United States Court of Appeals
For the First Circuit
No. 04-1625
MICHAEL WIRZBURGER, ET AL.,
Plaintiffs, Appellants,
v.
WILLIAM F. GALVIN,
SECRETARY OF STATE, ET AL.,
Defendants, Appellees.
APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT
FOR THE DISTRICT OF MASSACHUSETTS
[Hon. George A. O'Toole, Jr., U.S. District Judge]
Before
Torruella, Circuit Judge,
Campbell, Senior Circuit Judge,
and Lipez, Circuit Judge.
Derek L. Gaubatz, with whom Anthony R. Picarello, Jr.,
Roman P. Storzer, Burns & Levinson LLP, Michael J. Meagher and
Robert J. O'Regan were on brief, for appellants.
William W. Porter, Assistant Attorney General, with whom
Thomas F. Reilly, Attorney General, and Peter Sacks, Assistant
Attorney General, were on brief, for appellees.
June 24, 2005
TORRUELLA, Circuit Judge. Plaintiffs-appellants would
like to amend the Massachusetts Constitution to allow public
financial support to be directed toward private, religiously
affiliated schools. Plaintiffs attempted to propose their
amendment through the Massachusetts initiative procedure, but two
distinct provisions of the Massachusetts Constitution prevented
initiatives on this subject. They now challenge these subject-
matter exclusions from the initiative process on federal Free
Speech, Free Exercise, and Equal Protection grounds. In the end,
plaintiffs' arguments fail, and although our analysis diverges at
points, we affirm the district court's grant of summary judgment.1
I. Facts
Plaintiffs are parents of children enrolled in
religiously affiliated schools who sought to amend Amendment
Article 18 of the Massachusetts Constitution (the "Anti-Aid
Amendment"), which prohibits public financial support for private
primary or secondary schools.2 Mass. Const. amend. art. 18.
Article 48 of the Massachusetts Constitution provides that, in
1
In sum, because we recognize the communicative aspect of the
initiative process, we apply intermediate scrutiny to
Massachusetts' initiative exclusions, whereas the district court
applied rational basis review. We find that the exclusions
nevertheless survive this heightened review. Our Free Exercise and
Equal Protection Clause analyses elaborate on the district court's
similar grounds for decision.
2
The district court found that Plaintiffs lacked standing to
challenge the constitutionality of the Anti-Aid Amendment directly,
but that issue has not been raised on appeal.
-2-
addition to the amendment procedure available to the state
legislature, the Constitution may also be amended by popular
initiative. Mass. Const. amend. art. 48, pt. 1. Following the
required procedure, plaintiffs submitted an initiative petition,
for certification, to the Massachusetts Attorney General to modify
the Anti-Aid Amendment by adding a sentence stating that nothing in
the Anti-Aid Amendment shall prevent the Commonwealth from
providing loans, grants, or tax benefits to students attending
private schools, regardless of the schools' religious affiliation.
The Attorney General, however, denied certification of the proposed
initiative, because Article 48 prohibits amendment of the Anti-Aid
Amendment by initiative (the "Anti-Aid Exclusion") and because the
petition explicitly relates to "religious institutions," another
matter expressly excluded from the initiative process by Article 48
(the "Religious Exclusion").
Section Two of Article 48 limits Massachusetts'
initiative process by listing the "Excluded Matters," which are not
subject to popular action by initiative, including, inter alia,
appointment or compensation of judges; the powers, creation or
abolition of the courts; and specific appropriation of state money.
Mass. Const. amend. art. 48, pt. 2, § 2. The pertinent provision
of Article 48, referred to as the Anti-Aid Exclusion, states that
"[n]either the eighteenth [Anti-Aid] amendment of the constitution
. . . nor this provision for its protection, shall be the subject
-3-
of an initiative amendment," while the Religious Exclusion mandates
that "[n]o measure that relates to religion, religious practices or
religious institutions . . . shall be proposed by an initiative
petition." Id. Plaintiffs challenge the validity of both of these
exclusions under the U.S. Constitution.
II. Analysis
A. Free Speech Claim
The first issue before us is whether the Massachusetts
Constitution's limitations on the initiative process violate the
First Amendment free speech rights of prospective initiative
proponents. Appellants argue that the exclusions to the state
initiative process, which prevent them from pursuing amendments
regarding religion or state aid to private institutions, should be
considered content-based restrictions on core political speech
subject to strict scrutiny.
The difficulty with the appellants' argument is that a
state initiative procedure, although it may involve speech, is also
a procedure for generating law, and is thus a process that the
state has an interest in regulating, apart from any regulation of
the speech involved in the initiative process. In other words, the
challenged exclusions constitute regulations "aimed at non-
communicative impact, but nonetheless having adverse effects on
communicative opportunity." Laurence H. Tribe, American
Constitutional Law § 12-2 at 790 (2d ed. 1988). See, e.g., United
-4-
States v. O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 382 (1968) (rejecting draft card
burner's claim that a statute prohibiting the destruction of draft
cards violated his First Amendment rights, reasoning that the law
punished him for the "noncommunicative impact of his conduct,"
although the court recognized the symbolic value of burning a draft
card). Unlike regulations that are "aimed at communicative
impact," regulations that aim at preventing some harm independent
of speech -- in this case, the use of the initiative process for
the passage of certain types of laws believed to be unsuited to
that process -- are not presumed unconstitutional, and are not
subjected to strict scrutiny. Tribe, American Constitutional Law
§ 12-2, at 790. See, e.g., City of Erie v. Pap's A.M., 529 U.S.
277, 291 (2000) (upholding a ban on nude dancing, because "the
ordinance does not attempt to regulate the primary effects of the
expression, i.e., the effect on the audience of watching nude
erotic dancing, but rather the secondary effects, such as the
impacts on public health, safety, and welfare," which are unrelated
to expression). Regulations of this type are, at most, subject to
intermediate scrutiny, under which they will be upheld if the
"harmful consequences of this particular form of expressive
behavior, quite apart from any ideas it might convey, outweigh the
good." Tribe, American Constitutional Law § 12-2, 791. See, e.g.,
Grayned v. Rockford, 408 U.S. 104, 115-16 (1972) (upholding
ordinance barring noisy demonstrations near schools, because the
-5-
government has sufficiently "weighty reasons" to restrict this type
of expressive activity). Applying this balancing, we uphold
Massachusetts' exclusions to its initiative process for the reasons
explained below.
Before arriving at this explanation, we will first
examine the arguments of the parties -- a task that is particularly
difficult in this case, because the parties have planted themselves
firmly at opposite poles, with plaintiffs arguing for strict
scrutiny and Massachusetts arguing that only minimal rationality
review is appropriate. In the end, we find that the law requires
our analysis to proceed by a middle path in this apparent battle of
absolutes. We hold that Massachusetts' exclusions to its
initiative process are narrowly drawn to further a significant
state interest, and thus survive intermediate scrutiny.
1. The Communicative Value of the Initiative Process
The first step in our free speech analysis must be to
determine whether citizens' use of the initiative process
constitutes expressive conduct, permitting appellants to invoke the
First Amendment to challenge the Massachusetts initiative
exclusions. See, e.g., Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 403 (1989)
(citing Spence v. Washington, 418 U.S. 405, 409-11 (1974)). We do
not find that there is any serious debate as to this point. A
state initiative process provides a uniquely provocative and
effective method of spurring public debate on an issue of
-6-
importance to the proponents of the proposed initiative. The
Supreme Court has made clear that the process involved in proposing
legislation by means of initiative involves core political speech.
See Meyer v. Grant, 486 U.S. 414 (1988) (overturning state's
prohibition on using paid petition circulators); Buckley v. Am.
Constitutional Law Found., Inc., 525 U.S. 182 (1999) (overturning
various registration requirements for petition circulators). In
Meyer, the Supreme Court recognized that "the solicitation of
signatures for a petition involves protected speech." 486 U.S. at
422, n.5. Furthermore, the mere fact that plaintiffs "remain free
to employ other means to disseminate their ideas does not take
their [preferred means of] speech through [the initiative process]
outside the bounds of First Amendment protection." Id. at 424.
Clearly, plaintiffs have been prevented from engaging in the sort
of activity that implicates the First Amendment. This conclusion,
however, in no way ends our analysis; it only opens the door for us
to apply constitutional freedom of speech principles to the
limitations Massachusetts places on its initiative process.
We have recognized that "a fine line separates
permissible regulation of state election processes from
impermissible abridgement of First Amendment rights," Pérez-Guzmán
v. Gracia, 346 F.3d 229, 239 (1st Cir. 2003), and the same is true
of regulation of state initiative procedures. In Pérez-Guzmán, 346
F.3d at 239-47, we invalidated Puerto Rico's requirement that
-7-
petition signatures needed for registering a new political party to
appear on the general election ballot be notarized, holding that it
violated the First Amendment of the federal Constitution. In so
doing, we stated that "we afford exacting scrutiny to severe
restrictions on ballot access." Id. at 239. We began our analysis
"with an assessment of the severity of the restriction," id., and
having found it to be severe, we applied strict scrutiny, id. at
243-44.
Plaintiffs argue that we should apply a similar two-step
analysis here. However, plaintiffs' suggested analysis makes an
end-run around the most difficult part of their case. The district
court in this case found that speech was only incidentally affected
by the Massachusetts subject matter exclusions. Boyette v. Galvin,
311 F. Supp. 2d 237, 240 (D. Mass. 2004). Although the district
court recognized that speech was involved, it concluded that the
primary goal of the exclusion was to prevent certain types of laws
from being passed by means of the popular initiative process, and
not to limit what people could say or how they could say it. Id.
at 240-41. By contrast, the common denominator in Pérez-Guzmán and
other cases cited by plaintiffs is a direct restriction on the
communicative aspect of the political process. In Pérez-Guzmán,
like in Meyer, the state regulated how people could promulgate
their political views, in their respective attempts to put a new
party on the ballot, Pérez-Guzmán, 346 F.3d at 230-31, and to
-8-
circulate petitions for a proposed initiative, Meyer, 486 U.S. at
414. Strict scrutiny applied in these cases precisely because they
involved direct regulation of the petition process itself.
We believe that the present case calls for a lower level
of scrutiny. We know of no general principle that, in addition to
constitutional amendment or lawmaking via a process instituted by
the state legislature, a state must provide an opportunity for its
residents to propose constitutional amendments or laws on all
subjects by means of an initiative process. While we accept that
use of the initiative process can facilitate dissemination of
initiative proponents' views, the next step in a free speech
analysis is to determine whether or not the regulation in question
aims at regulating speech, or whether it has some other primary
end, such that any effect on speech is purely incidental. As we
alluded to at the outset of this analysis, the First Amendment
generally provides greater protection against laws that are "aimed
at communicative impact" of the conduct they regulate than from
laws "aimed at non-communicative impact, but nonetheless having
adverse effects on communicative opportunity." Tribe, American
Constitutional Law § 12-2, at 790. The primary goal of state
initiative procedures is to create an avenue of direct democracy
whereby citizens can participate in the generation of legislation
-- that is, the act of creating law. Laws such as those considered
in Meyer and its progeny were aimed at directly regulating the
-9-
means that initiative proponents could use to reach their audience
of potential petition signers. In contrast, we find that subject
matter exclusions like those regulating the Massachusetts
initiative process aim at preventing the act of generating laws and
constitutional amendments about certain subjects by initiative.
While they eliminate a valuable avenue of expression about those
subjects, the speech restriction is no more than an unintended
side-effect of the exclusions. It is because of this sometimes
overlooked, but nevertheless fundamental principle in
constitutional free speech doctrine that we must reject appellants'
proposed analysis. We turn now to Massachusetts' proposed
alternative analysis.
2. Massachusetts' Need to Regulate the Lawmaking Act
The communicative power of an initiative stems precisely
from the fact that it is not just speech; it is a process that can
lead to the creation of new laws or constitutional amendments.
Massachusetts urges us to hold that its restrictions on the
amendment process do not regulate speech qua speech, and thus do
not trigger strict scrutiny under the First Amendment.
Government actions that are aimed at some goal other than
restricting the conveyance of ideas are generally permissible, even
if they incidentally inhibit free speech. See, e.g., Arcara v.
Cloud Books, Inc., 478 U.S. 697 (1986) (upholding the closure of an
adult bookstore because prostitution was taking place on the
-10-
premises). Arcara is a prototypical example of this type of case,
because the law in question only regulated a specific type of
conduct -- prostitution -- which did not implicate speech.
However, even a law seemingly entirely removed from speech can have
effects on speech. In Arcara, for example, the prohibition on
prostitution resulted in the closure of a book store. Enforcement
of a prohibition with such incidental effects does not, however,
implicate the First Amendment, and this type of law need only
survive rationality review.
Plaintiffs do not cite to any precedent for the
proposition that, under the Free Speech Clause of the First
Amendment, a state may not restrict the subjects that can be
addressed through its initiative process. The D.C. Circuit
addressed a similar free speech challenge to a restriction on an
initiative process in the case of Marijuana Policy Project v.
United States, 304 F.3d 82 (D.C. Cir. 2002). In that case, the
D.C. Circuit held that a statute precluding the use of the D.C.
ballot initiative process to lower drug penalties did not
unconstitutionally restrict free speech rights of medical marijuana
advocates, but only shifted the forum of debate from the District
of Columbia to Congress. Id. at 85-86. The court explained that
"although the First Amendment protects public debate about
legislation, it confers no right to legislate on a particular
-11-
subject." Id. at 85. Massachusetts argues that we should adopt
this reasoning to apply rational basis review in the instant case.
3. Regulating Conduct with Speech and Nonspeech Elements
We cannot agree with the D.C. Circuit's finding that
subject-matter exclusions from the initiative process "restrict[]
no speech," id. at 85, nor with its conclusion that this type of
selective carve-out "implicates no First Amendment concerns," id.
at 83. For the same reasons, we also reject Massachusetts'
argument that we should apply only rational basis review to the
Anti-Aid and Religious Exclusions. This case is not like Arcara,
where the Supreme Court criticized the New York Court of Appeals
for having applied the analysis established in United States v.
O'Brien, 391 U.S. 367 (1968), because the Court did not consider
the regulated conduct -- prostitution -- expressive. See Arcara,
478 U.S. at 705 (concluding that "unlike the symbolic draft card
burning in O'Brien, the sexual activity carried on in this case
manifests absolutely no element of protected expression"). Rather,
we would continue along the analysis laid out by the Supreme Court
in Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. at 403. Having determined that
Meyer, 486 U.S. at 422, indicates that a state initiative process
manifests elements of protected expression, under Johnson, "we next
decide whether the State's regulation is related to the suppression
of free expression." 491 U.S. at 403. Here, as we have already
explained, the Massachusetts exclusions in question regulate which
-12-
types of laws or amendments can be passed by initiative, without
any reference to who may speak or what message they may convey.
Thus, because "the State's regulation is not related to expression,
. . . the less stringent standard [the Supreme Court] announced in
United States v. O'Brien for regulations of noncommunicative
conduct controls." Id. (citing O'Brien, 391 U.S. at 377 (finding
that, although burning a draft card can be expressive conduct, the
federal government's interest in preventing the destruction of
draft cards is sufficient to uphold defendant's conviction)).
The standard enunciated in O'Brien governs "when 'speech'
and 'nonspeech' elements are combined in the same course of
conduct." O'Brien, 391 U.S. at 376. See also Clark v. Community
for Creative Non-Violence, 468 U.S. 288 (1984) (applying O'Brien
scrutiny to the application of a ban on camping on the Mall in
Washington, D.C., to demonstrators who sought to sleep overnight
there to protest the plight of homeless people). While we agree
with the D.C. Circuit that this type of regulation of a state
initiative process is not aimed at regulating speech, we cannot see
how, given the Supreme Court's analysis in Meyer, subject-matter
exclusions from a state initiative process "restrict[] no speech."
Marijuana Policy Project, 304 F.3d at 85. To the contrary, since
expression is affected by the regulations of the state initiative
process, we apply the intermediate scrutiny standard set out in
O'Brien.
-13-
4. Applying O'Brien Scrutiny
Under the O'Brien standard, conduct combining "speech"
and "non-speech" elements can be regulated if four requirements are
met: (1) the regulation "is within the constitutional power of the
Government;" (2) "it furthers an important or substantial
governmental interest;" (3) "the governmental interest is unrelated
to the suppression of free expression;" and (4) "the incidental
restriction on alleged First Amendment freedoms is no greater than
is essential to the furtherance of that interest." O'Brien, 391
U.S. at 377. We have no difficulty finding that the Massachusetts
exclusions meet the second requirement, as Massachusetts certainly
has a substantial interest in maintaining the proper balance
between promoting free exercise and preventing state establishment
of religion. Neither do we doubt that Massachusetts has a
substantial interest in restricting the means by which these
fundamental rights can be changed. We have already stated that the
exclusions aim at preventing certain uses of the initiative
process, not at stemming expression, and thus meet the third
O'Brien requirement.
As for the first requirement, that the regulation be
within the constitutional power of the government, we find that the
only serious, non-speech-related constitutional challenges to
Massachusetts' power to regulate the subjects that may be reached
by its initiative process are the Free Exercise and Equal
-14-
Protection arguments, which we reject in this opinion. Having now
concluded that Massachusetts' interest in protecting the
fundamental free exercise and freedom from state-established
religion is substantial and its method otherwise constitutionally
permissible, we finally consider the fourth O'Brien requirement:
whether the incidental restrictions on would-be initiative
proponents' First Amendment freedoms are greater than essential to
the furtherance of that interest. Since we see no other way in
which Massachusetts could achieve its interest in safeguarding
these fundamental freedoms in its Constitution from popular
initiative, we recognize that the restriction on speech is no more
than is essential. Thus, we conclude that Massachusetts' Anti-Aid
and Religious Exclusions do not violate the First Amendment free
speech guarantee.
B. Free Exercise Claim
We now consider whether the Religious Exclusion violates
the Free Exercise Clause of the First Amendment.3 The Free
Exercise Clause guarantees that "Congress shall make no law
respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free
exercise thereof," U.S. Const. amend. I (emphasis added), and it
has been applied to the States through the Fourteenth Amendment.
See Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U.S. 296, 303 (1940).
3
Appellants do not challenge the Anti-Aid Exclusion under the
Free Exercise Clause.
-15-
The protections provided by the Free Exercise Clause may
be broken down into a number of conceptual categories, none of
which are implicated by the Religious Exclusion. First and
foremost, the Free Exercise Clause entails an absolute prohibition
on government infringement on the "freedom to believe." Torcaso v.
Watkins, 367 U.S. 488, 492-93 (1961). Because the prohibition is
absolute, laws which infringe on individuals' freedom of belief are
per se unconstitutional. Id. (refusing to consider the state's
asserted justifications for a law that infringed on citizens'
freedom of belief); see also West Virginia State Bd. of Educ. v.
Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943) (holding that a state could not
compel students in public schools to salute the flag, where their
religion forbade it). However, that prohibition is inapposite here
because the Religious Exclusion does not hinge on the religious
beliefs of initiative proponents. See McDaniel v. Paty, 435 U.S.
618, 627 (1978) (finding that a Tennessee law that precluded
ministers from eligibility as constitutional convention delegates
did not infringe on freedom of belief, but nevertheless
invalidating it under strict scrutiny).
In McDaniel v. Paty, the Supreme Court examined a state
law preventing a minister from serving as a constitutional
convention delegate under strict scrutiny, because although it did
not directly burden his religious beliefs, it directly burdened his
religious "status, acts, and conduct." McDaniel, 435 U.S. at 626-
-16-
27. This protection is related to, though distinct from, the per
se prohibition on laws infringing on belief. Arguing from
McDaniel, plaintiffs maintain that a state violates the Free
Exercise Clause when it creates a general political process, but
excludes some from access to that process on the basis of religion.
However, plaintiffs fail to explain how this proposition applies to
their case. The Religious Exclusion prevents anyone from proposing
new laws or constitutional amendments relating to religion through
the initiative process. It does not exclude religious people, or
people of a certain religion, from proposing laws or amendments.
In other words, a religious individual of any particular faith,
like any other citizen, can propose a new law or amendment on any
subject that is open to amendment by initiative.
Moreover, the Religious Exclusion we are asked to
scrutinize does not distinguish based on religious status.4 Like
the scholarship program at issue in Locke v. Davey, the Religious
Exclusion does not deny plaintiffs "the right to participate in the
political affairs of the community," 540 U.S. at 720
4
Plaintiffs claim that McDaniel stands for the proposition that
opponents of a law need not show that the law imposes a particular
burden on religious belief or practice. Although this may be true
as a general proposition, this leaves plaintiffs to argue that they
are being discriminated against on the basis of religious "status,"
as was the case in McDaniel. 435 U.S. at 626-27 (finding violation
of plaintiff's right to Free Exercise of religion where his status
as a minister resulted in discrimination). However, plaintiffs
make no headway with this argument because they cannot show that
the Massachusetts Religious Exclusion treats people differently
based on their religious "status."
-17-
(distinguishing Locke from McDaniel, 435 U.S. 618); nor does it
"require[] [plaintiffs] to choose between their religious beliefs
and receiving a government benefit." Id. at 720-21 (distinguishing
Hobbie v. Unemployment Appeals Comm'n of Fla., 480 U.S. 136 (1987);
Thomas v. Review Bd. of Ind. Employment Security Div., 450 U.S. 707
(1981); Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398 (1963)). The exclusion
applies equally to measures proposed by any group or individual,
regardless of their religious affiliation or lack thereof.
Having concluded that the Religious Exclusion does not
discriminate on the basis of religious belief or status, we also
briefly note that plaintiffs make no colorable argument that the
exclusion prohibits any religious act or conduct. It does not, for
example, preclude performing rites required by their religion, see
Church of the Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520,
533 (1993) (outlawing animal sacrifice central to the Santería
religion), or single out their religion's method of worship, see
Fowler v. Rhode Island, 345 U.S. 67 (1953) (preventing Jehovah's
Witnesses from meeting in public parks while other denominations
were allowed to hold services). The Supreme Court has stated its
reluctance to strike down "legislation which imposes only an
indirect burden on the exercise of religion, i.e., legislation
which does not make unlawful the religious practice itself."
Braunfeld v. Brown, 366 U.S. 599, 606 (1961). Certainly, the
amendments that plaintiffs want to propose may be motivated by
-18-
their religious beliefs, but they do not claim that working to pass
those amendments is an aspect of practicing their religion.
Finally, plaintiffs ask us to consider whether the
passage of the Religious Exclusion was motivated by animus toward
religion. The Supreme Court has considered the existence of animus
motivating a law's proponents when determining whether the law
violates the Free Exercise Clause of the First Amendment. See,
e.g., Locke, 540 U.S. at 725 (finding nothing in the history, text
or application of the Washington scholarship program in question
"that suggests animus towards religion"). In the Establishment
Clause context, the Supreme Court has "often stated the principle
that the First Amendment forbids an official purpose to disapprove
of a particular religion or of religion in general." Church of the
Lukumi, 508 U.S. at 532 (noting that "[t]hese cases, however, for
the most part have addressed governmental efforts to benefit
religion or particular religions, and so have dealt with a question
different, at least in its formulation and emphasis, from the issue
here"). Although plaintiffs present significant evidence of animus
against Catholics in Massachusetts in 1855 when the Anti-Aid
Amendment was passed, they fail to show that religious animus
motivated the passage of the Religious Exclusion in 1918.
Plaintiffs rely heavily on one statement made by the Religious
Exclusion's sponsor, indicating that he would "protect the
initiative and referendum against the religious fanatics and
-19-
against the professional religionists." However, we need not reach
the question of whether this type of fervor against religiously
motivated political action would require that the amendment be
struck down, because plaintiffs present no evidence that the other
members of the Constitutional Convention of 1917-1918 acted from
similar motivations. Given the wide margin by which the Religious
Exclusion passed, and the significant Catholic representation at
the Convention, we see no evidence that animus against religion was
a motivating factor behind the Exclusion's passage.
Furthermore, plaintiffs cite to no case in which evidence
of animus toward religion was itself sufficient to invalidate a
government action, without the animus being tied to some resulting
infringement on freedom of belief or on religious status, acts or
conduct. While we must apply strict scrutiny when "the object of
a law is to infringe upon or restrict practices because of their
religious motivation," plaintiffs here have not shown that the
Religious Exclusion results in any restriction of their religious
practices. Id. at 533 (citing Employment Div., Dept. of Human
Resources of Ore. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 878-79 (1990)) (emphasis
added) (considering evidence of animus toward the Santería religion
where the ordinance prohibiting ritual slaughter of animals did
not, on its face, target the Santería religion, but effectively
outlawed one of the religion's "principal forms of devotion").
-20-
C. Equal Protection
Plaintiffs also argue that the Massachusetts Exclusions
violate the protections afforded by the Equal Protection Clause.
U.S. Const. amend. XIV. Plaintiffs argue that the Religious
Exclusion violates equal protection guarantees because it infringes
on the fundamental right to religious free exercise, disadvantages
a suspect class, and fails the more searching rational basis review
required in Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620 (1996). They also
challenge the Anti-Aid Exclusion under a suspect classification
theory and a disparate impact theory. Because of the complexity of
the various equal protection arguments presented, we will address
the arguments one at a time, to the extent that is possible. In
the end, we affirm the district court's grant of summary judgment
against plaintiffs' equal protection claims.
1. Alleged Violation of the Equal Protection Fundamental
Right to Free Exercise of Religion
Before moving to what we see as the substance of
plaintiffs' equal protection claims, we first address their
argument that the Massachusetts Exclusions restricts their
fundamental right to free exercise of religion. Where a
plaintiff's First Amendment Free Exercise claim has failed, the
Supreme Court has applied only rational basis scrutiny in its
subsequent review of an equal protection fundamental right to
religious free exercise claim based on the same facts. Locke, 540
U.S. at 721, n.3 (citing Johnson v. Robison, 415 U.S. 361, 375, n.
-21-
14, (1974)).5 Because we held, above, that the Religious Exclusion
does not violate the Free Exercise Clause, we apply rational basis
scrutiny to the fundamental rights based claim that this exclusion
violates equal protection. For the reasons stated throughout this
opinion, we find that the Massachusetts Exclusions pass such
review.
2. Plaintiffs' Claim that the Religious and Anti-Aid
Exclusions Implicate a Suspect Classification
The central equal protection issue presented is whether
the Massachusetts Religious Exclusion and Anti-Aid Exclusion
impermissibly distort the political process to the disadvantage of
religious individuals. Because we find that the Religious
Exclusion does not draw distinctions based on a suspect
5
In Locke, the Court quickly dismissed Davey's equal protection
claims. The Court explained that "[b]ecause we hold . . . that the
program is not a violation of the Free Exercise Clause, . . . we
apply rational-basis scrutiny to his equal protection claims."
Locke, 540 U.S. at 721, n.3. It bears clarifying that we do not
read this statement to be a blanket rule that where a Free Exercise
Claim fails, all equal protection claims based on the same facts
must also fail. Looking back to Johnson v. Robinson, we interpret
this line of Supreme Court cases to apply only to the extent that
the related equal protection claims are based on a theory that the
law or governmental action in question "interferes with the
fundamental constitutional right to the free exercise of religion."
Johnson, 415 U.S. at 375, n.14. Other types of equal protection
claims may have independent force, and must be considered
accordingly. See id. (finding that only rational basis review
could be applied to plaintiff's equal protection claim insofar as
it was based on interference with the fundamental right to freedom
of religion, and then separately, though briefly, considering the
merits of plaintiff's claim that "conscientious objectors are a
suspect class deserving special judicial protection").
-22-
classification, we hold that it does not violate the Equal
Protection Clause.
Plaintiffs claim that the Religious Exclusion and Anti-
Aid Exclusion draw distinctions on the basis of religion, which
they argue is a suspect classification for purposes of equal
protection analysis.6 However, even assuming that religious
classification should be treated as suspect, we do not see how the
Religious Exclusion and Anti-Aid Exclusion draw distinctions among
Massachusetts citizens based on a suspect classification. The
Religious Exclusion prohibits initiative petitions that concern
"religion, religious practices or religious institutions." The
Anti-Aid Exclusion precludes amendment by initiative of the Anti-
Aid Amendment, which, in addition to containing Massachusetts' free
exercise clause, prevents state funding for private institutions.
On their face, the Exclusions simply carve out particular subject
matters from the initiative process. They do not require different
treatment of any class of people because of their religious
beliefs. They do not give preferential treatment to any particular
religion. See Larson v. Valente, 456 U.S. 228, 246 (1982)
6
But see Tribe, American Constitutional Law § 16-13 at 1465 (2d
ed. 1988) ("Thus far, the cases have limited such strict scrutiny
to instances of prejudice operating to the detriment of racial or
ancestral groups."); see also San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v.
Rodríguez, 411 U.S. 1, 61 (1973) (naming race as the prime example
of a suspect classification, and listing national origin, alienage,
indigency and illegitimacy -- but not religion -- as other
classifications that are sometimes considered suspect).
-23-
(holding, on First Amendment grounds, that "a state law granting a
denominational preference" must be treated as suspect, and
subjected to strict scrutiny). In short, this is not the classic
violation of equal protection in which a law creates different
rules for distinct groups of individuals based on a suspect
classification. See, e.g., Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.S. 303
(1879) (overturning state law which limited jury service to white
men only).
The Supreme Court has, nevertheless, sometimes struck
down facially neutral laws, which it recognized were crafted to
avoid facial discrimination. See, e.g., Hunter v. Erickson, 393
U.S. 385, 387-91 (1969) (invalidating an amendment to the Akron,
Ohio city charter, which, in addition to the usual vote by the city
council, required approval by a majority of the city's voters for
any ordinance regulating real estate transactions "on the basis of
race, color, religion, national origin or ancestry," even though
the law "on its face treats [African-American] and white, Jew and
gentile in an identical manner"); Washington v. Seattle School
Dist. No. 1, 458 U.S. 457 (1982) (striking down a Washington
initiative that prohibited school boards from requiring children to
be bused to more distant public schools, while at the same time
making exceptions for every imaginable impetus for busing other
than racial integration). Unlike the Massachusetts Exclusions, the
law in Hunter evinces a clear, solely detrimental effect on a
-24-
suspect class. In Hunter, the law's one obvious result was to make
it more difficult to pass laws prohibiting racial discrimination.
Hunter, 393 U.S. at 391. Similarly, in Washington, although the
initiative did not say so on its face, children could be bused to
a more distant school for virtually any reason except racial
integration. 458 U.S. at 471. In contrast, the Massachusetts
Religious Exclusion prevents both initiatives that would disfavor
as well as those that might benefit religion, and the Anti-Aid
Exclusion, in addition to preventing amendment of the clause
precluding funding to private institutions, also prohibits
amendment of Massachusetts' free exercise clause. Unlike the laws
invalidated in Hunter and Washington, it is undeniable that the
Massachusetts Exclusions both hinder and help the causes of the
alleged suspect class.7
Certainly any form of invidious discrimination because of
religion is forbidden. But "the Establishment Clause and the Free
Exercise Clause[] are frequently in tension." Locke, 540 U.S. at
7
Moreover, in both Hunter and Washington, the Supreme Court found
that the laws were purposely aimed solely at unlawful goals.
Washington, 458 U.S. at 471 (noting that neither the initiative's
sponsors, nor the lower courts, had any difficulty perceiving the
racial aim of the initiative); Hunter, 393 U.S. at 392 (recognizing
Akron's decision to "move slowly in the delicate area of race
relations" as a euphemism for placing an obstacle in the path of
progress against racial discrimination). We address the question
of discriminatory purpose below in considering plaintiffs'
disparate impact argument. We conclude that plaintiffs failed to
present evidence sufficient to prove a uniquely discriminatory
purpose in this case.
-25-
718. States may properly refuse to enact laws that they reasonably
believe may tend to establish religion. While the free exercise of
religion is guaranteed, state support of religion is, in general,
disfavored. And we know of no constitutional principle that
prevents a state from determining that sensitive measures that
relate to religion, religious practices, or religious institutions
should not be made or initiated by the public initiative process
but rather only via the legislature. A state might fear that such
measures, if presented as public referenda, might be more likely to
fuel religious strife or to result in enactments unfair to
religious (or non-religious) minorities. Bearing these
distinctions in mind, we are disinclined to extend the race-based
Hunter and Washington lines of cases to this context, which so
closely mirrors the mandates found in our federal Establishment
Clause and Free Exercise Clause.
3. Plaintiffs Have Not Shown Discriminatory Intent
Plaintiffs further argue that the Anti-Aid Exclusion
violates the Equal Protection Clause on a disparate impact theory.
However, this argument fails because plaintiffs have not shown a
discriminatory purpose behind the exclusion. "[A] law, neutral on
its face and serving ends otherwise within the power of government
to pursue," is not invalid under the Equal Protection Clause simply
because it may disproportionately affect a suspect class.
Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229, 242 (1976). "An unwavering line
-26-
of cases from [the Supreme Court] holds that a violation of the
Equal Protection Clause requires state action motivated by
discriminatory intent; the disproportionate effects of state action
are not sufficient to establish such a violation." Hernández v.
New York, 500 U.S. 352, 372-73 (1991). Plaintiffs present evidence
that widespread anti-Catholic prejudice was a motivating factor
behind passage of the original Anti-Aid Amendment in 1855, a fact
which defendants do not dispute. However, the Anti-Aid Amendment
was largely overhauled in 1917, with the support of 85 of the 94
Catholic delegates to the Constitutional Convention, and soon
afterwards, the Anti-Aid Exclusion was passed with similarly broad
support. No evidence has been offered that the exclusion was
motivated by the same Anti-Catholic animus that impelled the
passage of the original Anti-Aid Amendment. Plaintiffs cannot mix
and match the intent behind one amendment and place it with the
impact of a later, distinct amendment. Thus, without reaching the
question of whether the Anti-Aid Exclusion has a disparate effect
on religious individuals, we reject plaintiffs' equal protection
disparate impact argument because plaintiffs fail to show the
required discriminatory intent.
4. Rational Basis Review Under Romer v. Evans
Having rejected plaintiffs' arguments that the
Massachusetts Exclusions should be subjected to strict scrutiny, we
conclude by considering whether the exclusions survive rational
-27-
basis review. "[I]f a law neither burdens a fundamental right nor
targets a suspect class, we will uphold the legislative
classification so long as it bears a rational relation to some
legitimate end." Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 631 (1996)
(striking down an amendment to the Colorado Constitution that would
have precluded protection from discrimination on the basis of
sexual orientation as failing rational basis review). In this
case, we have no difficulty finding that Massachusetts' goal of
preventing the establishment of religion is a legitimate one.
Additionally, the chosen means clearly bear a rational relation to
that end. Thus, the instant case is easily distinguished from
Romer, where the Court found that passage of the Colorado amendment
could only be explained by "'a bare . . . desire to harm a
politically unpopular group,'" which "'cannot constitute a
legitimate governmental interest.'" Id. at 634 (quoting Dep't of
Agric. v. Moreno, 413 U.S. 528, 534 (1973)).
III. Conclusion
For the foregoing reasons, the decision of the district
court is affirmed.
Affirmed.
-28-