concurring.*
Arizona, Nebraska, and North Carolina have passed laws forbidding agreements to employ only union members. The United States Constitution is invoked against these laws. Since the cases bring into question the judicial process in its application to the Due Process Clause, explicit avowal of individual attitudes towards that process may elucidate and thereby strengthen adjudication. Accordingly, I set forth the steps by which I have reached concurrence with my brethren on what I deem the only substantial issue here, on all other issues joining the Court’s opinion.
The coming of the machine age tended to despoil human personality. It turned men and women into “hands.” The industrial history of the early Nineteenth Century demonstrated the helplessness of the individual employee to achieve human dignity in a society so largely affected by technological advances. Hence the trade union made itself increasingly felt, not only as an indispensable weapon of self-defense on the part of work*543ers but as an aid to the well-being of a society in which work is an expression of life and not merely the means of earning subsistence. But unionization encountered the shibboleths of a pre-machine age and these were reflected in juridical assumptions that survived the facts on which they were based. Adam Smith was treated as though his generalizations had been imparted to him on Sinai and not as a thinker who addressed himself to the elimination of restrictions which had become fetters upon initiative and enterprise in his day. Basic human rights expressed by the constitutional conception of “liberty” were equated with theories of laissez faire.1 The result was that economic views of confined validity were treated by lawyers and judges as though the Framers had enshrined them in the Constitution. This misapplication of the notions of the classic economists and resulting disregard of the perduring reach of the Constitution led to Mr. Justice Holmes’ famous protest in the Lochner case against measuring the Fourteenth Amendment by Mr. Herbert Spencer’s Social Statics. 198 U. S. 45, 75. Had not Mr. Justice Holmes’ awareness of the impermanence of legislation as against the permanence of the Constitution gradually prevailed, there might indeed have been “hardly any limit but the sky” to the embodiment of “our economic or moral beliefs” in that Amendment’s “prohibitions.” Baldwin v. Missouri, 281 U. S. 586, 595.
The attitude which regarded any legislative encroachment upon the existing economic order as infected with unconstitutionality led to disrespect for legislative attempts to strengthen the wage-earner’s bargaining power. *544With that attitude as a premise, Adair v. United States, 208 U. S. 161, and Coppage v. Kansas, 236 U. S. 1, followed logically enough; not even Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U. S. 312, could be considered unexpected. But when the tide turned, it was not merely because circumstances had changed and there had arisen a new order with new claims to divine origin. The opinion of Mr. Justice Brandéis in Senn v. Tile Layers Union, 301 U. S. 468, shows the current running strongly in the new direction— the direction not of social dogma but of increased deference to the legislative judgment. “Whether it was wise,” he said, now speaking for the Court and not in dissent, “for the State to permit the unions to [picket] is a question of its public policy — not our concern.” Id. at 481. Long before that, in Duplex Printing Press Co. v. Deering, 254 U. S. 443, 488, he had warned:
“All rights are derived from the purposes of the society in which they exist; above all rights rises duty to the community. The conditions developed in industry may be such that those engaged in it cannot continue their struggle without danger to the community. But it is not for judges to determine whether such conditions exist, nor is it their function to set the limits of permissible contest and to declare the duties which the new situation demands. This is the function of the legislature which, while limiting individual and group rights of aggression and defense, may substitute processes of justice for the more primitive method of trial by combat.”
Unions are powers within the State. Like the power of industrial and financial aggregations, the power of organized labor springs from a group which is only a fraction of the whole that Mr. Justice Holmes referred to as “the one club to which we all belong.” The power of the former is subject to control, though, of course, the *545particular incidence of control may be brought to test at the bar of this Court. E. g., Northern Securities Co. v. United States, 193 U. S. 197; North American Co. v. S. E. C., 327 U. S. 686. Neither can the latter claim constitutional exemption. Even the Government — the organ of the whole people — -is restricted by the system of checks and balances established by our Constitution. The designers of that system distributed authority among the three branches “not to promote efficiency but to preclude the exercise of arbitrary power.” Mr. Justice Brandéis, dissenting in Myers v. United States, 272 U. S. 52, 293. Their concern for individual members of society, for whose well-being government is instituted, gave urgency to the fear that concentrated power would become arbitrary. It is a fear that the history of such power, even when professedly employed for democratic purposes, has hardly rendered unfounded.
If concern for the individual justifies incorporating in the Constitution itself devices to curb public authority, a legislative judgment that his protection requires the regulation of the private power of unions cannot be dismissed as insupportable. A union is no more than a medium through which individuals are able to act together; union power was begotten of individual helplessness. But that power can come into being only when, and continue to exist only so long as, individual aims are seen to be shared in common with the other members of the group. There is a natural emphasis, however, on what is shared and a resulting tendency to subordinate the inconsistent interests and impulses of individuals. From this, it is an easy transition to thinking of the union as an entity having rights and purposes of its own. An ardent supporter of trade unions who is also no less a disinterested student of society has pointed out that “As soon as we personify the idea, whether it is a country or a church, a trade union or an employers’ association, we obscure *546individual responsibility by transferring emotional loyalties to a fictitious creation which then acts upon us psychologically as an obstruction, especially in times of crisis, to the critical exercise of a reasoned judgment.” Laski, Morris Cohen’s Approach to Legal Philosophy, 15 U. of Chi. L. Rev. 575, 581 (1948).
The right of association, like any other right carried to its extreme, encounters limiting principles. See Hudson County Water Co. v. McCarter, 209 U. S. 349, 355. At the point where the mutual advantage of association demands too much individual disadvantage, a compromise must be struck. See Dicey, Law and Public Opinion in England 465-66 (1905). When that point has been reached — where the intersection should fall — is plainly a question within the special province of the legislature. This Court has given effect to such a compromise in sustaining a legislative purpose to protect individual employees against the exclusionary practices of unions. Steele v. Louisville & N. R. Co., 323 U. S. 192; Wallace Corp. v. Labor Board, 323 U. S. 248; Railway Mail Assn. v. Corsi, 326 U. S. 88; cf. Elgin, J. & E. R. Co. v. Burley, 325 U. S. 711, 733-34. The rationale of the Arizona, Nebraska, and North Carolina legislation prohibiting union-security agreements is founded on a similar resolution of conflicting interests.2 Unless we are to treat *547as unconstitutional what goes against the grain because it offends what we may strongly believe to be socially desirable, that resolution must be given respect.
It is urged that the compromise which this legislation embodies is no compromise at all because fatal to the survival of organized labor. But can it be said that the legislators and the people of Arizona, Nebraska, and North Carolina could not in reason be sceptical of organized labor’s insistence upon the necessity to its strength of power to compel rather than to persuade the allegiance of its reluctant members? In the past fifty years the total number of employed, counting salaried workers and the self-employed but not farmers or farm laborers, has not quite trebled, while total union membership has increased more than thirty-three times; at the time of the open-shop drive following the First World War, the ratio of organized to unorganized non-agricultural workers was about one to nine, and now it is almost one to three.3 However necessitous may have been the circumstances of unionism in 1898 or even in 1923, its status in 1948 precludes constitutional condemnation of a legislative judgment, whatever we may think of it, that the need of this type of regulation outweighs its detriments. It would be arbitrary for this Court to deny the States the right to experiment with such laws, especially in view of the fact that the Railroad Brotherhoods have held their own de*548spite congressional prohibition of union security4 and in the light of the experience of countries advanced in industrial democracy, such as Great Britain and Sweden, where deeply rooted acceptance of the principles of collective *549bargaining is not reflected in uncompromising demands for contractually guaranteed security.5 Whether it is preferable in the public interest that trade unions should be subjected to State intervention or left to the free play of social forces, whether experience has disclosed “union unfair labor practices” and, if so, whether legislative correction is more appropriate than self-discipline and the *550pressure of public opinion — these are questions on which it is not for us to express views. The very limited function of this Court is discharged when we recognize that these issues are not so unrelated to the experience and feelings of the community as to render legislation addressing itself to them wilfully destructive of cherished rights. For these are not matters, like censorship of the press or separation of Church and State, on which history, through the Constitution, speaks so decisively as to forbid legislative experimentation.
But the policy which finds expression in the prohibition of union-security agreements need not rest solely on a legislative conception of the public interest which includes but transcends the special claims of trade unions. The States are entitled to give weight to views combining opposition to the “closed shop” with long-range concern for the welfare of trade unions. Mr. Justice Brandéis, for example, before he came to this Court, had been a staunch promoter of unionism. In testifying before the Commission on Industrial Relations, he said:
“I should say to those employers who stand for the open shop, that they ought to recognize that it is for their interests as well as that of the community that unions should be powerful and responsible; that it is to their interests to build up the union; to aid as far as they can in making them stronger; and to create conditions under which the unions shall be led by the ablest and most experienced men.” 6
*551Yet at the same time he believed that “The objections, legal, economic, and social, against the closed shop are so strong, and the ideas of the closed shop so antagonistic to the American spirit, that the insistence upon it has been a serious obstacle to union progress.” Letter of Sept. 6, 1910, to Lawrence F. Abbott of the Outlook.7 On another occasion he wrote, “But the American people should not, and will not, accept unionism if it involves the closed shop. They will not consent to the exchange of the tyranny of the employer for the tyranny of the employee.” Letter of Feb. 26, 1912, to Lincoln Steffens.8 In summing up his views on unionism, he said:
“It is not true that the 'success of a labor union’ necessarily means a ‘perfect monopoly’. The union, in order to attain or preserve for its members industrial liberty, must be strong and stable. It need not include every member of the trade. Indeed, it is desirable for both the employer and the union that it should not. Absolute power leads to excesses and to weakness: Neither our character nor our intelligence can long bear the strain of unrestricted power. The union attains success when it reaches *552the ideal condition, and the ideal condition for a union is to be strong and stable, and yet to have in the trade outside its own ranks an appreciable number of men who are non-unionists. In any free community the diversity of character, of beliefs, of taste — indeed mere selfishness — -will insure such a supply, if the enjoyment of this privilege of individualism is protected by law. Such a nucleus of unorganized labor will check oppression by the union as the union checks oppression by the employer.” Quoted from Louis D. Brandéis’ contribution to a discussion entitled Peace with Liberty and Justice in 2 Nat. Civic Federation Rev., No. 2, pp. 1, 16 (May 15, 1905).
Mr. Brandéis on the long view deemed the preferential shop a more reliable form of security both for unions and for society than the closed shop; that he did so only serves to ¡Drove that these are pragmatic issues not appropriate for dogmatic solution.
Whatever one may think of Mr. Brandéis’ views, they have been reinforced by the adoption of laws insuring against that undercutting of union standards which was one of the most serious effects of a dissident minority in a union shop. Under interpretations of the National Labor Relations Act undisturbed by the Taft-Hartley Act,9 and of the Railway Labor Act, the bargaining representative designated by a majority of employees has exclusive power to deal with the employer on matters of wages and working conditions. Individual contracts, whether on more or less favorable terms than those obtained by the union, are barred. J. I. Case Co. v. Labor Board, 321 U. S. 332; Order of R. R. Telegraphers v. Railway Express Agency, 321 U. S. 342; Medo Photo Supply Corp. v. Labor Board, 321 U. S. 678; see Elgin, *553J. & E. R. Co. v. Burley, 325 U. S. 711, 737, n. 35. Under these laws, a non-union bidder for a job in a union shop cannot, if he would, undercut the union standards.
Even where the social undesirability of a law may be convincingly urged, invalidation of the law by a court debilitates popular democratic government. Most laws dealing with economic and social problems are matters of trial and error.10 That which before trial appears to be demonstrably bad may belie prophecy in actual operation. It may not prove good, but it may prove innocuous. But even if a law is found wanting on trial, it is better that its defects should be demonstrated and removed than that the law should be aborted by judicial fiat. Such an assertion of judicial power deflects responsibility from those on whom in a democratic society it ultimately rests — the people. If the proponents of union-security agreements have confidence in the arguments addressed to the Court in their “economic brief,” they should address those arguments to the electorate. Its endorsement would be a vindication that the mandate of this Court could never give. That such vindication *554is not a vain hope has been recently demonstrated by the voters of Maine, Massachusetts, and New Mexico.11 And although several States in addition to those at bar now have such laws,12 the legislatures of as many other States have, sometimes repeatedly, rejected them.13 What one State can refuse to do, another can undo.
*555But there is reason for judicial restraint in matters of policy deeper than the value of experiment: it is founded on a recognition of the gulf of difference between sustaining and nullifying legislation. This difference is theoretical in that the function of legislating is for legislatures who have also taken oaths to support the Constitution, while the function of courts, when legislation is challenged, is merely to make sure that the legislature has exercised an allowable judgment, and not to exercise their own judgment, whether a policy is within or without “the vague contours” of due process. Theory is reinforced by the notorious fact that lawyers predominate in American legislatures.14 In practice also the difference is wide. In the day-to-day working of our democracy it is vital that the power of the non-democratic organ of our Government be exercised with rigorous self-restraint. Because the powers exercised by this Court are inherently oligarchic, Jefferson all of his life thought of the Court as “an irresponsible body”15 and “independent of the nation itself.” 16 The Court is not saved from being oli*556garchic because it professes to act in the service of humane ends. As history amply proves, the judiciary is prone to misconceive the public good by confounding private notions with constitutional requirements, and such misconceptions are not subject to legitimate displacement by the will of the people except at too slow a pace.17 Judges appointed for life whose decisions run counter to prevailing opinion cannot be voted out of office and supplanted by men of views more consonant with it. They are even farther removed from democratic pressures by the fact that their deliberations are in secret and remain beyond disclosure either by periodic reports or by such a modern device for securing responsibility to the electorate as the “press conference.” But a democracy need not rely on the courts to save it from its own unwisdom. If it is alert — and without alertness by the people there can be no enduring democracy — unwise or unfair legislation can readily be removed from the statute books. It is by such vigilance over its representatives that democracy proves itself.
Our right to pass on the validity of legislation is now too much part of our constitutional system to be brought *557into question. But the implications of that right and the conditions for its exercise must constantly be kept in mind and vigorously observed. Because the Court is without power to shape measures for dealing with the problems of society but has merely the power of negation over measures shaped by others, the indispensable judicial requisite is intellectual humility, and such humility presupposes complete disinterestedness. And so, in the end, it is right that the Court should be indifferent to public temper and' popular wishes. Mr. Dooley’s “th’ Supreme Coort follows th’ iliction returns” expressed the wit of cynicism, not the demand of principle. A court which yields to the popular will thereby licenses itself to practice despotism, for there can be no assurance that it will not on another occasion indulge its own will. Courts can fulfill their responsibility in a democratic society only to the extent that they succeed in shaping their judgments by rational standards, and rational standards are both impersonal and communicable. Matters of policy, however, are by definition' matters which demand the resolution of conflicts of value, and the elements of conflicting values are largely imponderable. Assessment of their competing worth involves differences of feeling; it is also an exercise in prophecy. Obviously the proper forum for mediating a clash of feelings and rendering a prophetic judgment is the body chosen for those purposes by the people. Its functions can be assumed by this Court only in disregard of the historic limits of the Constitution.
[This is also a concurrence in No. 47, Lincoln Federal Labor Union v. Northwestern Iron & Metal Co., and No. 34, Whitaker v. North Carolina, decided together, ante, p. 525.]
Of course, theory never wholly squared with the facts. Even while laissez faire doctrines were dominant, State activity in economic affairs was considerable. See Handlin, Commonwealth: A Study of the Role of Government in the American Economy, Massachusetts, 1774-1861 (1947); Hartz, Economic Policy and Democratic Thought: Pennsylvania, 1776-1860 (1948).
See, e. g., State of Arizona Initiative and Referendum Publicity Pamphlet, 1946 (Compiled and Issued by the Secretary of State); Testimony before the Nebraska State Legislative Committee on Labor and Public Welfare, March 21, 1947 (transcript of the Committee’s record of the substance of the testimony kindly furnished by the Department of Justice of Nebraska); The Case against the Closed Shop in Nebraska, a pamphlet published by the “Right to Work Committee”; N. C. Sess. Laws, 1947, c. 328, § 1 (preamble). As to the similar purpose of similar legislation in other States, see, e. g., The Open Shop in Virginia, Report of the Virginia Advisory Legislative Council to the Governor of Virginia, House Doc. No. 2, *547p. 7 (1947); Address of Wm. M. Tuck to the General Assembly and People of Virginia, Extra Session, House Doc. No. 1, pp. 8-9 (1947); Tucumcari (N. M.) Daily News, Oct. 6, 1948, p. 3, col. 3 (report of radio addresses by sponsors of proposed “Right-to-Work Amendment”).
In the following table, “union membership” includes all members of AFL, CIO, and independent or unaffiliated unions, including Canadian members of international unions with headquarters in the United States; the “employment” figures include all non-*548agricultural employees (i. e., wage and salary workers), non-agricultural self-employed, unpaid family workers, and domestic-service workers.
Year Union Membership (thousands) Employment (thousands)
1898 467.
1900 791. 17,826
1903 1,824. 20,202
1908 2,092. 22,871
1913 2,661. 27,031
1918 3,368. 33,456
1923 3,629. 32,314
1928 3,567. 35,505
1933 2,857 28,670
1938 8,265. 34,530
1943 13,642. 45,390
1948 15,600. 50,400
The “union membership” totals, except for 1948, are taken from Membership of Labor Unions in the United States, U. S. Dept, of Labor, Bureau of Labor Statistics (mimeographed pamphlet); the “union membership” and “employment” totals for 1948 are preliminary estimates by the Bureau of Labor Statistics. The “employment” figures for years up to 1928 are taken from Employment and Unemployment of the Labor Force, 1900-1940, 2 Conference Board Economic Record 77, 80 (1940); “employment” figures for years since 1929, except 1948, and the basis upon which they are estimated may be found in Technical Note, 67 Monthly Labor Rev., No. 1, p. 50 (1948).
Section 2, Fourth, of the 1934 Amendment, 48 Stat. 1187, of the Railway Labor Act of 1926, 44 Stat. 577, 45 U. S. C. § 152, Fourth, appears on its face to bar union-shop agreements, and it has been so interpreted. 40 Ops. Atty. Gen., No. 59 (Dec. 29, 1942). The wisdom of such a legislative policy is of course not for us to judge.
In the following table, “Membership of Brotherhoods” includes the Brotherhood of Locomotive Engineers, the Brotherhood of Loco*549motive Enginemen and Firemen, the Order of Railway Conductors, and the Brotherhood of Railroad Trainmen, with the Canadian membership of each, but not railroad employees who are members of CIO or independent unions. The 1919 figure for “Employment Class I Railroads” includes all, not merely Class I, operating carriers.
Year Membership of Brotherhoods (thousands) Employment Class I Railroads (thousands)
1919 456. . 1,908
1924 434. . 1,774
1929 423. . 1,661
1934 268. . 1,008
1939 303. . 988
1944 442. . 1,415
1947 450. . 1,352
The “Membership of Brotherhoods” figures are estimates made available through the kindness of the Bureau of Labor Statistics. Those for 192¿H934 are based on Wolman, Ebb and Flow in Trade Unionism 230-31 (1936). The figures for “Employment Class I Ra-ilroads” have been obtained from the I. C. C. annual reports entitled Statistics of Railways in the United States, that for 1919 from the 33d Ann. Rep. at 21 (1922); that for 1924 from 38th Ann. Rep. at XXV (1926); those for 1929, 1934, and 1939 from 54th Ann. Rep. at 59 (1942); that for 1944 from 60th Ann. Rep. at 55 (1948); that for 1947 from I. C. C., Bureau of Transport Economics and Statistics, Statement No. M-300, Wage Statistics of Class I Steam Railways in the United States (1947).
See U. S. Dept. Labor, Report of the Commission on Industrial Relations in Great Britain 23 (1938); U. S. Dept. Labor, Report of the Commission on Industrial Relations in Sweden 9 (1938). Cf. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Art. 20, cl. 2, adopted by the General Assembly of the United Nations, Dec. 11, 1948, declaring that “No one may be compelled to belong to an association.”
Sen. Doc. No. 415, 64th Cong., 1st Sess. 7681. For other expressions of Mr. Justice Brandéis’ sympathy for the cause of trade unions, see id. at 7659-60, 7662, 7667; Brandéis, The Employer and Trades Unions, in Business — A Profession 13 (1914); Industrial Co-operation, 3 Filene Co-operative Association Echo, No. 3, p. 1 (May, 1905), reprinted in The Curse of Bigness 35 (Fraenkel ed. 1935); Big Business and Industrial Liberty, reprinted in id. at 38.
Copy obtained from the collection of Brandéis papers at the Law Library of the University of Louisville, to which I am indebted. The letter is quoted in part in Mason, Brandéis: A Free Man’s Life 301 (1946). See also testimony before the Commission on Industrial Relations, op. cit. supra, note 6, at 7680-81. As an alternative to the closed or union shop, Mr. Brandéis advocated the “preferential union shop,” which, apparently, is also barred by the Arizona, Nebraska, and North Carolina laws. For accounts of the working of the “preferential union shop,” see Moskowitz, The Power for Constructive Reform in the Trade Union Movement, 2 Life and Labor 10 (1912); Winslow, Conciliation, Arbitration, and Sanitation in the Cloak, Suit, and Skirt Industry in New York City, 24 Bulletin of the Bureau of Labor, No. 98, Jan., 1912, H. R. Doc. No. 166, 62d Cong., 2d Sess. 203, 215.
Copy obtained from the University of Louisville; quoted in part in Mason, op. cit. supra, note 7, at 303-04.
See H. R. Rep. No. 245, 80th Cong., 1st Sess. 17; 93 Cong. Rec. 4371 (May 1, 1947).
Examples of legislative experimentation undertaken to meet a recognized need were the bank-deposit guaranty laws passed in the wake of the panic of 1907 by Kansas, Nebraska, and Oklahoma. Despite serious doubts of their wisdom, the laws were sustained against due-process attack in Noble State Bank v. Haskell, 219 U. S. 104 and 575; Shallenberger v. First State Bank, 219 U. S. 114; Assaria State Bank v. Dolley, 219 U. S. 121. Experience proved the laws to be unworkable, see Robb, Guaranty of Bank Deposits in 2 Encyc. Soc. Sciences 417 (1930). But since no due-process obstacle stood in the way, it remained possible to profit by past errors and attempt a more mature solution of the problem on a national scale. See Sen. Rep. No. 77, 73d Cong., 1st Sess. 9-13; H. R. Rep. No. 150, 73d Cong., 1st Sess. 5-7. The result was establishment of the Federal Deposit Insurance Corporation by the Banking Act of 1933, 48 Stat. 168, 12 U. S. C. § 264. If that expedient should prove inadequate, the way is open for further experimentation. See Note, The Glass-Steagall Banking Act of 1933, 47 Harv. L. Rev. 325, 330-32 (1933).
On Sept. 13, 1948, the voters of Maine rejected “An Act to Protect the Right to Work and to Prohibit Secondary Boycotts, Sympathetic Strikes and Jurisdictional Strikes” and “An Act Protecting the Right of Members and Non-members of Labor Organizations to the Opportunity to Work.” The vote in favor of the first bill was 46,809; for the second, 13,676; against both bills, 126,285. These figures were kindly furnished by the Deputy Secretary of State of the State of Maine.
On Nov. 2, 1948, the voters of Massachusetts rejected a measure prohibiting “the denial of the opportunity to obtain or retain employment because of membership or non-membership in a labor organization,” by a vote of 1,290,310 to 505,575. Report of the Executive Department of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts, Nov. 24, 1948, p. 60.
On the same day the voters of New Mexico rejected a similar bill by a vote of 60,118 to 41,387 (incomplete returns). See Clovis (N. M.) News-Journal, Nov. 5,1948, p. 1, col. 3.
Ark. Const. Amend. No. 34, Nov. 7, 1944, and Acts of Ark., 1947, Act 101; Del. Laws, 1947, c. 196, §30; Fla. Const. Deel. of Rights § 12, as amended Nov. 7, 1944; Ga. Laws, 1947, No. 140; Iowa Laws, 1947, c. 296; La. Gen. Stat. §4381.2 (Dart, 1939); Md. Ann. Code Gen. Laws art. 100, § 65 (1939); Nev. Comp. Laws § 10473 (1929); N. D. Laws, 1947, c. 243; S. D. Const, art. 6, §2, as amended Nov. 1, 1946, and Laws, 1947, c. 92; Term. Public Acts, 1947, c. 36; Texas Laws, 1947, c. 74; Va. Acts of Assembly, 1947, c. 2.
For a valuable digest of State laws regulating labor activity see Killingsworth, State Labor Relations Acts, Appendix A, by Beverley Kritzman Killingsworth, at 267 (1948). It shows the variety and empiric character of such legislation for a single decade (1937-47).
The following list of rejected anti-closed-shop laws has been compiled from U. S. Dept. Labor, Division of Labor Standards, Legislative Reports, 1939 to date.
Calif.: A. B. 1560, 1941; S. B. 974, 1941; Conn.: H. B. 557, S. B. 823, 1939; H. B. 302, 1947; Kans.: H. B. 256, S. B. 410, 1939; *555S. C. Res. No. 10, 1945; Ky.: S. B. 231, 1946; Mass.: H. B. 864, 1947; Minn.: S. B. 102, 1947; Miss.: H. B. 714, 1942; H. C. R. 21, 1944 (semble); H. B. 171, 1946; H. B. 328, 1948; H. B. 1000, 1948; Mo.: S. B. 144, 1945; N. H.: H. B. 225, 1945; Ohio: H. B. 49, 1947; Utah: S. J. R. 15, H. J. R. 15, 1947.
See, e. g., 25 U. S. News, No. 22, p. 11 (Nov. 26, 1948).
Letter to Charles Hammond, Aug. 18, 1821, 15 Writings of Thomas Jefferson 330, 331 (Memorial ed., 1904).
Letter to Samuel Kercheval, July 12, 1816, 15 id. at 32, 34. For similar expressions of Jefferson’s alarm at what he felt to be the dangerous encroachment of the judiciary upon the other functions of government, see his letters to William B. Giles, April 20, 1807, 11 id. at 187, 191; to Caesar Rodney, Sept. 25, 1810, 12 id. at 424, 425; to John Taylor, May 28, 1816, 15 id. at 17, 21; to Spencer Roane, Sept. 6, 1819, 15 id. at 212; to Thomas Ritchie, Dec. 25, 1820, 15 id. at 297; to James Pleasants, Dec. 26, 1821, 12 Works of Thomas Jefferson, 213, 214 (Federal ed., 1905); to William T. Barry, July 2, 1822, 15 Writings, supra, at 388; to A. Coray, Oct. 31, 1823, *55615 id. at 480, 487; to Edward Livingston, March 25, 1825, 16 id. at 112. See also the passage of Jefferson’s Autobiography reprinted in 1 Writings, supra, at 120-22. And see Commager, Majority Rule or Minority Rights 28-38 (1943).
In time, of course, constitutional obstacles may disappear or be removed. Yet almost twenty years elapsed between invalidation of the income tax in Pollock v. Farmers’ Loan & Trust Co., 158 U. S. 601, and adoption of the Sixteenth Amendment. And it took twenty years to establish the constitutionality of a minimum wage for women: it was put in jeopardy by an equally divided Court in Stettler v. O’Hara, 243 U. S. 629, and found unconstitutional in Adkins v. Children’s Hospital, 261 U. S. 525, which was not overruled until West Coast Hotel Co. v. Parrish, 300 U. S. 379, 400. The frustration of popular government, moreover, is not confined to the specific law struck down; its backwash drowns unnumbered projects that might otherwise be put to trial.