our list does not purport to be exhaustive.”). Bruen’s reference to
“ordinary, law-abiding” citizens is no different. See 142 S. Ct. at 2134.
From the record before us, Rahimi did not fall into any such group at
the time he was charged with violating § 922(g)(8), so the “strong
presumption” that he remained among “the people” protected by the
amendment holds. When he was charged, Rahimi was subject to an agreed
domestic violence restraining order that was entered in a civil proceeding.
That alone does not suffice to remove him from the political community
within the amendment’s scope. And, while he was suspected of other criminal
conduct at the time, Rahimi was not a convicted felon or otherwise subject to
another “longstanding prohibition[] on the possession of firearms” that
would have excluded him. Heller, 554 U.S. at 626–27; see Range, 53 F.4th at
273 (concluding that Heller, McDonald v. City of Chicago, Ill., 561 U.S. 742
(2010), and Bruen support that criminals, as a group, “fall[] outside ‘the
people’ . . . and that § 922(g)(1) is well-rooted in the nation’s history and
tradition of firearm regulation”).6
6
This discussion is not to cast doubt on firearm restrictions that attach during
criminal proceedings prior to conviction. E.g., 18 U.S.C. § 922(n) (prohibiting person
under indictment from shipping, transporting, or receiving any firearm); 18 U.S.C.
§ 3142(c)(B)(viii) (allowing judicial officer to require person released on pretrial bond to
“refrain from possessing a firearm, destructive device, or other dangerous weapon”).
Those restrictions are not before us. We simply hew carefully to the Supreme Court’s
delineation of who falls within, and without, the overarching class of “law-abiding,
responsible citizens” covered by the Second Amendment.
9
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 10 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
Indeed, the upshot of the Government’s argument is that the Second
Amendment right can be readily divested, such that “a person could be in
one day and out the next: . . . his rights would be stripped as a self-executing
consequence of his new status.” Kanter, 919 F.3d at 452 (Barrett, J.,
dissenting). But this turns the typical way of conceptualizing constitutional
rights on its head. And the Government’s argument reads the Supreme
Court’s “law-abiding” gloss so expansively that it risks swallowing the text
of the amendment. Cf. Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2156 (“The constitutional right
to bear arms in public for self-defense is not ‘a second-class right, subject to
an entirely different body of rules than the other Bill of Rights guarantees.’”
(quoting McDonald, 561 U.S. at 780)).
Further, the Government’s proffered interpretation of “law-abiding”
admits to no true limiting principle. Under the Government’s reading,
Congress could remove “unordinary” or “irresponsible” or “non-law-
abiding” people—however expediently defined—from the scope of the
Second Amendment. Could speeders be stripped of their right to keep and
bear arms? Political nonconformists? People who do not recycle or drive an
electric vehicle? One easily gets the point: Neither Heller nor Bruen
countenances such a malleable scope of the Second Amendment’s
protections; to the contrary, the Supreme Court has made clear that “the
Second Amendment right is exercised individually and belongs to all
Americans,” Heller, 554 U.S. at 581. Rahimi, while hardly a model citizen, is
nonetheless among “the people” entitled to the Second Amendment’s
guarantees, all other things equal.
B.
Which brings us to the question of whether Rahimi’s right to keep and
bear arms may be constitutionally restricted by operation of § 922(g)(8). The
parties dispute Rahimi’s burden necessary to sustain his facial challenge to
10
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 11 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
the statute. The Government contends that Rahimi “must establish that no
set of circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid.” United
States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 745 (1987). Rahimi contests that assertion,
asserting during oral argument that the Government’s interpretation of
Salerno has fallen out of favor, though he contends that in any event, he has
satisfied Salerno’s standard.
Bruen instructs how to proceed. The plaintiffs there levied a facial
challenge to New York’s public carry licensing regime. 142 S. Ct. at 2122.
To evaluate the challenged law, the Supreme Court employed a historical
analysis, aimed at “assess[ing] whether modern firearms regulations are
consistent with the Second Amendment’s text and historical
understanding.” Id. at 2131. Construing Heller, the Court flatly rejected any
means-end scrutiny as part of this analysis, id. at 2129, such that if a statute
is inconsistent with the Second Amendment’s text and historical
understanding, then it falls under any circumstances. Cf. Salerno, 481 U.S.
at 745; Freedom Path, Inc. v. Internal Revenue Serv., 913 F.3d 503, 508 (5th Cir.
2019) (“A facial challenge to a statute considers only the text of the statute
itself, not its application to the particular circumstances of an individual.”
(cleaned up)).
Bruen articulated two analytical steps: First, courts must determine
whether “the Second Amendment’s plain text covers an individual’s
conduct[.]” 142 S. Ct. at 2129–30. If so, then the “Constitution
presumptively protects that conduct,” and the Government “must justify its
regulation by demonstrating that it is consistent with the Nation’s historical
tradition of firearm regulation.” Id. at 2130. “Only then may a court
conclude that the individual’s conduct falls outside the Second
Amendment’s unqualified command.” Id. (internal quotation marks
omitted).
11
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 12 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
To carry its burden, the Government must point to “historical
precedent from before, during, and even after the founding [that] evinces a
comparable tradition of regulation.” Id. at 2131–32 (internal quotation marks
omitted). “[W]e are not obliged to sift the historical materials for evidence
to sustain [§ 922(g)(8)]. That is [the Government’s] burden.” Id. at 2150.
The Government need not identify a “historical twin”; rather, a
“well-established and representative historical analogue” suffices. Id. at
2133. The Supreme Court distilled two metrics for courts to compare the
Government’s proffered analogues against the challenged law: how the
challenged law burdens the right to armed self-defense, and why the law
burdens that right. Id. (citing McDonald, 561 U.S. at 767, and Heller, 544 U.S.
at 599). “[W]hether modern and historical regulations impose a comparable
burden on the right of armed self-defense and whether that burden is
comparably justified are central considerations when engaging in an
analogical inquiry.” Id. (internal quotation marks and emphasis omitted).
As to the degree of similarity required, “analogical reasoning under
the Second Amendment is neither a regulatory straightjacket nor a regulatory
blank check.” Id. “[C]ourts should not uphold every modern law that
remotely resembles a historical analogue, because doing so risks endorsing
outliers that our ancestors would never have accepted.” Id. (internal
quotation marks, alterations, and citations omitted). On the other hand,
“even if a modern-day regulation is not a dead ringer for historical
precursors, it still may be analogous enough to pass constitutional muster.”
Id. The core question is whether the challenged law and proffered analogue
are “relevantly similar.” Id. at 2132.
When the challenged regulation addresses a “general societal problem
that has persisted since the 18th century, the lack of a distinctly similar
historical regulation addressing that problem is relevant evidence that the
12
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 13 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
challenged regulation is inconsistent with the Second Amendment.” Id. at
2131. Moreover, “if earlier generations addressed the societal problem, but
did so through materially different means, that also could be evidence that a
modern regulation is unconstitutional.” Id.
C.
Rahimi’s possession of a pistol and a rifle easily falls within the
purview of the Second Amendment. The amendment grants him the right
“to keep” firearms, and “possession” is included within the meaning of
“keep.” See id. at 2134–35. And it is undisputed that the types of firearms
that Rahimi possessed are “in common use,” such that they fall within the
scope of the amendment. See id. at 2143 (“[T]he Second Amendment
protects only the carrying of weapons that are those ‘in common use at the
time,’ as opposed to those that ‘are highly unusual in society at large.’”)
(quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 627)). Thus, Bruen’s first step is met, and the
Second Amendment presumptively protects Rahimi’s right to keep the
weapons officers discovered in his home. See id. at 2126.
But Rahimi, like any other citizen, may have forfeited his Second
Amendment rights if his conduct ran afoul of a “lawful regulatory
measure[]” “prohibiting . . . the possession of firearms,” Heller, 554 U.S. at
626–27 & 627 n.26, that is consistent with “the historical tradition that
delimits the outer bounds of the right to keep and bear arms,” Bruen, 142 S.
Ct. at 2127. The question turns on whether § 922(g)(8) falls within that
historical tradition, or outside of it.
To reiterate, the statute makes it unlawful
for any person[] who is subject to a court order that[:] (A) was
issued after a hearing of which such person received actual
notice, and at which such person had an opportunity to
participate; (B) restrains such person from harassing, stalking,
13
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 14 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
or threatening an intimate partner of such person or child of
such intimate partner or person, or engaging in other conduct
that would place an intimate partner in reasonable fear of bodily
injury to the partner or child; and (C)(i) includes a finding that
such person represents a credible threat to the physical safety
of such intimate partner or child; or (ii) by its terms explicitly
prohibits the use, attempted use, or threatened use of physical
force against such intimate partner or child that would
reasonably be expected to cause bodily injury . . . to . . . possess
in or affecting commerce, any firearm or ammunition . . . .
§ 922(g)(8); see McGinnis, 956 F.3d at 758 (stating that § 922(g)(8)’s purpose
is to reduce “domestic gun abuse”). Distilled to its essence, the provision
operates to deprive an individual of his right to possess (i.e., “to keep”)
firearms once a court enters an order, after notice and a hearing, that restrains
the individual “from harassing, stalking, or threatening an intimate partner”
or the partner’s child. The order can rest on a specific finding that the
restrained individual poses a “credible threat” to an intimate partner or her
child. Or it may simply include a general prohibition on the use, attempted
use, or threatened use of physical force reasonably expected to cause bodily
injury. The covered individual forfeits his Second Amendment right for the
duration of the court’s order. This is so even when the individual has not
been criminally convicted or accused of any offense and when the underlying
proceeding is merely civil in nature.
These characteristics crystallize “how” and “why” § 922(g)(8)
“burden[s] a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed self-defense.” Bruen, 142
S. Ct. at 2133. In particular, we focus on these key features of the statute:
(1) forfeiture of the right to possess weapons (2) after a civil proceeding 7
7
The distinction between a criminal and civil proceeding is important because
criminal proceedings have afforded the accused substantial protections throughout our
Nation’s history. In crafting the Bill of Rights, the Founders were plainly attuned to
14
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 15 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
(3) in which a court enters a protective order based on a finding of a “credible
threat” to another specific person, or that includes a blanket prohibition on
the use, of threatened use, of physical force, (4) in order to protect that
person from “domestic gun abuse.” The first three aspects go to how the
statute accomplishes its goal; the fourth is the statute’s goal, the why.
To sustain § 922(g)(8)’s burden on Rahimi’s Second Amendment
right, the Government bears the burden of proffering “relevantly similar”
historical regulations that imposed “a comparable burden on the right of
armed self-defense” that were also “comparably justified.” Id. at 2132–33.
And “when it comes to interpreting the Constitution, not all history is
created equal. Constitutional rights are enshrined with the scope they were
understood to have when the people adopted them.” Id. at 2136 (internal
quotation marks omitted). We thus afford greater weight to historical
analogues more contemporaneous to the Second Amendment’s ratification.
The Government offers potential historical analogues to § 922(g)(8)
that fall generally into three categories: (1) English and American laws (and
sundry unadopted proposals to modify the Second Amendment) providing
for disarmament of “dangerous” people, (2) English and American “going
armed” laws, and (3) colonial and early state surety laws. We discuss in turn
why each of these historical regulations falters as “relevantly similar”
precursors to § 922(g)(8).
preservation of these protections. See U.S. Const. amend. IV; U.S. Const. amend. V;
U.S. Const. amend. VI; U.S. Const. amend. VIII. It is therefore significant that
§ 922(g)(8) works to eliminate the Second Amendment right of individuals subject merely
to civil process.
15
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 16 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
1.
The Government relies on laws of varying antiquity as evidence of its
“dangerousness” analogues. We sketch these chronologically, mindful that
greater weight attaches to laws nearer in time to the Second Amendment’s
ratification.
Under the English Militia Act of 1662, officers of the Crown could
“seize all arms in the custody or possession of any person” whom they
“judge[d] dangerous to the Peace of the Kingdom.” 13 & 14 Car. 2, c.3, § 13
(1662). Citing scholarship, the Government thus posits that “by the time of
American independence, England had established a well-practiced tradition
of disarming dangerous persons—violent persons and disaffected persons
perceived as threatening to the crown.” Joseph G.S. Greenlee, The Historical
Justification for Prohibiting Dangerous Persons from Possessing Firearms, 20
Wyo. L. Rev. 249, 261 (2020).
But the Militia Act’s provenance demonstrates that it is not a
forerunner of our Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation. Under
Charles I (who reigned 1625–1649), the Crown and Parliament contested for
control of the militia. Nelson Lund, The Past and Future of the Individual’s
Right to Arms, 31 Ga. L. Rev. 1, 8 (1996). After the resulting civil war and
Oliver Cromwell’s interregnum, the monarchy was restored in 1660 when
Charles II took the throne. Charles II began using the militia to disarm his
political opponents. Id. (citing J. Malcolm, To Keep and Bear
Arms: The Origins of an Anglo-American Right (1994) 35–
38 (1994). The Militia Act of 1662 facilitated this disarmament, which
escalated under the Catholic James II once he took the throne in 1685. Id.;
see Heller, 554 U.S. at 593 (noting that the disarmaments “caused
Englishmen . . . to be jealous of their arms”). After the Glorious Revolution,
which enthroned Protestants William and Mary, the Declaration of Rights,
16
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 17 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
codified as the 1689 English Bill of Rights, qualified the Militia Act by
guaranteeing “[t]hat the subjects which are Protestants may have arms for
their defence suitable to their Conditions and as allowed by Law.” 1 W. &
M., ch. 2, § 7, in 3 Eng. Stat. at Large 441. “This right,” which restricted the
Militia Act’s reach in order to prevent the kind of politically motivated
disarmaments pursued by Charles II and James II, “has long been understood
to be the predecessor to our Second Amendment.” Heller, 554 U.S. at 593.
This understanding, and the history behind it, defeats any utility of the
Militia Act of 1662 as a historical analogue for § 922(g)(8).
The Government next points to laws in several colonies and states that
disarmed classes of people considered to be dangerous, specifically including
those unwilling to take an oath of allegiance, slaves, and Native Americans.
See Robert H. Churchill, Gun Regulation, the Police Power, and the Right to
Keep Arms in Early America: The Legal Context of the Second Amendment, 25
Law & Hist. Rev. 139, 157–60 (2007). These laws disarmed people
thought to pose a threat to the security of the state due to their perceived lack
of loyalty or societal status. See Nat’l Rifle Ass’n of Am., Inc. v. Bureau of
Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms, & Explosives, 700 F.3d 185, 200–01 (5th Cir. 2012)
(discussing relevant scholarship), abrogated by Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126–30.
“While public safety was a concern, most disarmament efforts were meant
to prevent armed rebellions. The early Americans adopted much of that
tradition in the colonies.” Greenlee, supra, at 261.
But we question at a threshold level whether colonial and state laws
disarming categories of “disloyal” or “unacceptable” people present tenable
analogues to § 922(g)(8). Laws that disarmed slaves, Native Americans, and
disloyal people may well have been targeted at groups excluded from the
political community—i.e., written out of “the people” altogether—as much
as they were about curtailing violence or ensuring the security of the state.
Their utility as historical analogues is therefore dubious, at best. In any
17
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 18 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
event, these laws fail on substance as analogues to § 922(g)(8), because out
of the gate, why they disarmed people was different. The purpose of laws
disarming “disloyal” or “unacceptable” groups was ostensibly the
preservation of political and social order, not the protection of an identified
person from the threat of “domestic gun abuse,” McGinnis, 956 F.3d at 758,
posed by another individual. Thus, laws disarming “dangerous” classes of
people are not “relevantly similar” to § 922(g)(8) such that they can serve
as historical analogues.
Finally, the Government offers two proposals that emerged in state
ratification conventions considering the proposed Constitution. A minority
of Pennsylvania’s convention authored a report in which they contended that
citizens have a right to bear arms “unless for crimes committed, or real danger
of public injury.” 2 Bernard Schwartz, The Bill of Rights: A
Documentary History 662, 665 (1971) (emphasis added). And at the
Massachusetts convention, Samuel Adams proposed a qualifier to the
Second Amendment that limited the scope of the right to “peaceable
citizens.” Id. at 681.
But these proposed amendments are not reflective of the Nation’s
early understanding of the scope of the Second Amendment right. While
they were influential proposals, see Heller, 554 U.S. at 604, neither became
part of the Second Amendment as ratified. Thus, the proposals might
somewhat illuminate the scope of firearm rights at the time of ratification,
but they cannot counter the Second Amendment’s text, or serve as an
analogue for § 922(g)(8) because, inter alia, they were not enacted. Cf.
Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2137 (“[T]o the extent later history contradicts what the
text [of the Second Amendment] says, the text controls.”).
18
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 19 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
2.
The Government also relies on the ancient criminal offense of “going
armed to terrify the King’s subjects.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2141 (alteration
and emphasis omitted). This common law offense persisted in America and
was in some cases codified. Id. at 2144. The Government offers four
exemplars codified in the Massachusetts Bay Colony, the state of Virginia,
and the colonies of New Hampshire and North Carolina.
The Massachusetts law provided “[t]hat every justice of the
peace . . . may cause to be staid and arrested all affrayers, rioters, disturbers
or breakers of the peace, and such as shall ride, or go armed
offensively . . . and upon view of such justice or justices, confession of the
party or other legal conviction of any such offence, shall commit the offender
to prison . . . and seize and take away his armor or weapons . . . .” 1 Acts and
Resolves, Public and Private, of the Province of the Massachusetts Bay, 52–
53 (1869) (1692 statute) (cleaned up). Similarly, the New Hampshire statute
authorized justices of the peace “upon view of such justice, confession of the
party, or legal proof of any such offense . . . [to] cause the [offender’s] arms
or weapons to be taken away . . . .” Acts and Laws of His Majesty’s Province
of New-Hampshire: In New-England; with Sundry Acts of Parliament, 17
(1771) (1701 statute); see Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2142–43 (noting that
Massachusetts and New Hampshire laws “were substantively identical”).
Virginia’s law differed slightly: “[N]o man . . . [shall] go []or ride armed by
night or by day, in fairs or markets, or in other places, in terror of the country,
upon pain of being arrested and committed to prison by any justice on his
view, or proof of others, there to a time for so long a time as a jury, to be
sworn for that purpose by the said justice, shall direct, and in like manner to
forfeit his armour to the Commonwealth . . . .” Revised Code of the State of
Virginia: Collection of All Such Acts of the General Assembly of Virginia, of
a Public and Permanent Nature, as Are Now in Force, 554 (1819) (1786
19
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 20 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
statute). North Carolina’s colonial law was contained within its constable’s
oath, which required constables to “arrest all such persons as, in your sight,
shall ride or go armed offensively, or shall commit or make any riot, affray, or
other breach of his Majesty’s peace . . . .” Collection of All of the Public Acts
of Assembly of the Province of North-Carolina: Now in Force and Use, 131
(1751) (1741 statute) (cleaned up). While similarly aimed at curbing “going
armed offensively,” the North Carolina law did not provide for forfeiture.
These proffered analogues fall short for several reasons. An
overarching one is that it is doubtful these “going armed” laws are reflective
of our Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation, at least as to
forfeiture of firearms. See Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2142 (“[W]e doubt that three
colonial regulations could suffice to show a tradition of public carry
regulation.”). North Carolina’s law did not provide for forfeiture, so it
quickly falls out of the mix. And fairly early on, Massachusetts and Virginia
dropped forfeiture as a penalty, going the way of North Carolina and thereby
undercutting the Government’s reliance on those laws. Indeed,
Massachusetts amended its law to remove the forfeiture provision in 1795,
just four years after the ratification of the Second Amendment. 2 Laws of the
Commonwealth of Massachusetts, from November 28, 1780 to February 28,
1807, 653 (1807) (statute enacted Jan. 29, 1795). Virginia had done so by
1847, shortly before the Commonwealth re-codified its laws in 1849. See
Code of Virginia: With the Declaration of Independence and Constitution of
the United States and the Declaration of Rights and Constitution of Virginia,
756 (1849).8 It is unclear how long New Hampshire’s “going armed” law
preserved its forfeiture provision, but assuming arguendo it persisted longer
8
By the 1849 code, Virginia’s going armed law had evolved into its anti-riot law
(chapter 195) and surety law (chapter 201). See id. Neither chapter provided for forfeiture
of an offender’s weapons.
20
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 21 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
than the others, one outlier is not enough “to show a tradition of public carry
regulation.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2142.
And on substance, the early “going armed” laws that led to weapons
forfeiture are not relevantly similar to § 922(g)(8). First, those laws only
disarmed an offender after criminal proceedings and conviction. By contrast,
§ 922(g)(8) disarms people who have merely been civilly adjudicated to be a
threat to another person—or, who are simply governed by a civil order that
“by its terms explicitly prohibits the use, attempted use, or threatened use of
physical force,” § 922(g)(8)(C)(ii), whether or not there is a “credible threat
to the physical safety” of anyone else, § 922(g)(8)(C)(i). Rahimi’s domestic
violence restraining order satisfied both conditions; but it bears emphasis that
the order at issue here was entered by agreement, in a civil proceeding, after
Rahimi apparently waived hearing (the order states no formal hearing was
held, and no record was created), and without counsel or other safeguards
that would be afforded him in the criminal context. These distinctions alone
defeat the “going armed” laws as useful analogues for § 922(g)(8).
Moreover, the “going armed” laws, like the “dangerousness” laws
discussed above, appear to have been aimed at curbing terroristic or riotous
behavior, i.e., disarming those who had been adjudicated to be a threat to
society generally, rather than to identified individuals. And § 922(g)(8)
works to disarm not only individuals who are threats to other individuals but
also every party to a domestic proceeding (think: divorce court) who, with no
history of violence whatever, becomes subject to a domestic restraining order
that contains boilerplate language that tracks § 922(g)(8)(C)(ii). In other
words, where “going armed” laws were tied to violent or riotous conduct and
threats to society, § 922(g)(8) implicates a much wider swath of conduct, not
inherently dependent on any actual violence or threat. Thus, these “going
armed” laws are not viable historical analogues for § 922(g)(8).
21
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 22 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
3.
Lastly, the Government points to historical surety laws. At common
law, an individual who could show that he had “just cause to fear” that
another would injure him or destroy his property could “demand surety of
the peace against such person.” 4 William Blackstone,
Commentaries on the Laws of England 252 (1769). The surety
“was intended merely for prevention, without any crime actually committed
by the party; but arising only from probable suspicion, that some crime [wa]s
intended or likely to happen.” Id. at 249. If the party of whom surety was
demanded refused to post surety, he would be forbidden from carrying a
weapon in public absent special need. See Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2148–49
(discussing operation of historical surety laws). Many jurisdictions codified
this tradition, either before ratification of the Bill of Rights or in early decades
thereafter.9
The surety laws come closer to being “relevantly similar” to
§ 922(g)(8) than the “dangerousness” and “going armed” laws discussed
supra. First, they are more clearly a part of our tradition of firearm regulation.
And they were “comparably justified,” id. at 2133, in that they were meant
to protect an identified person (who sought surety) from the risk of harm
posed by another identified individual (who had to post surety to carry arms).
9
E.g., 1 Acts and Resolves, Public and Private, of the Province of the Massachusetts
Bay, 52–53 (1869) (1692 statute); Acts and Laws of His Majesty’s Province of New-
Hampshire: In New-England; with Sundry Acts of Parliament, 17 (1771) (1701 statute); 2
Statutes at Large of Pennsylvania from 1682 to 1801, pg. 23 (1896) (1700 statute); 1 Laws
of the State of Delaware from the Fourteenth Day of October, One Thousand Seven
Hundred, to the Eighteenth Day of August, One Thousand Seven Hundred and Ninety-
Seven, pg. 52 (1797) (1700 statute); Acts and Laws of His Majesties Colony of Connecticut
in New-England 91 (1901) (1702 statute); see also Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2148 (stating that at
least ten jurisdictions enacted surety laws between 1836 and 1871).
22
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 23 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
Put simply, the why behind historical surety laws analogously aligns with that
underlying § 922(g)(8).10
Aspects of how the surety laws worked resemble certain of the
mechanics of § 922(g)(8) as well. The surety laws required only a civil
proceeding, not a criminal conviction. The “credible threat” finding
required to trigger § 922(g)(8)(C)(i)’s prohibition on possession of weapons
echoes the showing that was required to justify posting of surety to avoid
forfeiture. But that is where the analogy breaks down: As the Government
acknowledges, historical surety laws did not prohibit public carry, much less
possession of weapons, so long as the offender posted surety. See also id. at
2149 (noting that there is “little evidence that authorities ever enforced
surety laws”). Where the surety laws imposed a conditional, partial
restriction on the Second Amendment right, § 922(g)(8) works an absolute
deprivation of the right, not only publicly to carry, but to possess any firearm,
upon entry of a sufficient protective order. And, as discussed supra,
§ 922(g)(8)(C)(ii) works that deprivation based on an order that “prohibits
the use, attempted use, or threatened use of physical force,” whether there
is a “just cause to fear” any harm, or not. At bottom, the historical surety
10
The parties spar somewhat over the required granularity of the underlying
problem in comparing § 922(g)(8) to proffered analogues. Rahimi contends more generally
that domestic violence was, and remains, a persistent social ill that society has taken
numerous actions against—though not disarmament. The Government counters that
“crime statistics from the founding era are hard to come by,” but that “there is reason to
doubt that domestic homicide was as prevalent at the founding as it is in the modern era.”
To be sure, historical surety laws were not targeted to domestic violence or even more
specifically to domestic homicide. But somewhat abstracting the laws’ justifications, as we
do above the line, strikes us as consistent with Bruen’s instruction that “even if a modern-
day regulation is not a dead ringer for historical precursors, it still may be analogous enough
to pass constitutional muster.” 142 S. Ct. at 2133.
23
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 24 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
laws did not impose “a comparable burden on the right of armed self-
defense,” id. at 2133, as § 922(g)(8).
* * *
The Government fails to demonstrate that § 922(g)(8)’s restriction of
the Second Amendment right fits within our Nation’s historical tradition of
firearm regulation. The Government’s proffered analogues falter under one
or both of the metrics the Supreme Court articulated in Bruen as the baseline
for measuring “relevantly similar” analogues: “how and why the regulations
burden a law-abiding citizen’s right to armed self-defense.” Id.11 As a result,
§ 922(g)(8) falls outside the class of firearm regulations countenanced by the
Second Amendment.
11
Accord David B. Kopel & Joseph G. S. Greenlee, The Federal Circuits’ Second
Amendment Doctrines, 61 St. Louis L.J. 193, 244 (2017) (“[T]here is simply no
tradition—from 1791 or 1866—of prohibiting gun possession (or voting, jury service, or
government service) for people convicted of misdemeanors or subject to civil protective
orders.”); Carolyn B. Ramsey, Firearms in the Family, 78 Ohio St. L.J. 1257, 1301 (2017)
(“Historical support for the exclusion of domestic violence offenders from Second
Amendment protection appears rather thin.”); Keateon G. Hille, The Second Amendment:
From Miller to Chovan, and Why the Marzzarella Framework is the Best Shot Courts Have, 50
Gonz. L. Rev. 377, 392 (2015) (acknowledging that the “prohibition on firearms
possession by domestic violence misdemeanants is not longstanding” and advocating for a
means-ends test); Allen Rostron, Justice Breyer’s Triumph in the Third Battle Over the
Second Amendment, 80 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 703, 741 (2012) (“If longstanding tradition
is the key common characteristic of the items on the Heller list, modern legal innovations
like the ban on guns for domestic violence misdemeanants, however much they may reduce
risks and benefit society, do not qualify.”).
24
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 25 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
IV.
Doubtless, 18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8) embodies salutary policy goals
meant to protect vulnerable people in our society. Weighing those policy
goals’ merits through the sort of means-end scrutiny our prior precedent
indulged, we previously concluded that the societal benefits of § 922(g)(8)
outweighed its burden on Rahimi’s Second Amendment rights. But Bruen
forecloses any such analysis in favor of a historical analogical inquiry into the
scope of the allowable burden on the Second Amendment right. Through
that lens, we conclude that § 922(g)(8)’s ban on possession of firearms is an
“outlier[] that our ancestors would never have accepted.” Id. Therefore,
the statute is unconstitutional, and Rahimi’s conviction under that statute
must be vacated.
REVERSED; CONVICTION VACATED.
25
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 26 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
James C. Ho, Circuit Judge, concurring:
The right to keep and bear arms has long been recognized as a
fundamental civil right. Blackstone saw it as an essential component of “‘the
natural right’” to “‘self-preservation and defence.’” District of Columbia v.
Heller, 554 U.S. 570, 593–94 (2008) (quoting 1 William Blackstone,
Commentaries on the Laws of England 139–40 (1765)). And
the Supreme Court has repeatedly analogized the Second Amendment to
other constitutional rights guaranteed to every American. See, e.g., Johnson
v. Eisentrager, 339 U.S. 763, 784 (1950) (describing the First, Second, Fourth,
Fifth, and Sixth Amendments as the “civil-rights Amendments”);
Konigsberg v. State Bar of Cal., 366 U.S. 36, 49–50 n.10 (1961) (comparing
“the commands of the First Amendment” to “the equally unqualified
command of the Second Amendment”); N.Y. State Rifle & Pistol Ass’n v.
Bruen, 142 S. Ct. 2111, 2126, 2130 (2022) (quoting Konigsberg).
But lower courts have routinely ignored these principles, treating the
Second Amendment as “a second-class right.” McDonald v. City of Chicago,
561 U.S. 742, 780 (2010) (plurality opinion). So the Supreme Court has now
commanded lower courts to be more forceful guardians of the right to keep
and bear arms, by establishing a new framework for lower courts to apply
under the Second Amendment.
“When the Second Amendment’s plain text covers an individual’s
conduct, the Constitution presumptively protects that conduct.” Bruen, 142
S. Ct. at 2129–30. “The government must then justify its regulation by
demonstrating that it is consistent with the Nation’s historical tradition of
firearm regulation.” Id. at 2130. “[T]his historical inquiry that courts must
conduct will often involve reasoning by analogy—a commonplace task for
any lawyer or judge. Like all analogical reasoning, determining whether a
historical regulation is a proper analogue for a distinctly modern firearm
26
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 27 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
regulation requires a determination of whether the two regulations are
‘relevantly similar.’” Id. at 2132. This framework “is neither a regulatory
straightjacket nor a regulatory blank check.” Id. at 2133. It requires the
government to “identify a well-established and representative historical
analogue, not a historical twin.” Id.
Our court’s decision today dutifully applies Bruen, and I join it in full.
I write separately to explain how respect for the Second Amendment is
entirely compatible with respect for our profound societal interest in
protecting citizens from violent criminals. Our Founders firmly believed in
both the fundamental right to keep and bear arms and the fundamental role
of government in combating violent crime.
I.
“[T]he right to keep and bear arms . . . has controversial public safety
implications.” Bruen, 142 S. Ct. at 2126 n.3 (quotations omitted). But it’s
hardly “the only constitutional right” that does. Id. (quotations omitted,
emphasis added). To the contrary, “[a]ll of the constitutional provisions that
impose restrictions on law enforcement and on the prosecution of crimes fall
into the same category.” McDonald, 561 U.S. at 783 (plurality opinion).
So any legal framework that involves any of these constitutional
provisions can have significant and controversial public safety consequences.
A framework that under-protects a right unduly deprives citizens of liberty.
But a framework that over-protects a right unduly deprives citizens of
competing interests like public safety.
Take, for example, the exclusionary rule. See Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S.
643 (1961). Since its inception, the rule has been sharply criticized for over-
protecting the accused and releasing dangerous criminals into our
neighborhoods. It’s often said that nothing in the Constitution requires the
criminal to “go free because the constable has blundered.” Herring v. United
27
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 28 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
States, 555 U.S. 135, 148 (2009) (quoting People v. Defore, 150 N.E. 585, 587
(N.Y. 1926)). “The exclusionary rule generates substantial social costs” by
“setting the guilty free and the dangerous at large.” Hudson v. Michigan, 547
U.S. 586, 591 (2006) (cleaned up).
The same can be said about Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966).
The Supreme Court has “repeatedly referred to the Miranda warnings as
‘prophylactic’ and ‘not themselves rights protected by the Constitution.’”
Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428, 437–38 (2000) (citations omitted).
What’s more, “[i]n some unknown number of cases the Court’s rule will
return a killer, a rapist or other criminal to the streets and to the environment
which produced him, to repeat his crime whenever it pleases him.” Miranda,
384 U.S. at 542 (White, J., dissenting).
So it’s easy to see why decisions like Mapp and Miranda have been
criticized for over-protecting constitutional rights and harming public safety.
But there’s a big difference between the first criticism and the second,
at least as far as the judiciary is concerned. It’s our duty as judges to interpret
the Constitution based on the text and original understanding of the relevant
provision—not on public policy considerations, or worse, fear of public
opprobrium or criticism from the political branches. See, e.g., McDonald, 561
U.S. at 783 (plurality opinion) (finding “no case in which we have refrained
from holding that a provision of the Bill of Rights is binding on the States on
the ground that the right at issue has disputed public safety implications”);
Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Org., 142 S. Ct. 2228, 2278 (2022) (“[W]e
cannot allow our decisions to be affected by any extraneous influences such
as concern about the public’s reaction to our work.”); Mance v. Sessions, 896
F.3d 390, 405 (5th Cir. 2018) (Ho, J., dissenting from denial of rehearing en
banc) (“Constitutional rights must not give way to hoplophobia.”).
28
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 29 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
And that’s precisely the problem here: Members of the Supreme
Court have repeatedly criticized lower courts for disfavoring the Second
Amendment.1 The Supreme Court has now responded by setting forth a new
legal framework in Bruen. It is incumbent on lower courts to implement
Bruen in good faith and to the best of our ability.
Bruen calls on us to examine our Nation’s history and traditions to
determine the meaning and scope of the Second Amendment. It’s hardly the
first time that the Supreme Court has looked to history and tradition to
interpret constitutional provisions.2 And it surely won’t be the last.
1
See, e.g., Silvester v. Becerra, 138 S. Ct. 945, 945 (2018) (Thomas, J., dissenting
from denial of certiorari) (bemoaning “lower courts’ general failure to afford the Second
Amendment the respect due an enumerated constitutional right”); Peruta v. California, 137
S. Ct. 1995, 1999 (2017) (Thomas, J., joined by Gorsuch, J., dissenting from denial of
certiorari) (lamenting “distressing trend” of “the treatment of the Second Amendment as
a disfavored right”); Friedman v. City of Highland Park, 136 S. Ct. 447, 447 (2015) (Thomas,
J., joined by Scalia, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari) (criticizing “noncompliance with
our Second Amendment precedents” by “several Courts of Appeals”); Jackson v. City &
Cty. of San Francisco, 135 S. Ct. 2799, 2799 (2015) (Thomas, J., joined by Scalia, J.,
dissenting from denial of certiorari) (“lower courts, including the ones here, have failed to
protect [the Second Amendment right]”); id. at 2802 (“‘A constitutional guarantee
subject to future judges’ assessments of its usefulness is no constitutional guarantee at
all.’”) (quoting Heller, 554 U.S. at 634).
2
See, e.g., Myers v. United States, 272 U.S. 52, 109–76 (1926) (noting that “the
power of removal of executive officers . . . was presented early in the first session of the
First Congress,” known as the “decision of 1789,” and also surveying English and colonial
history and subsequent Congressional and Executive practice); Marsh v. Chambers, 463
U.S. 783, 786–92 (1983) (noting that “[t]he opening of sessions of legislative and other
deliberative public bodies with prayer is deeply embedded in the history and tradition of
this country” and surveying colonial history, the deliberations of the First Congress, and
“unambiguous and unbroken history of more than 200 years”); Crawford v. Washington,
541 U.S. 36, 43–50 (2004) (examining the “historical background” of the Confrontation
Clause, noting that “[t]he right to confront one’s accusers is a concept that dates back to
Roman times,” and surveying English history and colonial and early state practice); United
States v. Stevens, 559 U.S. 460, 468–69 (2010) (reviewing “historic and traditional
categories” of speech that government has been allowed to regulate “[f]rom 1791 to the
29
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 30 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
II.
Those who commit violence, including domestic violence, shouldn’t
just be disarmed—they should be detained, prosecuted, convicted, and
incarcerated. And that’s exactly why we have a criminal justice system—to
punish criminals and disable them from engaging in further crimes.
The Constitution presumes the existence of a criminal justice system.
See, e.g., U.S. Const. amends. V, VI (setting forth various rights of the
accused in criminal proceedings); U.S. Const. amend. VIII (prohibiting
cruel and unusual punishments). That system allows the government to deny
convicted criminals a wide range of liberties that it could not deny to
innocent, law-abiding citizens. For example, the government cannot deprive
innocent citizens of their liberty of movement. See, e.g., Williams v. Fears,
179 U.S. 270, 274 (1900); City of Chicago v. Morales, 527 U.S. 41, 53 (1999).
But it can certainly arrest and incarcerate violent criminals.
Arrest and incarceration naturally entail the loss of a wide range of
liberties—including the loss of access to weapons. See, e.g., Chimel v.
California, 395 U.S. 752, 762–63 (1969) (“When an arrest is made, it is
reasonable for the arresting officer to search the person arrested in order to
remove any weapons that the latter might seek to use in order to resist arrest
or effect his escape.”); State v. Buzzard, 4 Ark. 18, 21 (1842) (Ringo, C.J.)
(“Persons accused of crime, upon their arrest, have constantly been divested
of their arms, without the legality of the act having ever been questioned.”).
The Supreme Court has also made clear that our Nation’s history and
traditions include “longstanding prohibitions on the possession of firearms
present”); Timbs v. Indiana, 139 S. Ct. 682, 687–89 (2019) (observing that “[t]he Excessive
Fines Clause traces its venerable lineage back to at least 1215” and surveying authorities
from English history and colonial practice).
30
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 31 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
by felons”—and that such measures are “presumptively lawful.” Heller, 554
U.S. at 626 & n.26. See also McDonald, 561 U.S. at 786 (plurality opinion)
(“We made it clear in Heller that our holding did not cast doubt on such
longstanding regulatory measures as ‘prohibitions on the possession of
firearms by felons,’” and “[w]e repeat those assurances here. . . .
[I]ncorporation does not imperil every law regulating firearms.”). So the
government can presumably disarm dangerous convicted felons, whether
they’re incarcerated or not, without violating the Second Amendment.
The Second Amendment is not “a second-class right.” Bruen, 142 S.
Ct. at 2156. It is not “subject to an entirely different body of rules than the
other Bill of Rights guarantees.” Id. That principle guides us here: The
government can impose various restrictions on the rights of dangerous
convicted felons, consistent with our Nation’s history and traditions—and
that includes the right to keep and bear arms.
III.
The power to incarcerate violent criminals is not just constitutionally
permissible—it’s imperative to protecting victims. After all, anyone who’s
willing to break the law when it comes to domestic violence is presumably
willing to break the law when it comes to guns as well. The only way to
protect the victim may be to detain as well as disarm the violent criminal.
For example, the government can detain and disarm, not just after
conviction, but also before trial. Pre-trial detention is presumed by the
Excessive Bail Clause and the Speedy Trial Clause. And it plays a significant
role in protecting citizens from violence, including domestic violence. See,
e.g., United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 755 (1987) (permitting “the
detention prior to trial of arrestees charged with serious felonies who . . . pose
a threat to the safety of individuals or to the community”).
31
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 32 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
In addition, the government can detain and disarm, based not just on
acts of violence, but criminal threats of violence as well. See, e.g., United
States v. Ackell, 907 F.3d 67 (1st Cir. 2018) (upholding criminal stalking law);
United States v. Gonzalez, 905 F.3d 165 (3rd Cir. 2018) (same); United States
v. Osinger, 753 F.3d 939 (9th Cir. 2014) (same); United States v. Petrovic, 701
F.3d 849 (8th Cir. 2012) (same); see also People v. Counterman, 497 P.3d 1039
(Colo. App. 2021) (same), cert. granted sub nom. Counterman v. Colorado, 143
S. Ct. 644 (2023). After all, to the victim, such actions are not only life-
threatening—they’re life-altering, even if they don’t eventually result in
violence.
IV.
18 U.S.C. § 922(g)(8) disarms individuals based on civil protective
orders—not criminal proceedings. As the court today explains, there is no
analogous historical tradition sufficient to support § 922(g)(8) under Bruen.
Moreover, there are additional reasons why disarmament based on
civil protective orders should give us pause. Scholars and judges have
expressed alarm that civil protective orders are too often misused as a tactical
device in divorce proceedings—and issued without any actual threat of
danger. That makes it difficult to justify § 922(g)(8) as a measure to disarm
dangerous individuals.
A.
“Many divorce lawyers routinely recommend pursuit of civil
protection orders for clients in divorce proceedings . . . as a tactical leverage
device.” Jeannie Suk, Criminal Law Comes Home, 116 Yale L.J. 2, 62 n.257
(2006). See also, e.g., Randy Frances Kandel, Squabbling in the Shadows: What
the Law Can Learn from the Way Divorcing Couples Use Protective Orders as
Bargaining Chips in Domestic Spats and Child Custody Mediation, 48 S.C. L.
32
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 33 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
Rev. 441, 448 (1997) (civil protective orders are deployed as “an affirmative
element of divorce strategy”).
That’s because civil protective orders can help a party in a divorce
proceeding to “secure [favorable] rulings on critical issues such as [marital
and child] support, exclusion from marital residence and property
disposition.” Murray v. Murray, 631 A.2d 984, 986 (N.J. Super. Ct. App.
Div. 1993). Protective orders can also be “a powerful strategic tool in custody
disputes.” Suk, supra, at 62.
That makes civil protective orders a tempting target for abuse. Judges
have expressed “concern[] . . . with the serious policy implications of
permitting allegations of . . . domestic violence” to be used in divorce
proceedings. Murray, 631 A.2d at 986. See also City of Seattle v. May, 256
P.3d 1161, 1166 n.1 (Wash. 2011) (Sanders, J., dissenting) (noting “the
growing trend to use protection orders as tactical weapons in divorce cases”).
And for good reason. “[N]ot all parties to divorce are above using [protective
orders] not for their intended purpose but solely to gain advantage in a
dissolution.” Scott A. Lerner, Sword or Shield? Combating Orders–of–
Protection Abuse in Divorce, 95 Ill. Bar J. 590, 591 (2007). Anyone who
is “willing to commit perjury can spend months or even years . . . planning to
file a domestic violence complaint at an opportune moment in order to gain
the upper hand in a divorce proceeding.” David N. Heleniak, The New Star
Chamber: The New Jersey Family Court and the Prevention of Domestic Violence
Act, 57 Rutgers L. Rev. 1009, 1014 (2005). So “[a] plaintiff willing to
exaggerate past incidents or even commit perjury can have access to a
responsive support group, a sympathetic court, and a litany of immediate
relief.” Peter Slocum, Biting the D.V. Bullet: Are Domestic-Violence
Restraining Orders Trampling on Second Amendment Rights?, 40 Seton
Hall L. Rev. 639, 662–63 (2010).
33
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 34 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
Moreover, these concerns are exacerbated by the fact that judges are
too often ill-equipped to prevent abuse. Family court judges may face
enormous pressure to grant civil protective orders—and no incentive to deny
them. For example, family court judges may receive mandatory training in
which they’re warned about “the unfavorable publicity” that could result if
they deny requests for civil protective orders. Id. at 668. As one judge has
noted, “[a] newspaper headline can be death to a municipal court judge’s
career.” Id. at 667 n.213 (quotations omitted). So “the prospect of an
unfavorable newspaper headline is a frightening one.” Id. To quote another
judge: “Your job is not to become concerned about all the constitutional
rights of the [defendant] you’re violating as you grant a restraining order.
Throw him out on the street, give him the clothes on his back and tell him,
‘See ya’ around.’” Id. at 668. Yet another judge said: “If there is any doubt
in your mind about what to do, you should issue the restraining order.” Id.
As a result, “[r]estraining orders . . . are granted to virtually all who
apply.” May, 256 P.3d at 1166 n.1 (Sanders, J., dissenting) (quotations
omitted). So there’s a “tremendous” risk that courts will enter protective
orders automatically—despite the absence of any real threat of danger.
Heleniak, supra, at 1014. See generally Slocum, supra. In one case, for
example, a family court judge granted a restraining order on the ground that
the husband told his wife that he did not love her and was no longer attracted
to her. See Murray, 631 A.2d at 984. “There was no prior history of domestic
violence,” yet the judge issued the order anyway. Id. Another judge issued
a restraining order against David Letterman on the ground that his presence
on television harassed the plaintiff. See Todd Peterson, David Letterman
Fights Restraining Order, People (Dec. 21, 2005).
These orders were later rescinded. But the defendants were
nevertheless prohibited from possessing a firearm while the orders were in
effect, as a result of § 922(g)(8).
34
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 35 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
B.
Moreover, the consequences of disarming citizens under § 922(g)(8)
may be especially perverse considering the common practice of “mutual”
protective orders.
In any domestic violence dispute, a judge may see no downside in
forbidding both parties from harming one another. A judge “may think that
mutual restraining orders are not substantially different from regular
restraining orders—after all, the goal is to keep the parties away from one
another so that the violence will not continue.” Jacquie Andreano, The
Disproportionate Effect of Mutual Restraining Orders on Same-Sex Domestic
Violence Victims, 108 Cal. L. Rev. 1047, 1054 (2020). “Judges may also
feel that issuing a mutual restraining order saves time because they do not
have to hear testimony and make a finding regarding which party is a primary
aggressor or even that one party has committed domestic violence.” Id.
But “[t]hese judicial assessments have often led to the issuance of
unmerited mutual restraining orders, namely in situations where one party is
the abuser and the other party is a victim.” Id. (emphasis added). As a result,
“both parties are restrained even if only one is an abuser.” Id. at 1055
(emphasis added). See also Elizabeth Topliffe, Why Civil Protection Orders
Are Effective Remedies for Domestic Violence but Mutual Protective Orders Are
Not, 67 Ind. L.J. 1039, 1055–56 (1992) (“[J]udges often issue a mutual
protection order without any request from the respondent or his lawyer. . . .
[J]udges and lawyers . . . may be tempted to resort to mutual protective orders
frequently. However, when they do this in cases where there truly is one
victim and one batterer, they ignore some of the real difficulties of mutual
protection orders.”). See generally David Hirschel, Nat’l
Criminal Justice Reference Serv., Domestic Violence
35
Case: 21-11001 Document: 00516662588 Page: 36 Date Filed: 03/02/2023
No. 21-11001
Cases: What Research Shows About Arrest and Dual
Arrest Rates (2008).
The net result of all this is profoundly perverse, because it means that
§ 922(g)(8) effectively disarms victims of domestic violence. What’s worse,
victims of domestic violence may even be put in greater danger than before.
Abusers may know or assume that their victims are law-abiding citizens who
will comply with their legal obligation not to arm themselves in self-defense
due to § 922(g)(8). Abusers might even remind their victims of the existence
of § 922(g)(8) and the entry of a mutual protective order to taunt and subdue
their victims. Meanwhile, the abusers are criminals who have already
demonstrated that they have zero propensity to obey the dictates of criminal
statutes. As a result, § 922(g)(8) effectively empowers and enables abusers
by guaranteeing that their victims will be unable to fight back.
***
We must protect citizens against domestic violence. And we can do
so without offending the Second Amendment framework set forth in Bruen.
Those who commit or criminally threaten domestic violence have
already demonstrated an utter lack of respect for the rights of others and the
rule of law. So merely enacting laws that tell them to disarm is a woefully
inadequate solution. Abusers must be detained, prosecuted, and
incarcerated. And that’s what the criminal justice system is for. I concur.
36