The suit below was upon a promis • sory note, dated the 8th of May, 1812, fbr 750 dollars, payable in 100 days.
This note was one of twelve notes, given by M, $■ W. Ward to the plaintiff, and payable at different periods, the whole of them amounted to 9,000 dollars, and were all given at the same time. Instead of cash, the plaintiff gave in exchange for those notes, four notes of his own, amounting to the same sum of 9,000 dollars, payable at more distant periods. Upon this exchange of notes the plaintiff received a commission of 2 and 1-2 per cent., amounting to 225 dollars, for making the exchange. This commission exceeded the legal rate of interest upon four notes of the plaintiff, supposing them to have been intended as a loan of so much cash. It amounted to a rfite of interest of twelve percent. ; and the question is, whether this commission was not ano
The jury have found the fact submitted to them by the judge at the trial, that the exchange of the notes was for the purpose of raising money at a greater rate of interest than seven per cent, per annum. This fact appears to me to establish, beyond all contradiction, the charge of usury -set up by the defendant. If that was the object of the parties, (and the jury have so found it,) then it was a shift or contrivance to get rid of the statute of usury, and such a 'shift or contrivance no court of justice can tolerate.
But the plaintiff offered to show upon the trial that the charge of a commission of two and a half per cent, upon the exchange of notes was within the understanding, usage, -and custom of merchants, and this evidence was overruled ■ as immaterial and useless. ■
The question on the competency of this evidence ap* ..pears to be the only point in the case.
If the evidence offered was not, in judgment of law, material upon the point of the shift or contrivance to evade the statute, then it was improper, and ought to have been rejected.
This point appears to me as clear and self evident as the -ether.
It was observed by Lord Chancellor Loughborough, in the case Ex parte Aynsworth, (4 Vesey, 678.) that the custom of a trade to take a discount above five per cent., (or the legal rate of interest in England,) cannot authorise a greater demandaban five per cent. It is perfectly idle to talk of a custom of merchants to take a commission above the legal rate of interest-on the-exchange-of notes. The custom of merchants is ndt applicable ‘to such a case. It is not a matter of trade and commerce, within the meaning of the law merchant. And if there were such a local usage in New-York it would be null and void, and could not be set up as a cover -or pretext to trample down the law of the land. The mo
The usage, therefore, that, was offered to be shown would not have been of any avail, if it had been proved, for it would have been an illegal usage, and the evidence in favour of it was properly overruled.
This, then, being a clear case of usury, it is not necessary for me to observe, that it is the duty of the Court to give full effect to the statute made to suppress it. The counsel who argued this cause, on the part of the plaintiff, while he acknowledged this to be our duty, yet, at the same time very ingeniously arraigned the justice and policy of the law. The effect of the attack, (if well founded,) would naturally be to induce us to look with an unfavourable eye upon every plea under the statute of usury, and to lay hold of any pretext or argument, however specious, such, for instance, as that these were commissons only, and not interest, or that this was the usage of the merchants, or that here was only the loan of notes, in order to free ourselves from the bondage of the law. But this, I apprehend, we are not at liberty to do. Asjlong as the statute exists in full force, we are bound in all honest policy to give it a fair and manly support. I will even go further, and say, that I have not been able to perceive the injustice, and
/ The Romans, through the greater part of their history, had the deepest abhorrence of usury. They did not derive their objection to usury from the prohibitions in the Mosaic law, nor did they hold it sinful, as the learned Fathers of the early and middle ages of the church have done, forthey.knew nothing of that law. ■''í’he Roman lawgivers and jurists acted from views of public policy. They found, by their own experience, that unlimited usury led to unlimited oppression, and that the extortion of the creditor, and the resistance of the debtor, were constantly agitating and disturbing the public peace. </
But it is not only the civilized and commercial nations of modern Europe, and the sage lawgivers of ancient Rome, that have regulated the interest of money. It will be deemed a little singular, that the same voice against usury should have been raised in the laws of China, in the Hindu Institutes of Menu, in the Koran of Mahomet, and perhaps,, we may say, in the laws of all nations that we know of, whether Greek or Barbarian.
There is one exception, however, that I ought to notice, and which is supposed to be found in the laws of Solon, given to -the Athenian Republic. Tins celebrated-
Now, according to this view of the fact, interest was limited at Athens, as, effectually and as precisely, by this customary law, as it would have been by any penal statute, and the Athenian commonwealth is not to be cited as a real exception to the general practice of mankind.
The principal error which has prevailed oh this subject, is the condemnation of any kind of interest, however small. A host of great names from Aristotle among the Greeks, to the modern civilians, such as Domat and Pothier might be cited, who rank all interest of money under the name of Usury, and condemn it. But the sense of mutual benefit has, on this point, resisted, with equal firmness, the decrees of the church, and the speculations of philosophers, and a regulated and reasonable interest has had the sanction, not only of our own municipal law, but of the most cultivated and enlightened human reason. Grotius, (lib. 2. c. 12. § 20. ■-22.) after discussing the question, whether usury be permitted by the natural and divine law, .concludes, that a reasonable
Can we suppose, that a principle of moral restraint' of such uniform, and universal adoption, has no good sense in it ? Is it altogether the result of monkish prejudice ? Ought we not rather to conclude, that the provision is adapted to the necessities and the wants of our species, and grows out of the natural infirmity of man, and the temptation to abuse inherent in pecuniary loans. The question of interest arises constantly, and intrudes itself into almost every transaction. It stimulates the cupidity for gain, and sensibly affects the heart, and gradually presses upon the relation of debtor and creditor. Civil government is continually placing guards over the weaknesses, and checks upon the passions
The Roman commonwealth, if we may place reliance-upon its earlier history, tried every experiment on this interesting subject. The Romans had no law regulating the interest of money, and left the parties to their own contracts, until the law of the twelve tables, according to Tacitus, or the law of the tribunes, in the year of Rome 398, according to Montesquieu. The consequence was, unceasing quarrels between the patricians and plebeians, and popular secessions to the mons sacer, in which one party pleaded the obligation, and the other the severity of their contracts. Interest was then reduced to the smallest allowance, and finally abolished, which led to a still more frightful usury, until at last, the emperors were obliged to allow, but regulate, and limit the charge of usury. So true it is, according to the President Montesquieu (Esprit des Loix, liv. 22. ch. 21,22.) who has discussed this subject at large, that extreme laws produce extreme evil, les loix extremes dans le bien font naitre le mal extreme. The Romans, at one time, had no laws against
Lord Redesdale said, in 1803, (1 Sch. & Lef. 195. 312.) many years after Jeremy Bentham, to whom the learned counsel referred for an able defence of usury, had first published his letters, that the statute of usury was founded on great principles of public policy. It was intended, he said, to protect distressed men, by facilitating'the means of procuring money on reasonable terms, and by re-. fusing to men who sit idle, as high a rate of interest without hazard, as those can procure who employ money in the hazardous undertakings of trade and manufacture.
I trust that theoretic reformers have not yet attained, on this subject, any decided victory over public opinion. Mr. Bentham contends, that we ought hot so much as to wish “ to see the spirit of projects in any degree repressed.” It may be so; but I hope I may be permitted to wish that the first experiments of his projects may not be made within these walls. The statute of usury is constantly interposing its warning voice between the creditor and the debtor, even in their most secret and dangerous negotiations, and teaches a lesson of moderation to the one, and offers its protecting arm to the other. I am not willing to withdraw such a sentinel. I have been called to witness, in the course of my official life, too many victims to the weakness and to the inflamed passions of men. All sudden and extreme reforms are unwise. We ought not to stretch or to amputate, in order to make our institutions fit exactly to any theory. It is better to follow the course and order of Providence, and suffer our general system of laws, like our habits, to accommodate itself slowly to our necessities, and to vary only with the gradual and almost imperceptible progress of time and experience.
I am accordingly of opinion, that the judgment of the Supreme Court ought to be affirmed.
This being the unanimous opinion of the Court, (exceptMr, Bates, Senator,) it. was therefore; Ordered and adjudged, that the judgment of thy Supreme Court be affirmed, arid
Judgment of affirmance.