United States Court of Appeals
For the First Circuit
No. 08-1569
PAUL SIMMONS; PEDRO VALENTIN; DENNIS BELDOTTI,
Plaintiffs, Appellees/Cross-Appellants,
v.
WILLIAM FRANCIS GALVIN,
in his capacity as Secretary of the Commonwealth of Massachusetts,
Defendant, Appellant/Cross-Appellee.
APPEAL FROM THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT
FOR THE DISTRICT OF MASSACHUSETTS
[Hon. Mark L. Wolf, U.S. District Judge]
Before
Lynch, Chief Judge,
Torruella and Boudin, Circuit Judges.
Kenneth W. Salinger, Assistant Attorney General, and Peter
Sacks, Assistant Attorney General, with whom Martha Coakley,
Attorney General of Massachusetts, was on brief for
appellant/cross-appellee.
Christopher P. Silva with whom Thomas H. Wintner, Gail E.
Cornwall, and Edwards Angell Palmer & Dodge, LLP were on brief for
appellee/cross-appellant.
July 31, 2009
LYNCH, Chief Judge. By nearly a two-to-one margin in the
year 2000, Massachusetts voters passed Article 120, which amended
the state constitution to disqualify currently incarcerated felons
from voting in certain elections. Shortly thereafter, the state
legislature extended this disqualification by statute, Chapter 150,
to prevent inmates from voting in all Massachusetts elections.
In 2001, several incarcerated felons in state custody,
challenged these provisions (collectively "Article 120") by suing
the Secretary of the Commonwealth in federal court. This appeal
concerns two of their claims: (1) that the Commonwealth's
disenfranchisement provisions violated the Voting Rights Act
("VRA") § 2, 42 U.S.C. § 1973, because the percentage of imprisoned
felons who are Hispanic or African-American is higher than the
percentages of those groups in the population of the state; and (2)
that the provisions violated the Ex Post Facto Clause, U.S. Const.
art. I, § 10, as to those inmates who were not disqualified from
voting before the these provisions took effect. As to their claim
under the VRA, the plaintiffs make no allegation of any intentional
discrimination or of any history by Massachusetts of intentional
discrimination against minority voters. All they have claimed is
that past practices in the Massachusetts criminal justice system
produced inmate populations which, in combination with the
disqualification of inmates imprisoned for felonies, have resulted
-2-
in disproportionate disqualification of minorities from voting.
Theirs is a claim of disparate impact.
After allowing initial discovery, the district court in
2007 denied the Commonwealth's motion for entry of judgment on the
pleadings on plaintiffs' VRA claim but granted the Commonwealth's
motion for summary judgment on the Ex Post Facto Clause argument.
We think it clear from the language, history, and context
of the VRA that Congress never intended § 2 to prohibit the states
from disenfranchising currently incarcerated felons. We do not say
that direct vote denial claims of other types may not be brought
under § 2, only that no VRA claim is stated against a state law
which disenfranchises incarcerated felons. We reverse and order
the dismissal of the VRA § 2 claim. We affirm the grant of summary
judgment on the Ex Post Facto claim.
I.
A. Enactment of the Massachusetts Incarcerated Felon
Disenfranchisement Provisions
Before Article 120 was enacted, prisoners were able to
vote by absentee ballot. In 1997, there was an unsuccessful
proposal for legislation to disenfranchise currently incarcerated
persons for certain felonies: murder, rape, other sex-related
offenses, and controlled substances offenses. Massachusetts
prisoners responded by forming a political action committee
("PAC"), aimed at influencing criminal justice issues, including
-3-
sentencing, prison reform, and "Draconian laws on punishment."
PACs, inter alia, raise money for and endorse candidates.
State elected officials reacted swiftly. On August 12,
1997, then-Acting Governor Cellucci proposed a constitutional
amendment that would disenfranchise all incarcerated individuals
(not just felons), saying:
Criminals behind bars have no business
deciding who should govern the law-abiding
citizens of the Commonwealth. This proposed
amendment will ensure that criminals pay their
debt to society before they regain their right
to participate in the political process.
The legislature did not act on this proposal. Rather, the
legislature approved a different proposed amendment that would
disenfranchise only those currently incarcerated for felonies.
Lawmakers received the legal opinions of House and Senate Counsel
that such an alternative amendment would be constitutional under
the U.S. Constitution.
Article 120, the proposed amendment to Article 3 of the
Amendments to the state constitution, was presented to the voters
along with an Information for Voters Guide. That Guide constitutes
relevant legislative history. The Guide included 150-word
arguments written by proponents and opponents of each ballot
question. The statement from the proponents stated, "A yes vote
prevents criminals serving time for a felony conviction from voting
in Massachusetts's elections while in jail." The proponents
argued:
-4-
When someone in Massachusetts is sentenced to
jail for committing a felony, we deprive them
of their liberty and right to exercise control
over their own lives, yet current law allows
these same criminals to continue to exercise
control over our lives by voting from prison.
This amendment will change the law that gives
jailed criminals the right to vote.
Massachusetts is one of only three states in
our nation where felons serving time may vote
while in jail. Voting yes on this important
question will make the Commonwealth the 48th
state to prohibit the practice of allowing
convicted criminals to vote from jail. This
change discriminates against no one except
jailed criminals.
The Guide also contained the opponents' argument:
The Constitution of Massachusetts is clear on
this point: Citizens retain their right to
vote even while incarcerated. The founders of
Massachusetts intended this right, and our
Supreme Judicial Court affirmed in in 1977.
In the history of the Commonwealth, we have
never amended our Constitution in order to
narrow fundamental rights. There is no reason
to do so now.
No one has alleged that prisoner voting has
harmed our democracy or social fabric. Very
few prisoners vote, and no one claims that
prisoner voting has negatively influenced any
election. Stripping incarcerated felons of
their right to vote serves no public safety
function. It will not deter crime, repair the
harm done by crime, nor help to rehabilitate
prisoners.
The voters approved the amendment with 60.3% voting "yes"
to 33.9% voting "no," and 5.8% of voters not casting a vote on the
question. The amendment took effect on December 6, 2000. Article
3 now reads:
-5-
Every citizen of eighteen years of age and
upwards, excepting persons who are
incarcerated in a correctional facility due to
a felony conviction, and excepting persons
under guardianship and persons temporarily or
permanently disqualified by law because of
corrupt practices in respect to elections who
shall have resided within the town or district
in which he may claim a right to vote, six
calendar months next preceding any election of
governor, lieutenant governor, senators or
representatives, shall have a right to vote in
such election of governor, lieutenant
governor, senators and representatives; and no
other person shall be entitled to vote in such
election.
Mass. Const. amend. art. 3 (emphasis added).
The Massachusetts legislature then enacted Chapter 150 of
the Acts of 2001, which effectuated Article 120 by broadening the
ban on felon voting to cover all Massachusetts elections and by
changing the statutory requirements for obtaining absentee ballots.
Chapter 150 took effect November 27, 2001. Unlike many other
states, Massachusetts does not disqualify convicted felons from
voting once they are released from prison.
B. Procedural History of the Litigation
Plaintiffs Paul Simmons, an African-American, Pedro
Valentin, a Hispanic-American, and Dennis J. Beldotti, a
Caucasian-American, are Massachusetts residents currently in the
custody of the Massachusetts Department of Correction for felonies
they committed on or before December 5, 2000. Plaintiffs were
eligible to be Massachusetts voters before that date, but the
record does not reveal whether they were registered to vote.
-6-
Plaintiffs' pro se complaint was amended twice by court-
appointed counsel. Their final amended complaint alleged that
Article 120 violates § 2 of the VRA because it has a
"disproportionately adverse effect on the voting rights of
African-Americans and Hispanic Americans compared to its effect on
the voting rights of other citizens." This effect "is caused by,
among other things, the facts that African-Americans and
Hispanic-Americans are over-represented in the population of
Massachusetts incarcerated felons, and that there exists
considerable racial and ethnic bias, both direct and subtle, in the
Massachusetts court system."1 Article 120, plaintiffs contended,
"interact[s] with social and historical conditions to cause an
inequality in the opportunities enjoyed by minority and
non-minority voters to elect their preferred representatives."
In describing plaintiffs' complaint, which alleges a
"vote denial" claim, we distinguish vote denial cases from vote
dilution2 claims under § 2 of the VRA. The Supreme Court first
1
By "over-represented" the complaint referred to the
representation of African-Americans and Hispanic-Americans in the
prison population compared with their representation in the
Massachusetts population at large, but gave no statistics.
2
Vote dilution claims comprise the vast majority of § 2
claims. See E. Katz et al., Documenting Discrimination in Voting:
Judicial Findings Under Section 2 of the Voting Rights Act Since
1982, 39 U. Mich. J.L. Reform 643, 650 (2005), available at
http://sitemaker.umich.edu/votingrights/files/finalreport.pdf; D.P.
Tokaji, The New Vote Denial: Where Election Reform Meets the Voting
Rights Act, 57 S.C. L. Rev. 689, 709 (2006) ("[I]t is clear that
the overwhelming majority of Section 2 lawsuits since 1982 have
-7-
articulated the distinction in explaining that "[t]he right to vote
can be affected by a dilution of voting power as well as by an
absolute prohibition on casting a ballot." Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S.
630, 640 (1993) (quoting Allen v. State Bd. of Elections, 393 U.S.
544, 569 (1969)). Thus in voting rights parlance, "'[v]ote denial'
refers to practices that prevent people from voting or having their
votes counted." D.P. Tokaji, The New Vote Denial: Where Election
Reform Meets the Voting Rights Act, 57 S.C. L. Rev. 689, 691
(2006). Vote denial cases challenge practices such as literacy
tests, poll taxes, white primaries, and English-only ballots. Id.
By contrast, vote dilution challenges involve "practices that
diminish minorities' political influence," such as at-large
elections and redistricting plans that either weaken or keep
minorities' voting strength weak. Id.; see also P.S. Karlan, The
Impact of the Voting Rights Act on African Americans, in Voting
Rights and Redistricting 121, 122 (M.E. Rush ed., 1998).
To be clear, plaintiffs did not allege and have disavowed
making a § 2 vote dilution claim, such as that the votes of
African-Americans and Hispanics who are not imprisoned for felonies
have been diluted by Article 120. This case also does not involve
any claim that generalized rules or practices governing the
administration of elections have resulted in a disproportionate
involved claims of vote dilution and not vote denial."); see
generally, Bartlett v. Strickland, 129 S. Ct. 1231, 1240-41 (2009)
(plurality opinion).
-8-
denial of votes of minorities. Further, plaintiffs have not
asserted that the state has otherwise created barriers to the
election of minority group members or other participation of
minorities in the political process. Finally, the plaintiffs'
complaint made no allegation that the Commonwealth acted with
racially discriminatory intent or purpose in enacting Article 120,
and plaintiffs have specifically disavowed any such claim. This is
a claim based purely on the allegation that Article 120 has a
disparate impact on minorities by disqualifying from voting
imprisoned felons.
In support of their pleadings, the complaint referred to
and appended a 1994 Final Report by the Commission to Study Racial
and Ethnic Bias in the Courts to the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial
Court ("SJC").3 Plaintiffs alleged the legislators were aware of
or should have been aware of the conclusions in that 1994 Report.
That 1994 Report, however, was not referenced in or part of the
Voters Guide, and there is no claim the voters were aware of it.
3
The specific findings in the 1994 Commission Report, as
stated in the pleadings, included that "racial minorities were
underrepresented in jury pools selected from communities with
large racial and ethnic populations; that Massachusetts courts are
an unfriendly environment for people whose primary language is not
English . . . ; and that minorities are underrepresented in [the]
Massachusetts bar and bench." The 1994 Report itself goes on to
say, as to sentencing, that it lacked the necessary data to "test
[the] hypothesis" that "[r]acial and ethnic bias may influence
sentencing decisions." The report did not conclude that any race
bias resulted in minority defendants being sentenced as felons.
-9-
Plaintiffs further alleged that Article 120 is punitive
in purpose and effect and therefore violates the Ex Post Facto
Clause as to those inmates who committed their offenses before the
disenfranchisement measures took effect.
The relief sought was a declaration that Article 120 was
unconstitutional under the Ex Post Facto Clause and illegal under
§ 2 of the VRA, injunctive relief, and costs and attorneys' fees.
Plaintiffs unsuccessfully moved for a preliminary
injunction; defendant opposed, filing affidavits which described
the legislative history of Article 120 and the ratification
process. The parties conducted written discovery.4 Defendant then
moved for summary judgment as to the Ex Post Facto and equal
protection claims and for judgment on the pleadings as to the VRA
§ 2 claim on January 12, 2007. The plaintiffs opposed the
Commonwealth's motions and also cross-moved for summary judgment as
to the Ex Post Facto and equal protection claims.
On August 30, 2007, the district court granted the
Commonwealth's motion for summary judgment on the Ex Post Facto
Clause claim and the equal protection claim and denied plaintiffs'
4
Plaintiffs served interrogatories and document requests on
defendant William Galvin, Secretary of the Commonwealth, seeking
data as to the effect of Article 120 on minorities. For example,
plaintiffs requested through interrogatories information on all
individuals who have been arrested in Massachusetts since 1985 by
name, date of birth, Social Security Number, race, ethnicity, skin
color, and/or alleged offense. Defendant replied saying defendant
did not maintain such records and had no responsive information.
-10-
cross-motion. The court denied the Commonwealth's motion on the
VRA claim. On January 16, 2008, the district court certified its
order on the VRA claim for interlocutory appeal. Plaintiffs
petitioned to cross-appeal on the Ex Post Facto and equal
protection claims. This court granted leave to appeal all three
claims under 28 U.S.C. § 1292(b). Plaintiffs have abandoned the
Equal Protection Clause claim and contest only the Ex Post Facto
Clause ruling, and the Commonwealth appeals the denial of its
motion for judgment on the pleadings as to the VRA § 2 claims.
C. Standard of Review
Our review of the court's ruling on both claims is de
novo, and we take the facts in the light most favorable to the
plaintiffs. Estate of Bennett v. Wainwright, 548 F.3d 155, 163,
165 (1st Cir. 2008) (considering dismissals under Rule 12(c) and
Rule 56). We treat the denial of a motion for judgment on the
pleadings "much like a Rule 12(b)(6) motion to dismiss."
Pérez-Acevedo v. Rivero-Cubano, 520 F.3d 26, 29 (1st Cir. 2008).5
"[T]o survive a Rule 12(b)(6) motion (and, by extension, a Rule
5
Despite the nomenclature of the defendant's motion on the
VRA § 2 claim as a motion for judgment on the pleadings, in fact
both sides brought additional undisputed materials to the court's
attention. "In reviewing a motion [for judgment on the pleadings]
under Rule 12(c) . . . we may consider 'documents the authenticity
of which are not disputed by the parties; . . . documents central
to plaintiffs' claim; [and] documents sufficiently referred to in
the complaint.'" Curran v. Cousins, 509 F.3d 36, 44 (1st Cir.
2007) (alteration and omission in original) (quoting Watterson v.
Page, 987 F.2d 1, 3 (1st Cir. 1993)).
-11-
12(c) motion) a complaint must contain factual allegations that
'raise a right to relief above the speculative level, on the
assumption that all the allegations in the complaint are true.'"
Id. (quoting Bell Atl. Corp. v. Twombly, 127 S. Ct. 1955, 1965
(2007)). Nonetheless, questions of statutory interpretation are
questions of law ripe for resolution at the pleadings stage. Gen.
Motors Corp. v. Darling's, 444 F.3d 98, 107 (1st Cir. 2006)
("Statutory interpretation typically raises questions of law
engendering de novo review.").
II.
VRA § 2 CLAIM
Plaintiffs' § 2 challenge is to the Massachusetts law
disenfranchising only currently incarcerated felons. Article 120
is among the narrowest of state felon disenfranchisement
provisions.6 Only two states permit incarcerated felons to vote,
and Massachusetts is one of thirteen jurisdictions that limit
disenfranchisement to the period of incarceration. Currently,
thirty-five states prevent felons from voting during the period of
their parole or probation or both. Eleven states disenfranchise
6
See Developments in the Law -- One Person, No Vote: The
Laws of Felon Disenfranchisement, 115 Harv. L. Rev. 1939, 1942-49
(2002) (surveying state felon disenfranchisement statutes). This
led the student law review note to comment: "The nation seems to be
nearing a consensus that the presently incarcerated should not have
the right to vote." Id. at 1942.
-12-
felons beyond the term of their incarceration, probation, and
parole. Two states disenfranchise felons for life.
The question of state felon disenfranchisement laws and
the VRA § 2 has been addressed by five circuits. Four circuits,
including two en banc, have rejected § 2 challenges to broader
disqualifications; one panel in the Ninth Circuit had allowed such
a § 2 challenge to go forward, although it was ultimately
unsuccessful. The Second Circuit, consistent with our holding
here, has rejected a § 2 challenge to a state statute
disenfranchising prisoners, as well as parolees. Hayden v. Pataki,
449 F.3d 305 (2d Cir. 2006) (en banc). Faced with a state lifetime
felon disenfranchisement law, the Eleventh Circuit concluded in an
en banc decision that all felon disenfranchisement claims are
excluded from the scope of § 2 of the VRA. Johnson v. Gov. of
Fla., 405 F.3d 1214 (11th Cir. 2005) (en banc). Two circuits have
rejected similar claims on the pleadings without directly
considering whether felon disenfranchisement statutes are immune
from attack under § 2. Howard v. Gilmore, No. 99-2285, 2000 WL
203984, at *1 (4th Cir. Feb. 23, 2000) (per curiam); Wesley v.
Collins, 791 F.2d 1255, 1259-61 (6th Cir. 1986) (treating claim as
a dilution claim). Our conclusion accords with that of the
majority of the circuits.
A Ninth Circuit panel decision has concluded that some
disenfranchisement statutes, not as narrow as this one, may be
-13-
challenged under § 2. Farrakhan v. Washington, 338 F.3d 1009 (9th
Cir. 2003) (addressing disenfranchisement of those convicted of an
"infamous crime" until those former felons comply with civil rights
restoration statute). Over a dissent by seven judges, the Ninth
Circuit denied the state's petition for rehearing en banc in that
case, Farrakhan v. Washington, 359 F.3d 1116, 1116 (9th Cir. 2004)
(Kozinski, J., dissenting). On remand, judgment was entered for
the state. Farrakhan v. Gregoire, No. CV-96-076-RHW, 2006 WL
1889273 (E.D. Wash. July 7, 2006).
A. Constitutional Background to the VRA § 2 Claim
Under the U.S. Constitution, the states generally set the
eligibility criteria for voters. "[T]he Constitution 'does not
confer the right of suffrage upon any one.'" Rodriguez v. Popular
Democratic Party, 457 U.S. 1, 9 (1982) (quoting Minor v.
Happersett, 88 U.S. (21 Wall.) 162, 178 (1875)); see also U.S.
Const. art. I, § 4; id. amend. XIV, § 2; Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98,
104 (2000) (per curiam) ("The individual citizen has no federal
constitutional right to vote for electors for the President of the
United States unless and until the state legislature chooses a
statewide election as the means to implement its power to appoint
members of the electoral college.").
The criteria for eligibility to vote are defined by the
states, subject to certain federal restrictions, such as the
federal constitutional prohibition on exclusion from the franchise
-14-
on the basis of race, sex, or payment of a poll tax. "No function
is more essential to the separate and independent existence of the
States and their governments than the power to determine within the
limits of the Constitution the qualifications of their own voters
for state, county, and municipal offices." Oregon v. Mitchell, 400
U.S. 112, 125 (1970).
The power of the states to disqualify from voting those
convicted of crimes is explicitly set forth in § 2 of the
Fourteenth Amendment. The Supreme Court has held, "the exclusion
of felons from the vote has an affirmative sanction in § 2 of the
Fourteenth Amendment." Richardson v. Ramirez, 418 U.S. 24, 55
(1974). Section 2 concerns the abridgement of the right to vote at
any election for "President and Vice President of the United
States, Representatives in Congress, the Executive and Judicial
officers of a State, or members of the Legislature." U.S. Const.
amend. XIV, § 2. The Amendment specifically excludes (from its
non-abridgement language) and thus provides for the denial by
states of the right to vote to persons "for participation in
rebellion, or other crime." Id. The Fourteenth Amendment also
grants Congress the power to enforce, by appropriate legislation,
the provisions of that article. Id. § 5. Thus, the state's denial
of the right to vote to felons has a constitutional grounding.
-15-
Broad felon disenfranchisement provisions are
presumptively constitutional. See Richardson, 418 U.S. at 54-55.7
There, the Court rejected a non-race-based equal protection
challenge to the felon disenfranchisement provision of
California's constitution. The Supreme Court has continued to
adhere to Richardson. See Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 634
(1996) (describing principle that states may disenfranchise a
convicted felon as "unexceptionable").
Richardson, to be clear, does not hold that a state felon
disenfranchisement law may never raise equal protection concerns.
If a state enacts a law which disenfranchises felons "with the
intent of disenfranchising blacks," that state has run afoul of
§ 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment. Hunter v. Underwood, 471 U.S.
222, 229 (1985) (holding Alabama's petty crime and misdemeanor
disenfranchisement provisions unconstitutional under Equal
Protection Clause based on evidence of discriminatory intent); see
also City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 477
n.25 (1985) ("[In Hunter], we did not suggest that felons could
not be deprived of the vote through a statute motivated by some
purpose other than racial discrimination."). Here, plaintiffs
make no allegation of intentional discrimination, and on appeal
7
The SJC has also recognized that under Richardson states
may disenfranchise felons. Dane v. Bd. of Registrars of Voters,
371 N.E.2d 1358, 1364 (Mass. 1978) ("Disfranchisement of convicted
criminals by State law was held by the . . . Supreme Court in
Richardson . . . not to violate the equal protection clause.").
-16-
they allege no constitutional violation other than the Ex Post
Facto claim. By definition, then, plaintiffs do not assert that
whatever discrimination existed in the state's criminal justice
system rose to the level of an independent constitutional
violation which caused the vote denial.
A state's interest in preventing "persons who . . . were
not eligible to vote because they had been convicted of felonies"
from inflating its voter rolls was accepted only last year by the
Supreme Court as a "neutral and nondiscriminatory reason" for a
voter identification law. Crawford v. Marion County Election Bd.,
128 S. Ct. 1610, 1619-20 (2008).
The legitimacy of the reasons for this state interest in
disqualifying imprisoned felons from voting is apparent. Judge
Henry Friendly some time ago described some of the pragmatic
purposes underlying disenfranchisement laws:
[I]t can scarcely be deemed unreasonable for a
state to decide that perpetrators of serious
crimes shall not take part in electing the
legislators who make the laws, the executives
who enforce these, the prosecutors who must
try them for further violations, or the judges
who are to consider their cases.
Green v. Bd. of Elections, 380 F.2d 445, 451 (2d Cir. 1967).8
8
There are philosophical reasons as well, such as that those
who violate the laws so seriously have removed themselves from the
Lockean notion of the social contract:
The early exclusion of felons from the
franchise by many states could well have
rested on Locke's concept, so influential at
the time, that by entering into society every
-17-
Here, the Commonwealth enacted this prohibition after
prisoners attempted to organize to change the laws under which
they were convicted, sentenced, and imprisoned. The state has a
strong interest in setting its own qualifications for voters, a
strong interest in the integrity of its system of enforcing and
administering its criminal laws, and a strong interest in how its
correctional systems are maintained and run. Preiser v.
Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 475, 491-92 (1973) ("It is difficult to
imagine an activity in which a State has a stronger interest . . .
than the administration of its prisons."); cf. Hayden, 449 F.3d at
327. The Massachusetts provision, it is important to note, is
narrowly tailored. Because the disqualification is confined to
currently imprisoned felons, the state interests it serves are
clearly at their strongest.
Further, Article 120 of the Massachusetts constitution
does not raise issues about a history of laws in Massachusetts,
including felon disenfranchisement laws, that were used
deliberately to impede voting by minorities. Such historical
man "authorizes the society, or which is all
one, the legislature thereof, to make laws for
him as the public good of the society shall
require, to the execution whereof his own
assistance (as to his own decrees) is due." A
man who breaks the laws he has authorized his
agent to make for his own governance could
fairly have been thought to have abandoned the
right to participate in further administering
the compact.
Green, 380 F.2d at 451.
-18-
concerns about practices in other states have been the subject of
academic commentary. See, e.g., G. Brooks, Comment, Felon
Disenfranchisement: Law, History, Policy and Politics, 32 Fordham
Urb. L.J. 851, 858-59 (2005) (concluding that the VRA does not
reach state felon disenfranchisement laws). Plaintiffs have made
no claim that Massachusetts has historically ever used any tests
or devices to discourage minority voting or minority candidates.
Nor is there any claim that Massachusetts has defined Article 120
disenfranchisement in terms of felonies that have higher
conviction rates for minorities than for whites. Cf. Hunter, 471
U.S. at 229.
B. Text, Context and Legislative History of § 2
It is against the backdrop of the Constitution's express
approval of felon disenfranchisement provisions, which were not
motivated by intentional race discrimination, that Congress
enacted the VRA in 1965.
Section 2 of the VRA, 42 U.S.C. § 1973, as amended in
1982, now provides:
(a) No voting qualification or prerequisite
to voting or standard, practice, or procedure
shall be imposed or applied by any State or
political subdivision in a manner which
results in a denial or abridgement of the
right of any citizen of the United States to
vote on account of race or color . . . .
(b) A violation of subsection (a) is
established if, based on the totality of
circumstances, it is shown that the political
processes leading to nomination or election in
-19-
the State or political subdivision are not
equally open to participation by members of a
class of citizens protected by subsection (a)
in that its members have less opportunity than
other members of the electorate to participate
in the political process and to elect
representatives of their choice.
While the language of the original § 2 tracked the language of the
Fifteenth Amendment, prohibiting practices that deny or abridge
the right to vote on account of race, the 1982 amendment to § 2
inserted the phrase "results in a denial or abridgment."
§ 1973(b) (emphasis added). The amendment of § 2 also made clear
that an abridgement or denial could be identified "as provided in
subsection (b)," which was added by the 1982 amendments.
To start, it is clear that under the plain terms of the
statute, not every "voter qualification" is actionable under § 2.
For § 2 to apply, the burden is on the plaintiffs to make other
showings, including that the qualification "results in a denial or
abridgement of the right of any citizen of the United States to
vote on account of race or color." § 1973(a); see also Metts v.
Murphy, 363 F.3d 8, 12 (1st Cir. 2004) (en banc) (per curiam).
Plaintiffs' theory of how they meet this burden under § 2
is that from the very enactment of § 2 in 1965, the broad language
of § 2 has created a cause of action on these facts. Article 120,
they contend, is obviously a voter disqualification and the
disqualification results in a denial of the right to vote "on
account of race" because the percentages of incarcerated felons
-20-
who are black or Hispanic are higher than those two groups in the
population as a whole.
Plaintiffs argue the language of § 2(a) is so clear it
stands alone and that rules of statutory construction prohibit
consideration of the history or context of § 2.9 Plaintiffs' claim
assumes that felon disenfranchisement laws are not different from
and should be treated like any other voting qualification under
§ 2. That assumption is a fatal flaw in their case. Felon
disenfranchisement statutes are not like all other voting
qualifications. Congress has treated such laws differently. They
are deeply rooted in our history, in our laws, and in our
Constitution. We conclude Congress did not intend § 2 to provide
a cause of action against Article 120.
As a matter of textual analysis, it is neither plain nor
clear that plaintiffs' claim fits within the text of § 2(a). For
example, it is logical to understand the state law
9
In addition, plaintiffs contend § 2(a) must be read to be
independent of § 2(b), which was added by the 1982 amendments. And
even if § 2(b) is read as informing and restricting the meaning of
§ 2(a), plaintiffs submit, they have nonetheless stated a claim
under the clear language of § 2(a).
Plaintiffs alternatively argue that, to the extent § 2(b)
may be considered, it only establishes a totality of the
circumstances test for proving a violation of § 2(a) and in no way
limits the scope of § 2(a). Plaintiffs argue that, to the extent
§ 4 and § 5 (which ban certain practices) are relevant, those later
sections demonstrate only that Congress meant § 2(a) to be read
broadly. If legislative history is consulted, they argue that the
legislative history of § 2 establishes that their claim falls
within Congress's intent in enacting § 2.
-21-
disenfranchisement of incarcerated felons as not "resulting" in a
denial "on account of race or color" but on account of
imprisonment for a felony, and thus not within the text of § 2 at
all.10 We agree with the Second Circuit that the language of
§ 2(a) is both broad and ambiguous and that judicial
interpretation of a claim concerning felon disenfranchisement
under the VRA may not be limited to the text of § 2(a) alone. See
Hayden, 449 F.3d at 315 (citing Watt v. Alaska, 451 U.S. 259, 266
(1981); Boston Sand & Gravel Co. v. United States, 278 U.S. 41,
48(1928)).
Under any set of rules of construction, our inquiry into
§ 2(a) neither starts nor ends with an examination of that text.
"[S]tatutory interpretation turns on 'the language itself, the
specific context in which that language is used, and the broader
context of the statute as a whole.'" Nken v. Holder, No. 08-681,
___ S. Ct. ___, 2009 WL 1065976, at *6 (Apr. 22, 2009) (quoting
Robinson v. Shell Oil Co., 519 U.S. 337, 341 (1997)).
Under Supreme Court precedent, we cannot adopt
plaintiffs' limited approach. The direction to look at context,
10
There are questions as to whether a claim of disparate
impact is sufficient to state a § 2 vote denial case. See Johnson,
405 F.3d at 1235-37 (Tjoflat, J., concurring); see also Goosby v.
Town Bd. of Hempstead, 180 F.3d 476, 499 (2d Cir. 1999) (Leval, J.,
concurring); Nipper v. Smith, 39 F.3d 1494, 1524-25 (11th Cir.
1994) (en banc); LULAC v. Clements, 999 F.2d 831, 859-63 (5th Cir.
1993) (en banc). Whether a claim of mere disproportionality alone
supports a "resulting" claim is not clear under § 2 and is a
difficult question we need not reach.
-22-
structure, history, and constitutional concerns is particularly
true of the VRA, a complex statute with an extensive legislative
history and caselaw. See Nw. Austin Mun. Util. Dist. No. 1 v.
Holder, No. 08-322, ___ S. Ct. ___, 2009 WL 1738645 at *10 (June
22, 2009) ("[S]pecific precedent, the structure of the Voting
Rights Act, and underlying constitutional concerns compel a
broader reading of the [VRA's] bailout provision."). The Supreme
Court itself, in deciding § 2 cases has never resorted to plain
text alone to give § 2 meaning. See, e.g., Chisom v. Roemer, 501
U.S. 380, 397 (1991). It has commonly used legislative history.
See League of United Latin Am. Citizens v. Perry, 548 U.S. 399,
426 (2006); see also 2A N.J. Singer & J.D. Singer, Sutherland
Statutes and Statutory Construction § 48A:11 (7th ed. 2008) ("In
reviewing legislative history, the Court consults . . . committee
reports, floor debates, hearings, rejected proposals, and even
legislative silence.").
In examining § 2, we are required to comply with "the
cardinal rule that a statute is to be read as a whole," King v.
St. Vincent's Hosp., 502 U.S. 215, 221 (1991). As "the meaning of
statutory language, plain or not, depends on context," id., we
must "look not only to the particular statutory language, but to
the design of the statute as a whole and to its object and
policy." Dada v. Mukasey, 128 S. Ct. 2307, 2317 (2008) (quoting
-23-
Gozlon-Peretz v. United States, 498 U.S. 395, 407 (1991))
(internal quotation marks omitted).
When we look at the terms of the original VRA as a whole,
the context, and recognized sources of congressional intent, it is
clear the original § 2 of the VRA of 1965 was not meant to create
a cause of action against a state which disenfranchises its
incarcerated felons. The purposes and congressional history of
the 1982 amendments, as well as congressional action after 1982,
further confirm our understanding that § 2 does not encompass this
claim.
1. The Original VRA of 1965
The original VRA was enacted against the background of
explicit constitutional and congressional11 approval of state felon
disenfranchisement laws and expressed no intention to invalidate
such laws, but rather an intention to leave such laws untouched.
Prior to the enactment of the VRA, enforcement of the
Fifteenth Amendment guarantee that the "right of citizens of the
United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged . . . on
account of race, color, or previous condition of servitude," U.S.
Const. amend. XV, § 1, was unsatisfactory. Nw. Austin, 2009 WL
1738645 at *4.
11
Indeed, in re-admitting southern states to the Union
following the Civil War, Congress approved new state constitutions
containing felon disenfranchisement provisions. Richardson, 418
U.S. at 48-52.
-24-
In 1965, Congress enacted the VRA with the intent to
"banish the blight of racial discrimination in voting, which ha[d]
infected the electoral process in parts of our country for nearly
a century." South Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383 U.S. 301, 308
(1966). Plaintiffs' claim here concededly does not involve any
such intent. The language of the original § 2 "tracked . . . the
text of the Fifteenth Amendment," Bartlett, 129 S. Ct. at 1240.
The Court emphasized this point when it said that the original § 2
did "no more than elaborate[] upon . . . the Fifteenth Amendment,"
id. at 1241 (omission in original) (quoting City of Mobile v.
Bolden, 446 U.S. 55, 60-61 (1980) (plurality opinion)) (internal
quotation marks omitted). The VRA's original object was plainly
to combat specific forms of racial discrimination.12 Beyond § 2,
the remainder of the VRA set up a scheme of stringent remedies to
address the most flagrant practices. "[T]he Act directly
pre-empted the most powerful tools of black disenfranchisement in
the covered areas. All literacy tests and similar voting
qualifications were abolished by §4 of the Act." Nw. Austin, 2009
WL 1738645, at *4 (citing Voting Rights Act of 1965, §§ 4(a)-(d),
79 Stat. 437, 438-439).
12
Plaintiffs rely heavily on the Court's statement, in a vote
dilution case, that Congress intended "to give the Act the broadest
possible scope," Allen v. State Bd. of Elections, 393 U.S. 544, 567
(1969) (interpreting the phrase "qualification . . . or procedure"
in § 2(a)). This language in Allen must be understood in light of
the Court's other statements in subsequent cases, including Bolden
and Bartlett.
-25-
The legislative history of the VRA shows that Congress
was not silent with respect to felon disenfranchisement laws. In
fact, Congress explicitly considered the effect of the VRA on
state felon disenfranchisement laws, and did so under § 4, rather
than under § 2.13 Section 4 of the VRA bans any "test or device"
that impermissibly limits the franchise. 42 U.S.C. § 1973b(c).
Congress, in enacting § 4(c) proscribed several categories of
historically discriminatory tests or devices, including some
literacy tests, educational achievement or knowledge tests, and
good moral character qualifications. But Congress was careful to
carve out from its proscription of tests for good moral character
any and all state felon disenfranchisement laws. H.R. Rep. No.
89-439 (1965), reprinted in 1965 U.S.C.C.A.N. 2437, 2547-57. In
excluding felon disenfranchisement laws from the scope of § 4,
Congress took the view that it did not consider such laws to be a
discriminatory voter qualification or a "tool[] of black
disenfranchisement." Nw. Austin, 2009 WL 1738645, at *4.
The Senate Judiciary Committee Report explicitly stated
that this § 4 prohibition on tests and devices "would not result
in the proscription of the frequent requirement of States and
political subdivisions that an applicant for voting or
registration for voting be free of conviction of a felony or
13
The 1965 legislative history indicates that Congress
focused much more attention on the import of § 4 and § 5 than on
§ 2 of the VRA.
-26-
mental disability." S. Rep. No. 89-162 (1965), reprinted in 1965
U.S.C.C.A.N. 2508, 2562 (joint views of Senators Dodd, Hart, Long,
Kennedy, Bayh, Burdick, Tydings, Dirksen, Hruska, Fong, Scott, and
Javits).
The House Report confirms the Senate's understanding. It
stated that the VRA "does not proscribe a requirement of a State
or any political subdivision of a State that an applicant for
voting or registration for voting be free of conviction of a
felony or mental disability." H.R. Rep. No. 89-439, reprinted in
1965 U.S.C.C.A.N. at 2457.
In drafting the VRA, Congress considered felon
disenfranchisement statutes, and it viewed them as a potential
test or device that fell within the purview of § 4 and not § 2.
We are not free to second guess Congress's categorizations of
felon disenfranchisement statutes. Further, Congress made clear
that it did not purport to outlaw state felon disenfranchisement
statutes based on their effect. Rather, under § 4, Congress
enumerated and outlawed tests or devices it viewed as
disqualifications excluding minority voters. Felon
disenfranchisement laws were specifically removed from this
category by Congress and were considered nondiscriminatory.
In light of this express history, Congress could not have
intended to create a cause of action under § 2 of the VRA against
disenfranchisement of incarcerated felons while saying explicitly
-27-
elsewhere that it did not intend to proscribe any such laws.
Other courts agree with our conclusion. Hayden, 449 F.3d at 319
("[I]t is apparent to us that Congress's effort to highlight the
exclusion of felon disenfranchisement laws from a VRA provision
that otherwise would likely be read to invalidate such laws is
indicative of its broader intention to exclude such laws from the
reach of the statute."); see also Farrakhan, 359 F.3d at 1120-21
(Kozinski, J., dissenting from denial of reh'g en banc).
This point is buttressed by another aspect of § 4. As
drafted in 1965, § 4 applied to covered jurisdictions.14 Congress
would not have permitted felon disenfranchisement laws in covered
jurisdictions where there was a history of discrimination, while
prohibiting them in non-covered jurisdictions like Massachusetts.
To subject felon disenfranchisement in a non-covered jurisdiction
to a VRA cause of action while prohibiting such a cause of action
for a covered jurisdiction would itself raise significant
constitutional concerns. See Nw. Austin, 2009 WL 1738645, at *9.
If there were any doubt as to Congress's intent not to
create a cause of action against laws like Article 120, other
14
Congress continued to revisit the discriminatory tests or
devices banned by § 4. Later VRA amendments extended the § 4 ban
on literacy tests nationwide. See Voting Rights Act Amendments of
1970, Pub. L. No. 91-285, § 201, 84 Stat. 314, 315 (current version
at 42 U.S.C. § 1973aa) (extending temporary ban to entire nation);
Voting Rights Act Amendments of 1975, Pub. L. No. 94-73, § 201, 89
Stat. 400, 400-01 (current version at 42 U.S.C. §§ 1973b-1973c)
(making the temporary nationwide ban permanent). Congress never
changed its view that felon disenfranchisement laws were not within
the reach of the VRA.
-28-
actions show congressional acceptance of even broader felon
disenfranchisement laws than involved here, reinforcing the
conclusion that § 2 was not meant to proscribe laws such as
Article 120. In 1971, just six years after passing the VRA,
Congress affirmatively enacted a broader felon disenfranchisement
statute covering both imprisoned and paroled felons in the
District of Columbia, over which it then exercised plenary power.
Act of Dec. 23, 1971, Pub. L. No. 92-220, § 4, 85 Stat. 788, 788;
see also Hayden, 449 F.3d at 315. Congress would not have
prohibited states from imposing such disqualifications when it
imposed them itself on the District.
Further, between the passage of the VRA in 1965 and the
1982 amendments, Congress considered and rejected proposals to
amend the VRA15 to prohibit certain types of state felon
disenfranchisement laws. Congress understood that the VRA, as
enacted in 1965, did not permit claims against state felon
disenfranchisement laws and that amendment of the VRA would be
needed to permit such suits, and it declined to make those
amendments. Two points are important. First, Congress rejected
each those proposed amendments. Second, even those rejected
amendments would have precluded suits raising claims of
15
The 1975 Amendments to the VRA added protections for
linguistic minorities and permanently banned literacy tests. 1975
Amendments §§ 203, 207, 89 Stat. at 401-02 (codified as amended at
42 U.S.C. §§ 1973b(f), 1973l(c)(3)). Nothing in those amendments
indicated any intent to broaden the VRA to permit suits against
state laws disenfranchising incarcerated felons.
-29-
disenfranchisement of a "citizen [who] is confined in a
correctional facility at the time of such . . . election," as does
Article 120 now at issue. See Ex-Offenders Voting Rights: Hearing
on H.R. 9020 Before the Subcomm. on Courts, Civil Liberties, and
the Administration of Justice of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary,
93d Cong. 4 (1974).
In 1972, the House Judiciary Committee held hearings on
"The Problems of the Ex-Offender." See Corrections, Part VI,
Illinois: The Problems of the Ex-Offender: Hearing Before Subcomm.
No. 3 of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 92d Cong. (1972). In
response to these hearings, several prominent VRA advocates in
Congress jointly introduced a bill designed "to amend the [VRA] to
prohibit the States from denying the right to vote in Federal
elections to former criminal offenders who have not been convicted
of any offense related to voting or elections and who are not
confined in a correctional institution." Hayden, 449 F.3d at 319
(emphasis added) (quoting H.R. 15,049, 92d Cong. (1972)) (internal
quotation marks omitted). The bill did not result in legislation.
Id.
Similarly, Congress held hearings in 1973 expressly
addressing but not adopting proposed amendments to the VRA to
allow challenges to felon disenfranchisement for only that
category of ex-offenders who were not imprisoned.16 See
16
The proposed amendment would have authorized "the Attorney
General . . . to institute in the name of the United States such
-30-
Ex-Offenders Voting Rights: Hearing on H.R. 9020, supra, 93d Cong.
1-38; see also Hayden, 449 F.3d at 319.
Plaintiffs' claim that § 2 as drafted in 1965 permits a
cause of action against Article 120 fails.
2. The 1982 Amendments
We reject plaintiffs' position that § 2(b), added in
1982, may not be considered in analyzing whether they have a claim
under § 2(a).17 Furthermore, we conclude that those amendments,
while altering the law as to vote dilution claims and perhaps as
to other claims (which we need not decide), undercut plaintiffs'
arguments that Congress intended the VRA to reach laws
disenfranchising incarcerated felons.
actions against States . . . including actions for injunctive
relief, as he may determine to be necessary to implement the
purposes of this title." Ex-Offenders Voting Rights: Hearing on
H.R. 9020, supra, at 4 (quoting H.R. 9020, 93d Cong. (1973)).
17
Under Supreme Court and circuit precedent, we read both §
2(a) and § 2(b) together and resort to legislative history. The
text of § 2(b) is explicit that its purpose is to give content and
context to the terms used in § 2(a). The Supreme Court has
interpreted both sections together. See Bartlett, 129 S. Ct. at
1241 ("The 1982 amendments . . . added . . . § 2(b), providing a
test for determining whether a § 2 violation has occurred.");
Chisom, 501 U.S. at 395 ("The two purposes of the amendment [to
§ 2] are apparent from its text. Section (a) adopts a results test
. . . . Section (b) provides guidance about how the results test
is to be applied.").
This court's precedent also requires we read §§ 2(a) and
2(b) together and in light of history and context. See Metts, 363
F.3d at 10 ("The Delphic language of the [1982] amendment [to § 2]
can be understood only against the background of its legislative
history and subsequent Supreme Court interpretation.").
-31-
The 1982 amendments did not alter the prior understanding
that the VRA did not reach the disenfranchisement of currently
incarcerated felons. When "Congress adopts a new law
incorporating sections of a prior law, Congress normally can be
presumed to have had knowledge of the [administrative or judicial]
interpretation given to the incorporated law, at least insofar as
it affects the new statute." Lorillard v. Pons, 434 U.S. 575, 581
(1978). Nothing in the text, context,18 or history supports
plaintiffs' position.
The Supreme Court held that "Congress amended § 2 of the
VRA to make clear that certain practices and procedures that
result in the denial or abridgement of the right to vote are
forbidden even though the absence of proof of discriminatory
intent protects them from constitutional challenge." Chisom, 501
U.S. at 383-84 (emphasis added); Johnson, 405 F.3d at 1228. Felon
disqualification was not among those certain practices and
procedures.
18
The context of the 1982 amendments confirms our
understanding that § 2 was not amended in isolation from the rest
of the statute and must be read in conjunction with the other
sections, including § 4. The 1982 amendments to § 2 arose in the
wake of Bolden because § 5 of the VRA was scheduled for
reauthorization in that year by the terms of the 1975 VRA
amendments. S. Issacharoff et al., The Law of Democracy 713-14
(rev. 2d ed. 2002). Indeed, in the House, most debate focused on
the structure of the preclearance and bailout provisions of the
VRA, while less attention focused on the § 2 amendments. Id. at
716; see also T.M. Boyd & S.J. Markman, The 1982 Amendments to the
Voting Rights Act: A Legislative History, 40 Wash. & Lee L. Rev.
1347 (1983).
-32-
Plaintiffs admirably admit that Congress's specific
purpose in amending § 2 of the VRA19 was to overrule certain
aspects of the Supreme Court's decision in Bolden, which was
concerned with vote dilution claims, not direct denial claims. We
explain. Prior to Bolden, in White v. Regester, 412 U.S. 755
(1973), minority plaintiffs had successfully challenged a state
districting plan on vote dilution grounds. There, the Court did
not require a showing of discriminatory intent. See id. at 766.
By contrast, the Bolden plurality held that state action "that is
racially neutral on its face violates the Fifteenth Amendment only
if motivated by a discriminatory purpose," 446 U.S. at 61, and
altered the White evidentiary standard in vote dilution cases to
19
Congress was clear about its intent. The Senate Report
states:
This Amendment is designed to make clear that
proof of discriminatory intent is not required
to establish a violation of Section 2. It
thereby restores the legal standards, based on
the controlling Supreme Court precedents,
which applied in voting discrimination claims
prior to the litigation involved in Mobile v.
Bolden. The amendment also adds a new
subsection to Section 2 which delineates the
legal standards under the results test by
codifying the leading pre-Bolden vote dilution
case, White v. Regester.See S. Rep. No.
97-417, at 2, reprinted in 1982 U.S.C.C.A.N.
177, 179; see also id. at 27, reprinted in
1982 U.S.C.C.A.N. at 205 ("The 'results'
standard is meant to restore the pre-Mobile
legal standard which governed [vote dilution
cases].").
-33-
require direct evidence of discriminatory intent.20 See Bartlett,
129 S. Ct. at 1240-41.
In 1982, Congress focused on reversing this aspect of
Bolden and clarifying the standard for vote dilution claims.
Congress aimed to reinstate the "results test," which had been the
rule developed in the pre-Bolden case law for vote dilution claims
under White. See Metts, 363 F.3d at 10 (stating the 1982
amendments made it clear that "discriminatory intent is not a
necessary element in a violation and that Congress [instead]
intended a broad range of factors to be taken into account"). But
the reinstated, multifactored results test was not meant to extend
to this limited felon disenfranchisement claim any more than the
pre-Bolden tests were. Nothing in the legislative history of
§ 2(b) indicated any intent to expand the VRA to create a cause of
action against a state felon disenfranchisement law such as
Article 120. To the contrary, in enacting § 2, Congress noted
that it was impossible to predict the variety of means that would
be used to infringe on the right to vote and that the voting
rights landscape was marked by innovation in discrimination. S.
Rep. No. 89-162, at 5 (1965); S. Rep. No. 89-439, at 10. But
these concerns do not go to felon disenfranchisement, which was
20
The Bolden plurality also held that the "language of § 2
[of the VRA] no more than elaborates upon that of the Fifteenth
Amendment, and the sparse legislative history of § 2 makes clear
that it was intended to have an effect no different from that of
the Fifteenth Amendment itself." 446 U.S. at 61.
-34-
neither a new innovation nor a predictable future innovation.
Felon disenfranchisement was a well-known and accepted part of the
voting landscape. "The Senate Report, which details many
discriminatory techniques used by certain jurisdictions, made no
mention of felon disenfranchisement provisions." Johnson, 405
F.3d at 1234; see also Tokaji, supra, at 707 ("The legislative
history of the 1982 amendments thus shows that Congress was almost
exclusively focused on vote dilution claims.").21
Further, the language of § 2(b) undercuts plaintiffs'
assertion they have stated a claim under § 2(a). The text of
subsection (b) protects a "class of citizens" who by law may and
should enjoy as full an "opportunity [as] other members of the
electorate to participate in the political process." § 1973(b).
For a host of valid reasons, incarcerated prisoners cannot
participate in the political process equally with free citizens
outside the prison walls. Hayden, 449 F.3d at 342 (Jacobs, J.,
concurring). As noted by Hayden, "There is no question that
incarcerated persons cannot 'fully participate in the political
process' -- they cannot petition, protest, campaign, travel, freely
associate, or raise funds." Id. at 321.
Further, the 1982 Congress amended § 2 to assuage
expressed fears that the courts would interpret a results test as
21
We need not reach the question of whether this amendment
was meant to reach other types of § 2 claims than vote dilution
claims; even if so, the amendments were not meant to create a cause
of action against imprisoned felon disenfranchisement laws.
-35-
a requirement for proportional representation in vote dilution
cases, and therefore the statute was amended to expressly disclaim
any right to proportional representation. § 1973(b) ("[N]othing in
this section establishes a right to have members of a protected
class elected in numbers equal to their proportion in the
population."); Tokaji, supra, at 705-06. This suggests that
Congress was fundamentally concerned with remedying discrimination
in voting, rather than guaranteeing proportionality in political
representation. See, e.g., S. Issacharoff, Polarized Voting and the
Political Process, 90 Mich. L. Rev. 1833 (1992). Plaintiffs' claim,
which is based on mere disproportionality in the prison population
from felon disenfranchisement, does not implicate these concerns.
3. Post-1982 Congressional Actions Assume the
Validity of State and Federal Felon
Disenfranchisement Laws
Congressional action, both after 1982 and in the
aftermath of Bush v. Gore, also undercuts the plaintiffs' reading
of the amended § 2 to support a claim against imprisoned felon
disenfranchisement laws. These statutes show continuing
congressional approval of state laws disenfranchising imprisoned
felons. The National Voter Registration Act of 1993, which
generally restricts states' ability to remove names from the voter
rolls, explicitly exempts state decisions to disenfranchise
individuals "by reason of criminal conviction." 42 U.S.C.
§ 1973gg-6(a)(3)(B). The Help America Vote Act of 2002 directs
-36-
states to remove disenfranchised felons from their lists of those
eligible to vote in federal elections. 42 U.S.C.
§ 15483(a)(2)(A)(ii)(I). These two recent statutes are entirely
inconsistent with reading § 2, whatever its breadth, to create a
cause of action against Article 120.
Further, Congress has continued to consider and reject
numerous proposals to require states to enfranchise even former
felons. Even these efforts have expressly excluded currently
incarcerated felons. See, e.g., Civic Participation and
Rehabilitation Act of 1999: Hearing on H.R. 906 Before the Subcomm.
on the Constitution of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 106th Cong.
1, 3 (2000) (quoting H.R. 906, 106th Cong. (1999)).22
Congress has excepted from the reach of the VRA
protections from vote denial for claims against a state which
disenfranchises incarcerated felons. We do not need to decide23
22
The Civic Participation and Rehabilitation Act would have
restored the voting rights of ex-felons, but not imprisoned felons,
in federal elections. H.R. 906 was not drafted as an amendment to
the VRA, but contained a savings clause clarifying that the measure
operated in addition the VRA and the National Voter Registration
Act. Civic Participation and Rehabilitation Act of 1999: Hearing
on H.R. 906, supra, at 4. A number of recent unsuccessful bills
are consistent with H.R. 906's proposal to restore the rights of
only former felons. And even these have been flatly rejected by
Congress. See, e.g., Democracy Restoration Act of 2008, S. 3640,
110th Cong. (2008); Democracy Restoration Act of 2008, H.R. 7136,
110th Cong. (2008); Count Every Vote Act of 2005, S. 450, 109th
Cong. (2005); Ex-Offenders Voting Rights Act of 2005, H.R. 663,
109th Cong. (2005).
23
It is doubtful plaintiffs have articulated a viable § 2
direct denial theory, in any event. Plaintiffs have explained only
that they think this claim falls within a broad reading of § 2,
-37-
what is needed to prove a denial (as opposed to a dilution) claim
under § 2 which is not a claim against a state provision
disenfranchising imprisoned felons.24
provided one ignores the text of § 4, the legislative history of
the Act, and the purpose and context of § 2(b). But they have not
explained even what their theory of liability is, what standards a
court would apply, or what the components of a winning claim would
be. This is the situation eight years after they filed suit and
have had discovery from defendants.
The most plaintiffs have suggested is that despite the self-
evident racial neutrality of depriving all incarcerated felons from
voting while imprisoned, there may be some causal connection
between being incarcerated for felonies and their race. But the
very 1994 Commission Report on which they rely concludes that no
such connection was shown. More than that, it concluded that if
one wished to see if such a connection could be shown, the data
simply did not exist to permit the testing of the hypothesis. When
plaintiffs asked the defendant officials in discovery for data
which would presumably assist them, the defendants said they did
not have and did not keep such data.
There is nothing else. Even if one were to look more broadly
at the Senate factors so often used in vote dilution cases, see S.
Rep. No. 97-417, at 28-29 (1982), reprinted in 1982 U.S.C.C.A.N.
177, 206-07, those factors do not aid plaintiffs.
Further, given our disposition of the case, we need not reach
the concerns raised by Judge Kozinski about the role of evidence of
statistical disparities in § 2 challenges. Farrakhan, 359 F.3d at
1119 (Kozinski, J. dissenting from denial of reh'g en banc); see
also Ricci v. DeStefano, No. 07-1428, --- S.Ct. ----, 2009 WL
1835138, at *19 (June 29, 2009) (reliance on threshold showing of
a raw statistical disparity in test results is not strong evidence
of disparate impact).
24
Some have commented on a "potential tension in the case law
[because] . . . section 2 [from 1982 onward] had been used almost
entirely for vote dilution claims [while] [t]he felon
disenfranchisement cases involve an older kind of claim involving
access to the ballot itself; such cases involve not vote dilution
but vote denial." S. Issacharoff et al., The Law of Democracy 140
(rev. 2d ed. Supp. 2006); see Tokaji, supra, at 709 ("While Gingles
and its progeny have generated a well-established standard for vote
dilution, a satisfactory test for vote denial cases under Section
2 has yet to emerge. . . . [and] the Supreme Court's seminal
opinion in Gingles . . . is of little use in vote denial cases.");
Karlan, supra, at 122 (["T]he second generation of voting rights
-38-
Given the historic legitimacy of felon
disenfranchisement, the constitutional recognition of the authority
of states to disenfranchise imprisoned felons, the congressional
recognition of that authority and the express congressional
statements that the VRA was not meant to proscribe that authority,
this is not the case in which to test the standards for other types
of purported direct disenfranchisement claims. While our emphasis
is somewhat different, we agree with the Second Circuit in Hayden
that the seven circumstances it identifies all necessitate the
conclusion that the this claim is not actionable. 449 F.3d at 315-
16.
Plaintiffs have failed to state a claim under VRA § 2.
We have no need to reach the serious constitutional questions which
the Commonwealth argues would be raised were we to adopt plaintiffs'
construction of the statute. In Northwest Austin, the Supreme Court
emphasized the principle that courts, particularly in VRA cases,
should avoid deciding constitutional issues where statutory
interpretation obviates the issue, as here. Nw. Austin, 2009 WL
1738645 at *4 ("Our usual practice is to avoid the unnecessary
resolution of constitutional questions.); see also Hayden, 449 F.3d
at 328 n.24; Johnson, 405 F.3d at 1230.
activity address the problem of racial vote dilution rather than
outright disenfranchisement."); A.A. Peacock, From Beer to
Eternity, in Redistricting in the New Millennium 119, 125 (P.F.
Galderisi ed., 2005) 119, 125 (same).
-39-
III.
EX POST FACTO CLAUSE CLAIM
We turn to plaintiffs' appeal from the district court's
grant of summary judgment in favor of the Commonwealth on the Ex
Post Facto Clause arguments. There are no material facts in dispute
in the record.
Plaintiffs argue the Ex Post Facto Clause was violated
because "the only plainly discernible purpose for Article 120 was
to seek to impose an additional measure of punishment upon those who
had violated the laws of the Commonwealth." Plaintiffs point to the
a transcript of the debates at the 1998 and 2000 Constitutional
Conventions over the bill that ultimately became Article 120.
Plaintiffs also rely on language from Acting Governor Cellucci's
proposed amendment and his statements to the public, an amendment
which was not accepted. These statements include: "The time has
come to tell would-be criminals in Massachusetts that committing
crimes has serious consequences," and that "[p]risons are a place
for punishment." Even though his initial proposal was never in
fact acted on by the legislature, we consider his comments as part
of the background.
Analysis of the Ex Post Facto Clause claim involves a
two-part inquiry. The first asks whether the denial of the right
to vote is a civil, regulatory measure within the meaning of the
caselaw, or whether it is punitive. "[W]here unpleasant
-40-
consequences are brought to bear upon an individual for prior
conduct," the central question "is whether the legislative aim was
to punish that individual for past activity, or whether the
restriction of the individual comes about as a relevant incident to
a regulation of a present situation." De Veau v. Braisted, 363 U.S.
144, 160 (1960) (holding that state statutory bans against
employment of convicted felons in certain jobs did not impose
punishment under Ex Post Facto Clause). Only a punitive measure can
violate the Ex Post Facto Clause. See, e.g., Smith v. Doe, 538 U.S.
84, 92 (2003); see also United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739
(1987) (holding preventative detention under the Bail Reform Act was
permissible because it was regulatory and preventative, rather than
punitive).
The Supreme Court has stated that felon
disenfranchisement provisions are considered regulatory rather then
punitive. In Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86 (1958), the Court
explained:
[A] statute has been considered nonpenal if it
imposes a disability, not to punish, but to
accomplish some other legitimate governmental
purpose. . . . The point may be illustrated by
the situation of an ordinary felon. A person
who commits a bank robbery, for instance,
loses his right to liberty and often his right
to vote. If, in the exercise of the power to
protect banks, both sanctions were imposed for
the purpose of punishing bank robbers, the
statutes authorizing both disabilities would
be penal. But because the purpose of the
latter statute is to designate a reasonable
ground of eligibility for voting, this law is
-41-
sustained as a nonpenal exercise of the power
to regulate the franchise.
Id. at 96-97; see also Lassiter v. N. Hampton County Bd. of
Elections, 360 U.S. 45, 51 (1959) (criminal record is an "obvious"
factor that "a State may take into consideration in determining the
qualifications of voters"). Article 120 is no exception.
Even if the Supreme Court had not already described such
regulation of the franchise with respect to incarcerated felons as
nonpenal, we would still find Article 120 to be a civil regulatory
scheme. In examining Article 120 "on its face," Hudson v. United
States, 522 U.S. 93, 100 (1997), there is no language indicating the
Commonwealth's provision is penal. Article 120 is not in the
Commonwealth's criminal code, but rather its civil constitutional
and statutory voter qualification provisions. See Hendricks, 521
U.S. at 361, ("[The State's] objective to create a civil proceeding
is evidenced by its placement of the Act within the [State's]
probate code, instead of the criminal code" (citations omitted)).
Article 120 also disenfranchises persons under guardianship, persons
disqualified because of corrupt elections practices, and all persons
under eighteen years of age, as well as incarcerated felons. And
the disqualification is enforced civilly, not criminally.
Article 120 does not involve a more general period of
disenfranchisement because of commission of a felony; rather Article
120 is limited to the period of incarceration. Article 120 thus
creates a temporary qualification on the right to vote coincident
-42-
with imprisonment, rather than a long-term consequence for the
commission of a crime.
Article 120 is a constitutional amendment, which was
later effectuated and extended by statute. The voters of
Massachusetts ratified Article 120 in a statewide election. The
Voter Guide read by the voters, which we described earlier, made no
mention of any goal of punishing prisoners. "The Ex Post Facto
Clause does not preclude a State from making reasonable categorical
judgments that conviction of specified crimes should entail
particular regulatory consequences." Smith, 538 U.S. at 1153.
Secondly, even if the legislature intended to deem a
particular law "civil," courts must further inquire whether "the
statutory scheme was so punitive either in purpose or effect as to
negate that intention." United States v. Ward, 448 U.S. 242, 248-49
(1980). "'[O]nly the clearest proof' will suffice to override
legislative intent and transform what has been denominated a civil
remedy into a criminal penalty." Hudson, 522 U.S. at 100 (quoting
Ward, 448 U.S. at 249). Plaintiffs fail to meet this standard.
We review whether plaintiffs' allegations of punitive
purpose meet the non-exclusive factors test set forth in Kennedy v.
Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 168-69 (1963), and followed in
Smith, 538 U.S. at 97.
The Mendoza-Martinez factors are: (1) whether the
sanction involves an affirmative disability or restraint; (2)
-43-
whether it has historically been regarded as punishment; (3) whether
it comes into play only on a finding of scienter; (4) whether its
operation will promote the traditional aims of punishment --
retribution and deterrence; (5) whether the behavior to which it
applies is already a crime; (6) whether there is a rational
connection to a nonpunitive purpose; and (7) whether it appears
excessive in relation to the alternative purpose assigned. Mendoza-
Martinez, 372 U.S. at 168-69. The most relevant factors are whether
felon disenfranchisement "has been regarded in our history and
traditions as a punishment; imposes an affirmative disability or
restraint; promotes the traditional aims of punishment; has a
rational connection to a nonpunitive purpose; or is excessive with
respect to this purpose." Smith, 538 U.S. at 97.
First, Article 120 does not impose any affirmative
disability or restraint, physical or otherwise. See Smith, 538 U.S.
at 100 ("[I]mprisonment . . . is the paradigmatic affirmative
disability or restraint."). Disenfranchisement during the period
of incarceration imposes no additional term of imprisonment, see
Flemming v. Nestor, 363 U.S. 603, 617 (1960), and is not as enduring
as permanent occupational debarment, which the Court has held is
nonpunitive. Hudson, 522 U.S. at 104; De Veau, 363 U.S. at 144;
Hawker v. New York, 170 U.S. 189 (1898) (revocation of a medical
license does not violate Ex Post Facto clause).
-44-
Second, felon disenfranchisement has historically not
been regarded as punitive in the United States, as the Supreme Court
indicated in Trop v. Dulles. Indeed, in holding that felon
disenfranchisement has "affirmative sanction" in § 2 of the
Fourteenth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution, Richardson, 418 U.S.
at 54, the Supreme Court noted the historical prevalence of state
felon disenfranchisement laws and never characterized even
California's broad disqualification of former felons as punitive.
Id. at 55.
As to the third and fifth factors, Article 120 is
effective regardless of a finding of scienter or the type of crime
so long as it is a felony. That Article 120 may be "tied to
criminal activity" is "insufficient to render the statut[e]
punitive." United States v. Ursery, 518 U.S. 267, 291 (1996).
The fourth Mendoza-Martinez factor considers whether
felon disenfranchisement will promote the traditional aims of
punishment, retribution and deterrence, to see whether plaintiffs
have offered the clearest proof to overcome the statement of
nonpenal purpose. Plaintiffs rely on some statements made by some
legislators that could be viewed as retributive, such as that felons
"don't deserve to vote." To the extent the legislators' comments
are relevant, they are sporadic and do not clearly evince a
retributive purpose. More significantly, since Article 120 was put
before the voters, the Information for Voters Guide is a better
-45-
source of context. The Guide contained a balanced debate about the
merits of allowing currently incarcerated felons to vote in state
elections, noted the problem of prisoners being able to affect the
laws under which they were confined by voting, and nowhere suggests
an intent to punish prisoners.
As to the sixth factor, there is an obvious rational
nonpunitive purpose for disenfranchisement: as the Guide shows,
voters were concerned about the influence of currently incarcerated
felons in "exercis[ing] control over [their] lives by voting from
prison." See also Smith, 538 U.S. at 1147 (noting that "even if the
objective of the Act is consistent with the purposes of the [state]
criminal justice system, the State's pursuit of it in a regulatory
scheme does not make the objective punitive."). Finally, Article
120 is not excessive in accomplishing this purpose. Article 120
does not violate the Ex Post Facto Clause.
IV.
The entry of judgment against the plaintiffs' Ex Post
Facto Clause claim is affirmed; the court's denial of the motion to
dismiss the VRA claim is reversed and the case is remanded to the
district court for dismissal of both claims with prejudice. Each
side shall bear its own costs.
So ordered.
-Dissenting Opinion Follows-
-46-
TORRUELLA, Circuit Judge (Dissenting). Lest we be misled
by the majority's choice of emphasis, this is not a case about the
state's authority to disenfranchise convicted felons, nor about the
popularity or desirability of that practice. Were that the issue
before us, I too would be in the majority, as the validity of felon
disenfranchisement laws, as a general matter, has been established.
See Richardson v. Ramirez, 418 U.S. 24, 56 (1974). Moreover, were
that the issue before us, it would not have spawned reams of
conflicting opinions, vigorous dissents and en banc reversals among
our sister circuits.25
Rather this is a case about interpreting a clearly worded
congressional statute, the Voting Rights Act of 1965 ("VRA"),
according to its terms, when there is no persuasive reason to do
otherwise. Nw. Austin Mun. Util. Dist. No. One v. Holder, 557 U.S.
____ (2009), 2009 WL 1738645 at *9 ("The Fifteenth Amendment
25
Compare Farrakhan v. Washington, 338 F.3d 1009 (9th Cir.
2003) (holding that § 2 of the VRA applies to felon
disenfranchisement statutes); Johnson v. Governor of Fla., 353 F.3d
1287 (11th Cir. 2003) (same); Baker v. Cuomo, 58 F.3d 814 (2d Cir.
1995) (same); Howard v. Gilmore, No. 99-2285, 2000 WL 203984, at *1
(4th Cir. Feb. 23, 2000)(assuming without expressly deciding that
§ 2 of the VRA applies to felon disenfranchisement laws and
evaluating plaintiff's vote dilution claim thereunder); Wesley v.
Collins, 791 F.2d 1255 (6th Cir. 1986) (same) with Hayden v.
Pataki, 449 F.3d 305 (2d Cir. 2006) (en banc) (reversing its
previous decision and denying coverage under the § 2 of the VRA for
felon disenfranchisement statutes); Johnson v. Governor of Fla.,
405 F.3d 1214 (11th Cir. 2005) (en banc) (same); Baker v. Pataki,
85 F.3d 919 (2d Cir. 1996) (en banc) (dividing evenly on the
question of whether felon disenfranchisement claim can proceed
under § 2 the VRA, thus reinstating the district court decision
dismissing the claim).
-47-
empowers 'Congress,' not the [c]ourt[s], to determine in the first
instance what legislation is needed to enforce it."). It is also
a case about the constitutional validity of altering the legal
consequences for committing a crime, long after the crime's
completion. Because I disagree with the majority's resolution of
both of these novel issues, I respectfully dissent.
I. Voting Rights Act Claim
Section 2 of the VRA, as amended in 1982, plainly
provides that "[n]o voting qualification or prerequisite to voting
or standard, practice, or procedure shall be imposed or applied by
any State . . . in a manner which results in a denial or abridgement
of the right . . . to vote on account of race or color . . . ." 42
U.S.C. § 1973(2)(a) (emphasis added); see also Nw. Austin, 557 U.S.
at ____, 2009 WL 1738645 at *4. Notably, § 2(a) employs a
"'results'" test, under which proof of discriminatory intent is not
necessary to establish a violation of the section. Chisom v.
Roemer, 501 U.S. 380, 395 (1991). Rather, plaintiffs can state a
§ 2 claim by showing that under the "totality of circumstances," a
"certain electoral law, practice, or structure interacts with social
and historical conditions to cause an inequality in the
opportunities enjoyed by black and white voters to elect their
preferred representatives." Thornburg v. Gingles, 478 U.S. 30, 43-
-48-
44 (1986).26 The allegations in plaintiffs' complaint, which we
must accept as true at this preliminary stage, see Pérez-Acevedo v.
Rivero-Cubano, 520 F.3d 26, 29 (1st Cir. 2008), are that
Massachusetts' Article 120, which disqualifies incarcerated felons
from voting in the Commonwealth, has a disproportionately adverse
effect on the voting rights of African-Americans and Hispanic-
Americans, who are over-represented in the incarcerated felon
population. Plaintiffs allege that this disparate impact is caused,
in part, by racial and ethnic bias in the Massachusetts court
system, and operates to deny these racial minorities the right to
vote, in violation of § 2 of the VRA. Plaintiffs further allege
26
Among the non-exhaustive factors listed by the Senate as
relevant to assessing the validity of a voter qualification is "the
extent to which members of the minority group in the state or
political subdivision bear the effects of discrimination in such
areas as education, employment and health, which hinder their
ability to participate effectively in the political process." S.
Rep. No. 94-417, at 29 (1982), as reprinted in 1982 U.S.C.C.A.N.
177, 207. The ultimate inquiry, according to the Senate Report is
"whether, in the particular situation, the practice operated to
deny the minority plaintiff an equal opportunity to participate and
to elect candidates of their [sic] choice." Id. at 30. The Ninth
Circuit, applying this test, has explicitly held that evidence of
racial bias in the criminal justice system is a relevant "social
and historical condition" for purposes of the totality of the
circumstances test, reasoning that "such discrimination would
clearly hinder the ability of racial minorities to participate
effectively in the political process as disenfranchisement is
automatic." Farrakhan, 338 F.3d at 1020; see also Nipper v. Smith,
39 F.3d 1494, 1513-14 (11th Cir. 1994) (en banc) (holding that the
existence of racial bias in the community is relevant to a § 2
claim). "Thus, racial bias in the criminal justice system may very
well interact with voter disqualifications to create the kinds of
barriers to political participation on account of race that are
prohibited by Section 2." Farrakhan, 338 F.3d at 1020.
-49-
that when enacting Article 120, Massachusetts legislators were aware
of the data regarding racial bias in the criminal justice system.27
The felon disenfranchisement provision at issue is
clearly a "voting qualification." Whether or not this provision
results in the denial of the right to vote "on account of race or
color" under the "totality of the circumstances" remains the
ultimate question for the trier of fact. But "[e]ven if serious
problems lie ahead in applying the 'totality of the circumstances
standard described in [VRA] § 2(b), that task, difficult as it may
prove to be, cannot justify a judicially created limitation on the
coverage of the broadly worded statute, as enacted and amended by
Congress." Chisom, 501 U.S. at 403. Plaintiffs have stated a claim
sufficient to preclude dismissal at this preliminary stage and are
entitled to the opportunity to develop it.
In order to avoid this obvious result, the majority makes
an expansive and unwarranted holding. It holds that despite the
broad language of VRA § 2, covering all "voting qualifications,"
Congress actually never intended for felon disenfranchisement laws,
even discriminatory ones, to be challengeable under that provision.
27
Notably, bearing on the question of plausibility of
plaintiffs' claim, one scholar has found that an analysis of the
factors inducing states to impose or eliminate felon
disenfranchisement provisions concluded that "[s]tates with greater
nonwhite prison populations have been more likely to ban convicted
felons from voting than states with proportionally fewer non-whites
in the criminal justice system." Angela Behrens, et al., Ballot
Manipulation and the "Menace of Negro Domination": Racial Threat
and Felon Disenfranchisement in the United States, 1850-2002, 109
Am. J. Soc. 559, 596 (2003).
-50-
It does so by disregarding the plain and unambiguous text of the
statute and resorting to a collection of secondary evidence, none
of which stand for the proposition the majority seeks to establish.
In the face of so startling a holding, I am left wondering, in the
words of Judge Calabresi, "[w]hat is behind this remarkable decision
to buck text, context, and legislative history in order to insulate
a particular racially discriminatory practice from an
anti-discrimination rule of general applicability?" Hayden, 449
F.3d at 365 (Calabresi, J., dissenting).
The fatal flaw in the majority's reasoning begins with
its improper reliance on legislative history given the plain and
unambiguous language of § 2(a), the section of the VRA governing the
central "applicability" question before us. See Robinson v. Shell
Oil Co., 519 U.S. 337, 340 (1997) ("Our first step in interpreting
a statute is to determine whether the language at issue has a plain
and unambiguous meaning with regard to the particular dispute in the
case." (emphasis added)). The plain language of § 2(a)
unambiguously applies to all "voting qualifications." 42 U.S.C. §
1973. A provision disqualifying incarcerated felons, listed among
the provisions of the Massachusetts Constitution governing
qualifications to vote, clearly constitutes a "voting
qualification." Therefore, where it is alleged, as here, that this
"qualification" is being applied "in a manner which results" in the
denial of the right to vote on account of race, a cognizable VRA
-51-
claim has been stated. Id. As the text of the statute
unambiguously manifests its meaning, there was no need to go any
further in order to conclude that plaintiffs have stated a
cognizable claim under § 2 of the VRA.
This is the reasoning upon which the Ninth Circuit
decision, holding that an identical VRA claim had been stated in
that Circuit, starts and ends. See Farrakhan, 338 F.3d at 1016
("Plaintiff's claim of vote denial [resulting from Washington's
felon disenfranchisement law] is cognizable under Section 2 of the
VRA" because '[f]elon disenfranchisement is a voting qualification,
and Section 2 is clear that any voting qualification that denies
citizens the right to vote in a discriminatory manner violates the
VRA (emphasis added))."28 As Judge Sotomayor similarly explained in
her powerful dissenting opinion in Hayden:
It is plain to anyone reading the Voting
Rights Act that it applies to all 'voting
qualifications.' And it is equally plain that
[the felon disenfranchisement provision at
issue] disqualifies a group of people from
voting. These two propositions should
constitute the entirety of our analysis.
28
The majority attempts to distinguish Farrakhan on the
ground that the Washington provision at issue in that case was "not
as narrow as this one." I, however, see no meaningful difference
between disenfranchising felons until the completion of their
sentences as under the Washington statute, or only while
incarcerated, as in the case before us. In any event, the
narrowness or breadth of a particular felon disenfranchisement
scheme bears no relevance upon the question of whether challenges
to these types of laws are cognizable under the VRA.
-52-
449 F.3d at 367-68; see also Johnson, 405 F.3d at 1247 (Barkett, J.,
dissenting) ("[Plaintiffs'] contention that Florida's felon
disenfranchisement law effectively denies their right to vote
because they are black is clearly encompassed by the plain language
of the VRA.").
The majority cannot dispute "the traditional rule that
where the plain text of the statute is unmistakably clear on its
face, there is no need to discuss legislative history." Succar v.
Ashcroft, 394 F.3d 8, 31 (1st Cir. 2005) (Lynch, J.) (quoting Sutton
v. United Air Lines, Inc., 527 U.S. 471, 481 (1999)). While the
majority cites Nken v. Holder, 129 S. Ct. 1749 (2009) for the
general proposition that statutory interpretations turns on
language as well as context, id. at 1756, neither Nken nor the case
upon which it relies addressed a statute whose plain meaning is as
evident and clear on its face as the one before us. In fact,
contrary to the majority’s contention, even with complicated
statutory schemes like the VRA, courts have not hesitated to rely
on the plain language of the text, where the text plainly answers
the very question before them. See, e.g., Lopez v. Monterey County,
525 U.S. 266, 278-79 (1999); Chisom, 501 U.S. at 396. There is
simply no support in our precedent for disregarding so plain and
unambiguous a statutory mandate based on nothing more than our own
assumption that Congress did not mean what it said. See BedRoc
Ltd., LLC, 541 U.S. at 183 (explaining that absent ambiguity we are
-53-
bound by the "preeminent canon of statutory interpretation [that]
requires us to presume that [the] legislature says in a statute what
it means and means in a statute what it says there" (internal
quotation marks omitted)); United States v. Shreveport Grain &
Elevator Co., 287 U.S. 77, 83 (1928) (quoting Hamilton v. Rathbone,
175 U.S. 414, 421 (1899) for proposition that legislative history
may be resorted to in order "to solve, but not to create, an
ambiguity" (emphasis added)); Ruiz v. Bally Total Fitness Holding
Corp., 496 F.3d 1, 8 (1st Cir. 2007) (explaining that we "are not
free to disregard the plain language of a statute and, instead,
conjure up legislative purposes and intent out of thin air").
Though it is unable to point to any actual textual
ambiguity, the majority nevertheless makes a conclusory assertion
that "[t]he language of § 2(a) is both broad and ambiguous."
Breadth, however, does not render a statute ambiguous. See BedRoc
Ltd., LLC v. United States, 541 U.S. 176, 187 n.8 (2004) ("Where a
law is plain and unambiguous, whether it be expressed in general or
limited terms, the legislature should be intended to mean what they
have plainly expressed, and consequently no room is left for
construction." (emphasis added & citation omitted)); Diamond v.
Chakrabarty, 447 U.S. 303, 315 (1980) ("Broad general language is
not necessarily ambiguous when congressional objectives require
broad terms."). Rather, "a statute is ambiguous only if it admits
of more than one reasonable interpretation." United States v.
-54-
Vidal-Reyes, 562 F.3d 43, 51 (1st Cir. 2009) (quoting United States
v. Godin, 534 F.3d 51, 56 (1st Cir. 2008)). But "[c]onspicuously
absent from the majority opinion is so much as a hint of an
intelligible reading under which [the felon disenfranchisement
provision] is not a 'voting qualification or prerequisite to voting
or standard, practice or procedure.' (What else on earth could [the
provision] possibly be?)". Hayden, 449 F.3d at 346 (Parker, J.,
dissenting). There is simply no reasonable interpretation of § 2
under which a felon disenfranchisement law would not be a "voting
qualification or prerequisite to voting" actionable thereunder.29
Given the clarity of the VRA language, which plainly
encompasses the claim before us, the majority's resort to secondary
sources to justify its contrary result constitutes a "radical
abandonment of our longstanding precedents that permit resort to
legislative history only when necessary to interpret ambiguous
statutory text." Id. at 187 n.8. I cannot endorse this
impermissible practice. But even if, for the sake of argument, I
take up the majority's invitation to investigate history and
context, I find that none of the evidence cited by the majority
29
We acknowledge that § 2(b) of the VRA, containing a
"totality of the circumstances" test for proving a violation of
§ 2(a), may require further interpretation. However, any ambiguity
in § 2(b) is irrelevant to whether a felon disenfranchisement
provision is a voting qualification governed by the Act - a
question which the plain language of § 2(a) unambiguously answers
in the affirmative. See Robinson, 519 U.S. at 340 (identifying the
relevant question as "whether the language at issue has a plain and
unambiguous meaning with regard to the particular dispute in the
case." (emphasis added)).
-55-
indicates congressional intent to exclude felon disenfranchisement
laws from § 2's purview so as to justify departing from the plain
language of that provision. In fact, my reading of the legislative
history is that it confirms the plain meaning of the text.
One need not delve too deeply into the legislative
history to discover that Congress enacted the Voting Rights Act of
1965 pursuant to its powers to enforce the Fifteenth Amendment for
the "broad remedial purpose of 'rid[ding] the country of racial
discrimination in voting.'" Chisom, 501 U.S. at 403 (quoting South
Carolina v. Katzenbach, 383 U.S. 301, 315 (1966)); see also Nw.
Austin, 557 U.S. at ____, 2009 WL 1738645, at *4-5.30 At that time,
although the Fifteenth Amendment guaranteeing the right to vote
without regard to race or color had been in effect for nearly a
hundred years, and thus, intentional discrimination was already
prohibited, states continued to devise facially "neutral" devices
such as gerrymandering, poll taxes, literacy tests and grandfather
clauses, which, coupled with violence and intimidation, served to
effectively bar minorities from access to the polls and preclude the
Fifteenth Amendment's promise of racial equality in voting from
becoming a reality. See Nw. Austin, 557 U.S. at ____, 2009 WL
1738645, at *4-5 (describing "the first century of congressional
30
Notably, despite its insistence on resorting to secondary
sources to ascertain congressional intent, the majority places
curiously little emphasis on the historical and policy
considerations that prompted Congress to pass into law the very
statute whose meaning it endeavors to ascertain.
-56-
enforcement of the [Fifteenth] Amendment" as a "failure" and noting
the "creativ[ity] [of states] in 'contriving new rules' to continue
violating the Fifteenth Amendment" (quoting Katzenbach, 383 U.S. at
335); Andrew L. Shapiro, Note, Challenging Criminal
Disenfranchisement Under the Voting Rights Act: A New Strategy, 103
Yale L. J. 537, 543 (1993). Accordingly, the text of the original
§ 2 "tracked, in part, the text of the Fifteenth Amendment."
Bartlett v. Strickland, 129 S. Ct. 1231, 1240 (2009). While the
legislative history of § 2 of the VRA is silent on the particular
question of felon disenfranchisement, that history does clearly
indicate that Congress intentionally kept § 2(a) as broad as
possible because it found it "impossible to predict the variety of
means that would be used to infringe on the right to vote" and
wanted to encompass all such measures that states could devise.
Johnson, 405 F.3d at 1243 (Wilson, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part); see also Katzenbach, 383 U.S. at 335 (noting
that "Congress knew that some of the States . . . had resorted to
the extraordinary stratagem of contriving new rules of various kinds
for the sole purpose of perpetuating voting discrimination in the
face of adverse federal court decrees" and that "Congress had reason
to suppose that these States might try similar maneuvers in the
future"); H.R. Rep. 89-439, at 10 (1965), reprinted in 1965
U.S.C.C.A.N. 2437 (1965) (describing how, "even after defeat
resisters s[ought] new ways and means of discriminating," and, as
-57-
a result, rejected the case by case approach that "too often ha[d]
caused no change in result, only in methods."). Thus, Congress
intentionally chose the expansive language "voting qualifications
or prerequisite to voting, or standard, practice, or procedure" for
§ 2 so as to be "all-inclusive of any kind of practice" that might
be used by states to deny citizens that right. Allen v. State Bd.
of Elections, 393 U.S. 544, 566-67 (1969) (citing testimony from
Senate Judiciary Committee Hearings on the VRA).31 As the Supreme
Court has held, Congress intended the term "voting qualification"
in § 2 to have the "broadest possible scope" and to reach "any state
enactment which altered the election of a covered State in even a
minor way." Id., 393 U.S. at 566-67.32
31
Indicative of Congress's intent to give this prophylactic
statute the broadest possible scope, it is notable that an earlier
draft of § 2(a) used the slightly narrower language "qualification
or procedure," but during Senate Hearings on the bill, one Senator
expressed concern that the word 'procedure' was not broad enough to
cover all the various practices that might effectively be employed
to deny citizens their right to vote. See Allen, 393 U.S. at
566-67 & n.8 (citing legislative history). In response, the
Attorney General said he had no objection to expanding the language
of the section, to be all-inclusive. Id. Congress then expanded
the language in the final version of § 2 to include any "'voting
qualifications or prerequisite to voting, or standard, practice, or
procedure.'" Id. (quoting 42 U.S.C. § 1973 (1964)).
32
In fact, in his concurrence in Holder v. Hall, Justice
Thomas acknowledged that § 2 of the VRA was broadly phrased "with
an eye to eliminating the possibility of evasion." 512 U.S. 874,
917 (1994) (Thomas, J., Concurring). Although Justice Thomas
argued for a more restrictive interpretation of the scope of § 2
than the majority of the Supreme Court had recognized, his more
restrictive interpretation of the provision was as follows:
[T]he specific items described in § 2(a) . . .
indicate that Congress was concerned in this
-58-
"Criminal disenfranchisement is an outright barrier to
voting that, like the poll tax and literacy test, was adopted in
some states with racially discriminatory intent and has operated
throughout our nation with racially discriminatory results."
Shapiro, supra, at 543.33 Thus, these laws were precisely the type
of potentially discriminatory qualification that Congress intended
to subject to scrutiny under the VRA. Yet the majority definitively
concludes that the VRA of 1965 was not meant to allow such an action
against any felon disenfranchisement law.
section with any procedure, however it might
be denominated, that regulates citizens'
access to the ballot – that is, any procedure
that might erect a barrier to prevent the
potential voter from casting his vote.
Id. (emphasis added). Surely, felon disenfranchisement laws, which
outright bar a segment of the population from voting, fall into
this expansive category.
33
See also George Brooks, Comment, Felon Disenfranchisement:
Law, History, Policy and Politics, 32 Fordham Urb. L.J. 851, 858
(2005) (noting that "[f]elon disenfranchisement was sometimes used
as a tool by the states to disenfranchise blacks" and citing
examples of states passing laws "disenfranchising those convicted
of what were considered to be 'black' crimes, while those convicted
of 'white' crimes did not lose their right to vote"); Virginia E.
Hench, The Death of Voting Rights: The Legal Disenfranchisement of
Minority Voters, 48 Case W. Res. L. Rev. 727, 738 (1998)
(describing how, during Reconstruction, in an effort to prevent
African-Americans from voting, several states enacted felon
disenfranchisement laws and "carefully selected disenfranchising
crimes in order to disqualify a disproportionate number of black
voters" and noting that "many of today's laws disenfranchising
felons can trace their roots to attempts by Reconstruction
constitutional conventions to enact laws that would keep black
voters out of the electoral process").
-59-
The majority makes much of the fact that felon
disenfranchisement was not specifically mentioned in the legislative
history, but "it would be a strange canon of statutory construction
that would require Congress to state in committee reports or
elsewhere in its deliberations that which is obvious on the face of
a statute." Harrison v. PPG Industries, Inc., 446 U.S. 578, 592
(1980). It is also illogical to interpret silence as intent to
exclude, given that the very purpose of § 2's broad language was to
avoid reciting the various maneuvers that states may devise in the
course of their "unremitting and ingenious defiance." Katzenbach,
383 U.S. at 309. Rather, the VRA subjects all voting qualifications
to scrutiny. In any event, if I were to read anything into that
silence, I would reach the opposite conclusion. This is because
felon disenfranchisement laws, which were undoubtedly among the
mechanisms being employed by states throughout the post-
reconstruction era to deprive minorities of the vote,34 were
inevitably within Congress's contemplation when drafting the VRA.
Had Congress had intended to exclude this particular type of
qualification from the reach of the statute, it could have done so
explicitly. But Congress made no provisos to carve felon
disenfranchisement laws out from the purposely "all inclusive"
language of § 2(a). See Allen, 393 U.S. at 566. In this historical
34
See, e.g., Shapiro, supra, at 543; Brooks, supra, at 858;
Hench, supra, at 738.
-60-
context, congressional silence suggests, if anything, that no such
exclusion was intended.
Moreover, through the 1982 amendments to the VRA,
Congress expanded the remedial power of the Act even further by
relieving plaintiffs of the burden of proving discriminatory intent.
Overturning a Supreme Court case that held that the original Act
contained such a requirement, see Mobile v. Bolden, 446 U.S. 55, 61
(1980), Congress, through the 1982 amendments, made clear that a
violation of § 2 could be established by proof of discriminatory
results. See Thornburg, 478 U.S. at 43-44 (emphasis added) (reading
the 1982 Amendment to the VRA as effectively overturning the Bolden
requirement of showing purposeful discrimination); S. Rep. No.
97-417, at 27-28, 36-37 (1982), as reprinted in 1982 U.S.C.C.A.N.
177, 204-06, 214-15 (noting that the purpose of the Amendments was
to repeal Bolden and to focus the judicial inquiry only into whether
there exists equal access to electoral opportunity). Congress did
so because it recognized the difficulty of proving deliberate and
purposeful discrimination, and sought to ensure that "in the context
of all the circumstances in the jurisdiction in question," any
disparate racial impact of facially neutral voting requirements did
not result from racial discrimination. S. Rep. No. 97-417 at 27.
This "results test" was intended "to serve as a prophylactic against
voting practices -- such as felon disenfranchisement . . . adopted
or retained due to intentional discrimination that would be
-61-
difficult to prove in court." Daniel P. Tokaji, The New Vote
Denial: Where Election Reform Meets the Voting Rights Act, 57 S.C.
L. Rev. 689, 722 (2006). And its Report accompanying the enactment
of the 1982 amendments, the Senate endorsed statements made by the
Attorney General during the original VRA hearings that the purpose
of "Section 2 w[as] [to] ban 'any kind of practice . . . if its
purpose or effect was to deny or abridge the right to vote on
account of race or color." S. Rep. No. 97-417, at 17 (emphasis
added). Given this history, it would be wholly incongruous with
Congress's broad ameliorative intent to conclude, as does the
majority, that where the particular voter qualification that results
in racial discrimination happens to be a felon disenfranchisement
law, in this eventuality only, does the VRA provide no relief and
permit the discriminatory qualification to persist.
To reach this unlikely result, the majority relies on
assorted evidence of the widespread use and general sanction of
felon disenfranchisement laws in various contexts. But all that any
of this evidence actually shows is that felon disenfranchisement is
not presumptively invalid, a proposition as to which, after
Richardson, 418 U.S. at 56, there is no doubt. None of the
majority's arguments support its conclusion that Congress intended
to insulate such laws from scrutiny under § 2 of the VRA where they
are alleged to effect a discriminatory result. Specifically, the
evidence relied on by the majority includes (1) § 2 of the
-62-
Fourteenth Amendment, (2) the legislative history of VRA § 4, and
(3) Congressional endorsement of felon disenfranchisement generally.
I will address each of these sources in turn.
A. Section 2 of the Fourteenth Amendment
The majority suggests that felon disenfranchisement
somehow differs from other voting qualifications because the "power
of the states to disqualify from voting those convicted of crimes
is explicitly set forth in § 2 of the Fourteenth Amendment." But,
looking at the text of that provision in context, it is by no means
a grant of power to states to disenfranchise felons. See U.S.
Const. amend. XIV, § 2. Rather, that provision simply states that
disenfranchised felons, unlike other persons disenfranchised by the
States, are to be included within the census for purposes of
apportioning representatives.35
35
In relevant part, that provision states as follows:
Representatives shall be apportioned among the
several States according to their respective
numbers, . . . . But when the right to vote
. . . is denied to any of the male inhabitants
of such State, being twenty-one years of age,
and citizens of the United States, or in any
way abridged, except for participation in
rebellion, or other crime, the basis of
representation therein shall be reduced in the
proportion which the number of such male
citizens shall bear to the whole number of
male citizens twenty-one years of age in such
State.
U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 2.
-63-
The most that can be gleaned from this language is that
by addressing the eventuality of "abridg[ment] . . . for
participation in . . . crime," Congress contemplated that at least
in some circumstances, felon disenfranchisement could exist. Thus,
it merely implies that there is no per se ban on such laws. But VRA
§ 2 is targeted at precisely those voting qualifications that are
not the subject of a per se ban. See S. Rep. No. 97-417, at 16
(explaining that under § 2 as amended in 1982, "electoral devices
. . . per se would not be subject to attack under section 2. They
would only be vulnerable, if, in the totality of circumstances, they
resulted in the denial of equal access to the electoral process").
As plaintiffs do not allege that felon disenfranchisement laws are
unlawful per se, but only as applied in Massachusetts, where they
"result in a denial . . . of the right . . . to vote on account of
race," 42 U.S.C. § 1973, there is absolutely no conflict between §
2 of the Fourteenth Amendment and allowing plaintiffs to challenge
disenfranchisement laws under the VRA.
In other words, that § 2 of the Fourteenth Amendment
contemplates disenfranchisement as a potential qualification is
unremarkable. As similarly emphasized by the majority, "[t]he
criteria for eligibility to vote are defined by the states," and
states have the power to fix all kinds of qualifications for voting,
disqualifying felons included, but only where the exercise of that
power "do[es] not contravene any restriction that Congress, acting
-64-
pursuant to its constitutional powers, has imposed." Lassiter v.
Northampton County Bd. Of Elections, 360 U.S. 45, 50 (1959).36
However, "[w]hile a State may choose to disenfranchise some, all or
none of its felons based on legitimate concerns, it may not do so
based upon distinctions that have the effect, whether intentional
or not, of disenfranchising felons because of their race." Hayden,
449 F.3d at 346 (Parker, J., dissenting) (quoting Baker, 85 F.3d at
937); see also Farrakhan, 338 F.3d at 1016 (noting that although,
as a general matter, "states may deprive felons of the right to vote
without violating the Fourteenth Amendment, . . . when felon
disenfranchisement results in denial of the right to vote . . . on
account of race or color, Section 2 affords disenfranchised felons
the means to seek redress").
B. Legislative History of VRA § 4
To support its contention that Congress did not intend to
include felon disenfranchisement laws within the scope of VRA § 2,
the majority also relies on statements in the legislative history
36
In fact, the majority’s contrary interpretation of § 2 of
the Fourteenth Amendment, i.e. that felon disenfranchisement is
constitutionally protected and cannot be restricted, would result
in a direct conflict between constitutional directives in that it
is well-established that a felon disenfranchisement statute
intended to discriminate against minorities are prohibited under
§ 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment. See Hunter v. Underwood, 471 U.S.
222, 229 (1985) (holding Alabama's disenfranchisement for
commission of petty crime or misdemeanor provision
unconstitutional). The only reading of § 2 that respects the
validity of Hunter and similar precedent is one that permits states
to disenfranchise felons only where federal law does not otherwise
preclude them from doing so.
-65-
of § 4, claiming that § 4 "would not result in the proscription of
the frequent requirement of States . . . that an applicant for
voting . . . be free of conviction of a felony." S. Rep. No. 89-162
(1965), as reprinted in 1965 U.S.C.C.A.N. 2508, 2562. This argument
is deeply flawed. It is error to assume that a statement about one
section of a statute applies to all other sections thereof. See
Hayden, 449 F.3d at 352-53 (Parker, J., dissenting) (stating that
legislative history of one section of an expansive statute such as
VRA is "typically of no value" when attempting to understand
another, entirely different, section). In fact, the Supreme Court
has explicitly warned against doing so in the VRA context. Hall,
512 U.S. at 883 ("To be sure, if the structure and purpose of § 2
mirrored that of § 5, then the case for interpreting §§ 2 and 5 to
have the same application in all cases would be convincing. But the
two sections differ in structure, purpose, and application."). This
is especially true in the case before us given that the two
provisions, § 2 and § 4, "differ in structure, purpose, and
application." Id. Specifically, § 4 is a provision that
categorically bans, in covered jurisdictions, the use of certain
facially neutral tests or devices including literacy tests,
educational requirements, and "any requirement that a person as a
prerequisite for voting or registration for voting . . . possess
good moral character." See 42 U.S.C. § 1973b(a)(1)(A), § 1973b(c).
In contrast, § 2 applies to "a broader range of practices than those
-66-
'tests and devices' defined in Section 4." Johnson, 353 F.3d at
1306 n.27. While § 4 applies only to "covered jurisdictions," and
"imposes an outright ban on tests or devices," "§ 2(a), [applies
nationally, and] creates a 'results' test, which requires
investigating and weighing numerous factors." Hayden, 449 F.3d at
353 (Parker, J., dissenting) (internal citation omitted); see also
Nw. Austin, 557 U.S. at __, 2009 WL 1738645 at *4 (distinguishing
§ 2 of the VRA, which "operates nationwide . . . [to] forbid[] any
'standard practice or procedure' that 'results in a denial or the
abridgment of the right of any citizen . . . to vote on account of
race or color'" from § 4 and the remainder of the VRA which,
"[r]ather than continuing to depend on case-by-case litigation . . .
directly pre-empted the most powerful tools of black
disenfranchisement in the covered areas." (emphasis added & internal
citations omitted)).
Thus, considering congressional statements about § 4 in
the context of the provision at which they were addressed (§ 4),
they signify nothing about the scope of what § 2 was intended to
cover. Given § 4's absolute bar on "good moral character" tests,
and the natural susceptibility of "moral character" being read as
a proxy for criminal history, the statements upon which the majority
relies merely clarify that the categorical bar on "good moral
character" tests in § 4 should not be interpreted as also an
outright ban on felon disenfranchisement. See Hayden, 449 F.3d at
-67-
364-65 (Calabresi, J., dissenting) ("[S]uch legislative statements
simply make the uncontroversial point that felon disenfranchisement
laws are not 'good moral character' requirements within the meaning
of § 4(c)."). In contrast, "section 2 addresses voting regulations
that are not per se invalid under section 4 but nonetheless result
in a racially disparate impact on voting rights." Thomas G. Varnum,
Let's Not Jump to Conclusions: Approaching Felon Disenfranchisement
Challenges Under the Voting Rights Act, 14 Mich. J. Race & L. 109,
136 (2008). Statements regarding § 4 thus provide no indication
that Congress intended to insulate felon disenfranchisement laws
from scrutiny under § 2 where it is alleged that the operation of
a particular law results in the denial of the right to vote on
account of race. See Johnson, 405 F.3d at 1249 (Barkett, J.,
dissenting) (noting that decision not to add felon
disenfranchisement statutes to list of per se violations does not
show intent to exempt these laws from the VRA); Hayden, 449 F.3d at
365 (Calabresi, J., dissenting) ("The fact that race-neutral felon
disenfranchisement is permissible under § 4(c) tells us nothing at
all about whether § 2 allows racially discriminatory felon
disenfranchisement." (emphasis in original)).
In support of its argument for applying § 4's legislative
history to § 2, the majority suggests that, in light of § 4's
limited applicability to "covered jurisdictions" with a history of
discrimination, in contrast to § 2's nationwide reach, Congress
-68-
could not have "permitted" felon disenfranchisement laws in covered
jurisdictions, while "prohibiting" them in non-covered jurisdictions
like Massachusetts. But this argument similarly misses the mark,
precisely because it mischaracterizes the statute. To be sure, the
majority’s argument would be persuasive if § 2 categorically
"prohibit[ted]" felon disenfranchisement laws in Massachusetts and
other "non-covered" jurisdictions. But it does not. See S. Rep.
No. 97-417, at 16. Nor does the VRA "permit" felon
disenfranchisement laws, in "covered jurisdictions," or otherwise.
Rather, § 2 uniformly imposes a "totality of the circumstances" test
to all "voting qualifications," anywhere in the country, prohibiting
them only in the event that they result in racial discrimination.
There is nothing illogical about creating a per se ban on certain
presumptively discriminatory qualifications in "covered
jurisdictions" only, as was done in § 4, but also permitting
scrutiny of all voting qualifications nationally, including felon
disenfranchisement laws, to ensure that no particular qualification
is discriminatory as applied under the particular circumstances.
And that is precisely what Congress did through § 2.
By exporting the legislative history of § 4 into the § 2
context, the majority ignores the very plausible interpretation that
Congress intended § 2 to include felony disenfranchisement laws
precisely because it chose to exclude them from § 4's list of
categorically barred regulations. While Congress did not seek to
-69-
have felon disenfranchisement banned in all cases, it nevertheless
intended that they be subjected, just like every other voting
qualification anywhere in the country, to a "totality of the
circumstances" test to assess whether they effectuate a
discriminatory result. The fact that members of Congress were
sufficiently cognizant of felon disenfranchisement laws to carve
them out from the scope of § 4, yet made no such statements in
regard to § 2, despite the intentionally broad language of that
provision, indicates that Congress did not in fact intend a similar
restriction in the § 2 context. See Vidal-Reyes, 562 F.3d at 53
(quoting United States v. Councilman, 418 F.3d 67, 73 (1st Cir.
2005)) ("'[W]here Congress includes particular language in one
section of a statute but omits it in another section of the same
Act, it is generally presumed that Congress acts intentionally and
purposely in the disparate inclusion or exclusion.'").37 Thus, as
it stands, the legislative history of § 4 shows that while Congress
did not intend to enact a blanket ban on felon disenfranchisement
laws as a prohibited "moral character" requirement neither did it
intend to exclude discriminatory laws from the scope of VRA
scrutiny.
37
While this rule, known as the expressio unius est exclusio
alterius canon of construction, see Councilman, 418 F.3d at 73-74,
is useful for evaluating the import of omissions and inclusions in
statutory text, I believe its principle is equally persuasive with
respect to express omissions and inclusions in the legislative
history of a statute.
-70-
C. Historical Legitimacy and Congressional Endorsement
of Felon Disenfranchisement Law
The remainder of the arguments in the majority opinion
rely on Congress' sanctioning or presupposing the validity of felon
disenfranchisement in various contexts, such as where (1) it has
rejected proposals to outright bar felon disenfranchisement, either
through the VRA or otherwise, and (2) endorsed disenfranchisement
laws generally in the aftermath of the VRA. First of all,
"subsequent legislative history will rarely override a reasonable
interpretation of a statute that can be gleaned from its language
and legislative history prior to its enactment." Solid Waste Agency
of N. Cook County v. U.S. Army Corps of Eng'rs, 531 U.S. 159, 170
n.5 (2001) (quoting Consumer Prod. Safety Comm'n v. GTE Sylvania,
Inc., 447 U.S. 102, 118 n.13 (1980)). But more importantly, these
arguments are entirely irrelevant to the question before us.
Congressional refusal to pass categorical prohibitions on felon
disenfranchisement or even its subsequent affirmation of the
practice generally, is not inconsistent with Congress's clear intent
to subject to scrutiny, through § 2 of the VRA, "any state enactment
which altered the election law of a covered State in even a minor
way." Allen, 393 U.S. at 566-67 (emphasis added). Congress may
very well have decided not to bar felon disenfranchisement wholesale
(as it did by omitting it from § 4) and may even have endorsed the
practice where it was motivated by and served legitimate ends. But
it may have nevertheless chosen, in order to make the guarantees of
-71-
the Fifteenth Amendment meaningful, to restrict the adoption of this
"qualification" in those cases where it is applied "in a manner
which results" in the denial of the right to vote on account of
race. This reading of the legislative history, which is consistent
with the statutory text, is far more compelling than the majority's
analysis.
Ultimately, "the plainer the language, the more
convincing contrary legislative history must be to overcome the
natural purport of a statute's language." United States v. U.S.
Steel Corp., 482 F.2d 439, 444 (7th Cir.), cert. denied, 414 U.S.
909 (1973). I see a clear textual mandate, uncontradicted by any
legislative history, that felon disenfranchisement laws, like all
voting qualifications, may be challenged under § 2 of the VRA. "If
the language of law is to have any meaning at all, then surely it
must prevail over the kind of speculation that is entailed in such
an enterprise as th[is] court[] ha[s] undertaken." United States
ex rel. Siller v. Becton Dickinson & Co., 21 F.3d 1339, 1355 (4th
Cir. 1994).
The plain language of the statute being as clear as it
is, and the legislative history and purpose only bolstering that
clarity, I cannot help but speculate that the majority is jumping
through hoops to defeat the remedial purpose for which the provision
was enacted in order to produce a result consistent with its own
preference in policy. But "[t]he Fifteenth Amendment empowers
-72-
'Congress,' not the [c]ourt[s], to determine in the first instance
what legislation is needed to enforce it." Nw. Austin, 557 U.S. at
___, 2009 WL 1738645 at *9. And even if we "question the wisdom of
Congress's decision to enact a statute that permits challenging
felon disenfranchisement laws, we are judges, not policy-makers."
Hayden, 449 F.3d at 348 (Parker, J., dissenting). "The duty of a
judge is to follow the law, not to question its plain terms." Id.,
449 F.3d at 368 (Sotomayor, J., dissenting). "I do not believe that
Congress wishes us to disregard the plain language of any statute
or to invent exceptions to the statutes it has created." Id.
Finally, I see no constitutional issues posed by
interpreting the VRA according to its language and consistent with
its purpose, so as to encompass felon disenfranchisement laws.
Rather, § 2 of the VRA is firmly within the scope of Congress’s
power to enforce the Reconstruction amendments, which includes the
power to "enact so-called prophylactic legislation that proscribes
facially constitutional conduct, in order to prevent and deter
unconstitutional conduct." Nev. Dep't of Human Res. v. Hibbs, 538
U.S. 721, 727-28 (2003). Finding challenges to felon
disenfranchisement laws to be cognizable under the VRA, I have no
trouble concluding that the plaintiffs have stated a claim
sufficient to preclude dismissal at this early juncture. Thus, I
would affirm the district court's decision on this issue.
-73-
II. Ex Post Facto Clause Claim
The second issue raised on appeal, a question of first
impression in this circuit, is whether the retroactive application
of a felon disenfranchisement provision violates the Ex Post Facto
Clause when it is applied to felons incarcerated for crimes
committed prior to the provision's passage into law. The Ex Post
Facto Clause "bars application of a law 'that changes the
punishment, and inflicts a greater punishment, than the law annexed
to the crime, when committed[.]'" Johnson v. United States, 529
U.S. 694, 699 (2000) (quoting Calder v. Bull, 3 U.S. 386, 390
(1798)); see U.S. Const. art. 1, § 10 ("No State shall . . . pass
any . . . ex post facto Law."). Plaintiffs, incarcerated in
Massachusetts for offenses committed prior to Article 120's
enactment, contend that Article 120 is unconstitutional as applied
to them because it subjects them to additional punishment not
provided for by the laws of the Commonwealth when they committed the
acts underlying their convictions. The majority affirms the
dismissal of plaintiffs' claim on grounds that the deprivation of
the right to vote, as accomplished by Article 120, does not
constitute "punishment," and thus, falls outside the protections of
the Ex Post Facto Clause. I cannot agree. While disenfranchising
convicted felons prospectively might be perfectly constitutional,
I would hold that the disenfranchisement provision here is a
punitive measure, which cannot be retroactively applied.
-74-
"The deprivation of any rights, civil or political,
previously enjoyed, may be punishment, the circumstances attending
and the causes of the deprivation determining this fact." Cummings
v. Missouri, 71 U.S. 277, 320 (1866). As the majority accurately
explains, analysis of whether a particular enactment imposes
retroactive punishment so as to implicate the Ex Post Facto Clause
requires a two-part inquiry. The first part asks whether the
challenged law has a civil, regulatory purpose, or whether it is
intended to punish. See Smith v. Doe, 538 U.S. 84, 92 (2002)
(citing Kansas v. Hendricks, 521 U.S. 346, 361 (1997)). If a court
finds that the law was intended to be punitive, then it constitutes
"punishment" for purposes of the Ex Post Facto Clause and would
violate the clause if retroactively applied. Id. However, if the
law conveys a non-punitive, regulatory purpose, the court moves to
the second part of the test to ascertain whether the law is "so
punitive either in purpose or effect as to negate [the state's]
intention to deem it civil." Id. (quoting United States v. Ward,
448 U.S. 242, 248-49 (1980)). The ultimate question is "whether
[Article 120] is intended to be, or by its nature necessarily is,
criminal and punitive, or civil and remedial." United States v. One
Assortment of 89 Firearms, 465 U.S. 354, 362 (1984).
While legislative purpose is not easily discernible given
the unique procedural history of Article 120's enactment by popular
referendum, I nevertheless find that a close look at the provision's
-75-
language and history reveals that it was intended by its proponents
to be a primarily punitive measure. Moreover, even if the primary
intent behind the enactment of Article 120 could not be clearly
identified,38 I would find this disenfranchisement law to be so
punitive in effect that it nevertheless constitutes a criminal
punishment under the second prong of Smith.
A. The Legislative Intent Was Punitive
We first ask whether Article 120 was intended to be a
civil or criminal measure. See Smith, 538 U.S. at 92. Determining
whether Article 120 was intended to be civil or criminal "'is first
of all a question of statutory construction.'" Id. (quoting
Hendricks, 521 U.S. at 361). As this court has made clear, analysis
of statutory construction "begin[s] with the language of the
statute." Phillips v. Pembroke Real Estate, Inc., 459 F.3d 128, 139
(1st Cir. 2006) (quoting Barnhart v. Sigmon Coal Co., 534 U.S. 438,
450 (2002)). Yet, in holding that Article 120 conveys a regulatory
intent, the majority again departs from this well-established
framework.
The majority disposes of the first prong of Smith by
citing Trop v. Dulles for the proposition that "felon
38
See Gabriel J. Chin, Are Collateral Sanctions Premised on
Conduct or Conviction?, 30 Fordham Urb. L.J. 1685, 1686 (2003)
(opining that "it is not always clear that the primary legislative
motivation for a collateral sanction is civil rather than punitive,
nor is it always a simple matter to discern the primary
motivation").
-76-
disenfranchisement provisions are considered regulatory rather then
punitive." See 356 U.S. 86, 94 (1958). But leaving aside the
merits of this proposition for the moment, the fact that
disenfranchisement provisions are generally considered regulatory
rather than punitive is not dispositive of what the Massachusetts
voters and legislators intended here. Rather, the relevant
questions are what Article 120's particular language says and if
there are any inferences that can be drawn from its broader
structure. See Smith, 538 U.S. at 92 (instructing that we should
first "consider the statute's text and its structure to determine
the legislative objective"). "[C]onsiderable deference must be
accorded to the intent as the legislature has stated it." Id.
In this case, looking at the text of Article 120, there
is no indication on the face of the provision of the legislative
intent behind its enactment. Article 120, which was passed pursuant
to a ballot question placed before Commonwealth voters, lacks any
kind of express "statement of purpose" which legislation often
includes, and none of its language reveals a particular government
interest in felon disenfranchisement, either regulatory or
punitive.39 Instead, Article 120 merely lays out the substantive
39
For an example of the kind of clear language "express[ing]
the objective of [a] law in the statutory text itself," see Smith,
538 U.S. at 93 (citing the Alaska Legislature's public safety
interest in "protecting the public from sex offenders" as the basis
for its sex offender registration provision).
-77-
voting requirements, including the newly enacted exclusion of
incarcerated felons.
Beyond the language of the provision, it is possible that
the "broader structure" of the provision may provide some indication
of its purpose. Id. The majority relies on the placement of
Article 120 within the Commonwealth's civil voter qualification
provisions, rather than in its criminal code, to infer a regulatory
purpose. But while manner of codification is certainly one factor
relevant to ascertaining the nature of a provision, the Supreme
Court has held that the "location and labels of a statutory
provision do not by themselves transform a civil remedy into a
criminal one," or vice versa. Smith, 538 U.S. at 94; see also Trop,
356 U.S. at 94 ("How simple would be the tasks of constitutional
adjudication and of law generally if specific problems could be
solved by inspection of the labels pasted on them! Manifestly the
issue of whether [a statute] is a penal law cannot be thus
determined."). Rather, the Supreme Court instructs that "a penalty
[] cannot be converted into [a non-penal measure] by so naming it,"
and we must "ascribe to [the particular statute] the character
disclosed by its purpose and operation, regardless of name." United
States v. Constantine, 296 U.S. 287, 294 (1935) (holding that even
though labeled a "tax" on conducting retail liquor business,
challenged statute was nevertheless a "penalty" designed to punish
the violation of state liquor laws). Likewise, "even a clear
-78-
legislative classification of a statute as 'non-penal' would not
alter the fundamental nature of a plainly penal statute." Trop, 356
U.S. at 95 (holding that a statute stripping army deserters of
citizenship is a "penal law" despite its codification amidst the
regulatory provisions of the "Nationality Act"); see also One
Assortment of 89 Firearms, 465 U.S. at 364-65 (holding a forfeiture
provision to be a civil action despite its codification in the
state's criminal code). It follows that the Commonwealth's
authority to regulate voting requirements as part of its civil power
does not, in and of itself, establish that Article 120 was intended
as a regulatory measure.
Moreover, any inference of legislative intent that could
be drawn from the codification of Article 120 in a civil section of
Massachusetts' constitution is undermined by the fact that the
Commonwealth was required to amend that constitutional provision,
which governs voting qualifications generally, in order to
disenfranchise felons. In addition, the subject matter of Article
120 is consistent not only with civil voting requirements, but also
with criminal rules imposing an additional deprivation upon persons
convicted of particular crimes and in the custody of the criminal
justice system. In that sense, Article 120's broader structure
implies both criminal punishment and civil regulation. In sum,
neither the language nor the structure of Article 120 betrays a
clear regulatory or punitive intent.
-79-
Without a clear indication of intended purpose from
Article 120 itself, we look to legislative history for evidence of
legislative intent.40 Rolland v. Romney, 318 F.3d 42, 48 (1st Cir.
2003). Here, there are two helpful sources of legislative history
-- public statements made by Massachusetts' politicians about a
series of disenfranchisement proposals that ultimately resulted in
Article 120,41 and the "Information for Voters" Guide ("the Guide")
that was distributed to voters at the law's ratification stage.
First, the public statements of proponents of the
legislation are quite revealing of the punitive motivation behind
Article 120. Writing to the Massachusetts Legislature to propose
an earlier version of the instant disenfranchisement law, Governor
Cellucci argued that "the time has come to tell would-be criminals
in Massachusetts that committing crimes has serious consequences."42
40
It is surprising that, given its extensive reliance on
statements in the legislative history to analyze the clear
statutory language of the VRA, the majority only mentions
legislative history briefly in its Ex Post Facto Clause analysis,
even though the language and structure of Article 120 is actually
ambiguous as to whether Article 120 was intended to be punitive or
regulatory. While the majority states that it will consider
certain comments made by Governor Cellucci, it never analyzes these
or other comments by Article 120's proponents relevant to the
legislative history of the provision.
41
The legislative process resulting in the passage of Article
120 is worth noting. A constitutional amendment initiated by a
legislator must be approved by two successive joint sessions of the
Massachusetts legislature and then ratified by Massachusetts
voters. Commonwealth Mass. Const. Art. 49, Init., pt. IV, §§ 2-5.
42
I agree with the majority that, even though earlier
proposals for felon disenfranchisement laws did not pass, their
legislative histories are relevant here. These earlier proposals
-80-
He advocated for the proposal because it would "ensure that
criminals pay their debt to society before they regain their right
to participate in the political process." Governor Cellucci also
argued in favor of disenfranchising incarcerated felons because
"prisons are a place for punishment." Striking a similar tone,
State Representative Paul Frost argued that prisoners "don't deserve
to vote" and that "this is an issue about justice." Senator Guy
Glodis advocated for the law by stating that "philosophically, no
inmates deserve the right to vote." These comments, reflecting
classic punitive rationales, see, infra, section II.B.4 (discussing
traditional theories of criminal punishment), provide strong
evidence that Article 120 was motivated by an intent to punish
felons.
As the majority recognizes, the Guide for voters
regarding the ballot question that culminated in the enactment of
Article 120, is also relevant to deciphering legislative intent.
The Guide stated that the proposal would change the law that "allows
criminals to continue to exercise control over our lives by voting
from prison." The majority found such language to indicate
regulatory intent. I disagree. While this language is more
ambiguous as to intent than anything else, it suggests to me another
are nearly identical to Article 120, so the motivation for them is
relevant evidence for the motivation behind Article 120. See
Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. 144, 180 (1963) (using the
legislative history of earlier legislation when assessing the
motivation of a law "quite obviously patterned on that of its
predecessor").
-81-
retributive statement about what felons "deserve," i.e. to have
their right to participate in government revoked. See id. The
Guide also stated that "[a] yes vote will protect democracy's
greatest gift - the right to vote, by reserving it for the law-
abiding." I believe this language is further evidence of the
punitive principle of "just desert." In any event, the ambiguous
indications of intent revealed by the Guide do not outweigh the
plainly punitive comments by the measure's proponents.
Confronted with potentially mixed manifestations of
legislative purpose -- and I believe such a characterization is
generous to the Commonwealth's position -- this court should
decipher the law's "primary function." See Mendoza-Martinez, 372
U.S. at 169 (emphasis added). Whereas Article 120 itself is unclear
as to intent, the Guide is also, at best, ambiguous, and the
statements made by Massachusetts politicians are strongly indicative
of punitive intent, I find that plaintiffs have made a compelling
argument that the weight of the evidence of intent reveals Article
120 to have been intended primarily as a punitive measure. This
punitive measure having been applied to plaintiffs retroactively,
I believe that an Ex Post Facto violation could be found without
further inquiry. But in an abundance of caution, I will proceed.
B. The Effect of Article 120 Is Punitive
Under the second prong of the Smith analysis, even if a
clear punitive intent is not discernable for the challenged law, it
-82-
would nevertheless constitute a criminal punishment subject to the
Ex Post Facto Clause if the measure's effect is so punitive as to
negate any intent to deem it civil. Hendricks, 521 U.S. at 361
(citing Ward, 448 U.S. at 248-49). The majority correctly explains
that, in order to gauge the actual effect of the law, this court
reviews the seven factors described in Mendoza-Martinez:
[(1)] Whether the sanction involves an
affirmative disability or restraint, [(2)]
whether it has historically been regarded as
a punishment, [(3)] whether it comes into play
only on a finding of scienter, [(4)] whether
its operation will promote the traditional
aims of punishment-retribution and deterrence,
[(5)] whether the behavior to which it applies
is already a crime, [(6)] whether an
alternative purpose to which it may rationally
be connected is assignable for it, and [(7)]
whether it appears excessive in relation to
the alternative purpose assigned.
See Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 168-69 (footnotes omitted). These
factors, which are "neither exhaustive nor dispositive," serve as
"useful guideposts." Smith, 538 U.S. at 97 (citations omitted).
I agree with the majority that, where the legislature has
clearly stated a civil regulatory intent in enacting the challenged
sanction, "'only the clearest proof' will suffice to override
legislative intent and transform what has been denominated a civil
remedy into a criminal penalty." Hudson v. United States, 52 U.S.
93, 100 (1997) (quoting Ward, 448 U.S. at 249). However, I disagree
that plaintiffs should be held to that burden, in this case, where
the legislative intent is ambiguous at best. The Supreme Court has
-83-
not resolved this particular question directly. However, where the
legislature fails to make its intent clear through express language,
or by implication through a law's broader structure, or even through
legislative history, there is strong support for the proposition
that a challenged law should be subjected to neutral evaluation when
determining its effect. See Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 169
(holding that, "[a]bsent conclusive evidence of congressional intent
as to the penal nature of a statute, these factors must be
considered in relation to the statute on its face"); Smith, 538 U.S.
at 107 (Souter, J., concurring) (distinguishing between cases where
the legislative intent is clear and those where it is ambiguous, and
rejecting the "clearest proof" burden where it is ambiguous).
Accordingly, I would approach the application of the Mendoza-
Martinez factors, without any starting presumption, to determine
whether the actual purpose or effect of Article 120 is punitive.
See Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 168-69. Applying the most
relevant of these factors to the inquiry before us, I find that each
of them weighs in favor of recognizing Article 120 to be a penal
measure subject to the Ex Post Facto Clause.
1. Scienter & Criminality
The third and fifth Mendoza-Martinez factors, "whether
the challenged sanction comes into place only on a finding of
scienter," and relatedly, "whether the behavior to which it applies
is already a crime," weigh heavily in favor of concluding that
-84-
Article 120 is a penal statute. See id. at 168. First of all, "the
disciplinary sanction here [is] triggered by a criminal conviction
which incorporate[s] a finding of criminal intent, and so the
disciplinary sanction came into play 'only on a finding of
scienter,'" Porter v. Coughlin, 421 F.3d 141, 147 (2d Cir. 2005)
(quoting Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 168). Similarly, as Article
120 applies only to persons who have already been convicted of a
felony, "the behavior to which it applies is [undoubtedly] already
a crime," as the fifth Mendoza-Martinez factor requires. Mendoza-
Martinez, 372 U.S. at 168; see also Dep't of Revenue of Montana v.
Kurth Ranch, 511 U.S. 767, 781 (1994) (noting that fact that a tax
on marijuana was "conditioned on the commission of a crime" is
"'significant of [its] penal and prohibitory intent'").
2. History
The second Mendoza-Martinez factor asks whether a
particular sanction has "historically been regarded as punishment."
Id. at 168. There is substantial evidence to this effect. First
of all, federal courts have frequently characterized felon
disenfranchisement as a punitive measure. In its decision in
Johnson, the Eleventh Circuit described felon disenfranchisement
laws as a "punitive device stemming from criminal law" and explained
that "throughout history, criminal disenfranchisement provisions
have existed as a punitive device." See 405 F.3d at 1228 & n.5.
Similarly, the Second Circuit has noted the "nearly universal use
-85-
of felon disenfranchisement as a punitive device." Muntaqim v.
Coombe, 366 F.3d 102, 123 (2d Cir. 2004) (vacated en banc on other
grounds). "Congress [has also] recognized the punitive nature of
felon disenfranchisement laws." See Pamela A. Wilkins, The Mark of
Cain: Disenfranchised Felons and the Constitutional No Man's Land,
56 Syracuse L. Rev. 85, 133-34 (2005) (describing how Congressional
acts readmitting former Confederate States to the Union did so on
the condition that States prohibited disenfranchisement "except as
a punishment for . . . crimes"). This point is reinforced by
renowned historian, Alexander Keyssar's review of voting rights in
this country in which he unequivocally characterizes America's felon
disenfranchisement laws as an intentionally punitive device. Id.
(citing Alexander Keyssar, The Right to Vote: The Contested History
of Democracy in the United States 316 (2000)). And the ALI's Model
Penal Code, a compilation examining the penal law of the United
States, labels prisoner disenfranchisement "an integral part of the
criminal law." Model Penal Code § 306.3 (Proposed Official Draft
1962). This is strong evidence that, regardless of how a particular
disenfranchisement provision is codified, the purpose of
disenfranchising felons in American history has been to punish them
for their crimes.
There is also substantial evidence, presented by
plaintiffs, of the historical use of felon disenfranchisement as a
penal mechanism throughout the world. See Hayden, 449 F.3d at 315-
-86-
16 (describing use of "civil death" laws in Medieval continental
Europe, "attainder" laws in medieval England, and "infamy" laws in
ancient Greece and Rome, all of which revoked political rights,
including the right to vote, "as additional punishment for [certain]
crimes"); Keyssar, supra, at 62-63 ("Disenfranchisement for
[infamous] crimes had a long history in English, European, and even
Roman law, and it [is] hardly surprising that the principle of
attaching civil disabilities to the commission of crimes appeared
in American law as well."). Although the district court dismissed
this evidence as not relevant to disenfranchisement provisions in
American history, that approach misreads this factor as used in
Mendoza-Martinez. In fact, in Mendoza-Martinez itself, the Supreme
Court explicitly relied on the history of citizenship deprivation
in other countries in determining that the challenged law depriving
draft evaders of citizenship was punitive in effect. See 372 U.S.
at 168 n.23 (discussing Roman and English societies' use of
forfeiting citizenship as a punishment). Thus, evidence of the
historical use of felony disenfranchisement laws both in this
country and others is relevant, and both reveal the prevalent
historic use of such laws as a penal mechanism.
To refute the extensive evidence that disenfranchisement laws
have been historically regarded as punitive, the majority cites one
court decision that did not concern the disenfranchisement of
felons, Trop. See 365 U.S. at 96-97. Trop does contain dicta
-87-
suggesting hypothetically that "the purpose of [a felon
disenfranchisement statute] is to designate a reasonable ground of
eligibility for voting," id., but as dicta, that language is not
binding upon us. See Wilkins, supra, at 102 (arguing that "Trop's
discussion of disenfranchisement statutes was dicta and, therefore,
does not excuse judges from the hard work necessary to analyze real
disenfranchisement laws"). Trop also explains alternatively, that
if "[disenfranchisement] were imposed for the purpose of punishing
[an offender], the statute[] would be penal." 365 U.S. at 96-97.
Moreover, that decision says nothing about how such laws have
historically been regarded. In any event, the problem with relying
on Trop's suggestion that felon disenfranchisement could be a
"reasonable ground of eligibility for voting," is that Trop fails
to reveal what legitimate purpose disenfranchisement serves that
would render it a "reasonable ground." This failure to identify why
disqualifying felons is a "reasonable ground" is particularly
problematic in light of the fact that both cases cited by Trop for
this proposition, Davis v. Beason and Murphy v. Ramsey, involve
voting qualifications that are no longer regarded as valid.43 As
43
See Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 634 (1996) (holding that
the decision of the Court in Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 333 (1890),
which upheld the disenfranchisement of polygamists on grounds that
they advocate "practical resistance to the laws of the Territory"
and "approve the commission of crimes forbidden by it" is "no
longer good law" because "persons advocating a certain practice may
[not] be denied the right to vote"). Murphy v. Ramsey, 114 U.S. 15
(1885), involved a suit similar to Davis in which the Supreme Court
upheld a voting qualification disqualifying any "polygamist,
bigamist, or any person cohabiting with more than one woman . . ."
-88-
several scholars argue, Trop was decided at a time when the
government had virtually unrestricted power to regulate the
franchise, prior to the Warren's court's curtailment of that power
when it recognized the fundamental nature of voting rights. See
Wilkins, supra, at 102-04; Pamela S. Karlan, Convictions and Doubts:
Retribution, Representation, and the Debate Over Felon
Disenfranchisement, 56 Stan. L. Rev. 1147, 1150-54 (2004). As such,
scholars argue that the dicta in Trop regarding the regulatory
nature of felon disenfranchisement laws was premised on an "outdated
conception of voting rights," rendering its continued validity
questionable. Wilkins, supra, at 102-04.
Thus, seeing sparse evidence to the contrary, I am
persuaded that the evidence cited by plaintiffs of the historical
use of disenfranchisement weighs in favor of deeming the practice
to be a punitive device.
3. Affirmative Disability or Restraint
In light of this country's struggle for independence in
pursuit of participatory democracy and the centrality attributed to
from voting in Utah. Id. at 38, 42-43. Though Murphy was not
expressly overruled by name, as was Davis in Romer, it is evident,
given the similarity between the Davis and Murphy challenges, that
neither decision continues to represent valid law. The rejection
of this line of cases suggests that keeping "undesirable" persons,
including felons, from voting is no longer a valid regulatory
purpose.
-89-
the right to vote in our legal and political culture,44 I am
compelled to conclude that the deprivation of the franchise is an
"affirmative disability or restraint" of the gravest sort.
Yet the majority concludes otherwise. In support of its
holding that felon disenfranchisement does not constitute criminal
punishment, the majority concludes that Article 120 does not impose
"any affirmative disability or restraint, physical or otherwise."
To the extent the majority suggests that a restraint need be
"physical" in order to resemble a punitive sanction, such a
requirement simply does not exist. Rather, Smith discusses physical
restraints as only one kind of possible restraint a criminal law
might impose. Smith, 538 U.S. at 100. In fact, our society
regularly punishes wrongdoers without actually imposing physical
restraints on them, most commonly, with criminal fines. And Supreme
Court decisions tasked with applying the Mendoza-Martinez factors
to ascertain the penal or regulatory nature of a particular sanction
have regularly found non-physical sanctions to be affirmative
disabilities or restraints. See, e.g., Kurth Ranch, 511 U.S. at 774
(holding a tax on illegal drugs to be a punitive measure in part
because it "allowed for sanctions by restraint of Debtors'
property"). In fact, Mendoza-Martinez itself held a non-physical
44
See Werme v. Merrill, 84 F.3d 479, 482 (1st Cir. 1996) ("It
is apodictic that the right to vote is a right that helps to
preserve all other rights.").
-90-
sanction, the deprivation of citizenship, to constitute a sanction
"essentially penal in character."
The majority also argues that disenfranchisement during
incarceration is not an affirmative disability because it is "not
as enduring as permanent occupational debarment." See Hawker v. New
York, 170 U.S. 189 (1898) (holding that revocation of medical
license does not violate the Ex Post Facto clause). But revoking
a license to practice a particular profession is also not the
deprivation of a fundamental right. In holding the revocation of
citizenship rights to be punitive in Mendoza-Martinez, the Supreme
Court emphasized that it is the "utmost import" and "value" of
citizenship rights that renders their deprivation among the gravest
of sanctions. Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 160. Like citizenship
itself, the right to vote, a fundamental component of citizenship,
is certainly comparable in its utmost value and importance.
Tashjian v. Republican Party, 479 U.S. 208, 217 (1986) (noting that
the right to vote is a fundamental right inherent in citizenship).
It is the importance of the right to vote that renders the gravity
of its deprivation so devastating a "disability." See Reynolds v.
Sims, 377 U.S. 533, 555 (1964) ("The right to vote freely for the
candidate of one's choice is of the essence of a democratic society,
and any restrictions on that right strikes at the heart of
representative government."); Igartúa-De La Rosa v. United States,
417 F.3d 145, 177 (1st Cir. 2005) (Torruella, J., dissenting)
-91-
("There are few countries in the world in which the right to vote
is as exalted as it is in the United States."); McLaughlin v. City
of Canton, 947 F. Supp. 954, 971 (S. D. Miss. 1995) (describing
disenfranchisement as the harshest sanction imposed by a democratic
society and noting that when one is "brought beneath its axe, the
disenfranchised is severed from the body politic and condemned to
the lowest form of citizenship, where voiceless at the ballot box
the disenfranchised, the disinherited must sit idly by while others
elect his civic leaders and while others choose the fiscal and
governmental policies that will govern him and his family").
Disenfranchisement, though neither physical nor permanent, deprives
U.S. citizens of a fundamental right, and as such, is undoubtedly
an affirmative disability.
4. Traditional Aims of Punishment
The fourth Mendoza-Martinez factor provides that a
sanction is more likely punitive if "its operation will promote the
traditional aims of punishment - retribution and deterrence."
Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 168; see also Bell v. Wolfish, 441
U.S. 520, 539 (1979) (noting that the Supreme Court has established
that "[r]etribution and deterrence are not legitimate nonpunitive
governmental objectives" (emphasis added)).45 Of course, the threat
45
See also Wilkins, supra, at 133 & n.316 (noting that in his
history of American suffrage, Alexander Keyssar characterized felon
disenfranchisement laws as intentionally punitive, noting that
"disenfranchisement, whether permanent or for an extended period,
serves as retribution for committing a crime and as a deterrent to
-92-
of being deprived of a fundamental right will, to a certain extent,
always operate to deter a rational person from engaging in unlawful
conduct.46 But as the Supreme Court has recognized, the deterrent
effect of a sanction cannot be wholly dispositive of criminal
punishment as all civil penalties have some deterrent effect. See
Kurth Ranch, 511 U.S. at 777. It is, however, in its retributive
nature that felon disenfranchisement truly reveals its punitive
colors. See Karlan, supra, at 1166 (arguing that
"disenfranchisement really can be justified only under a retributive
theory of criminal punishment"). In this sense, this factor also
conclusively weighs in favor of the plaintiffs.
As a form of retribution, "'[p]unishment is the way in
which society expresses its denunciation of wrongdoing.'" Gregg v.
Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 184 n.30. The notion is that the offender
"owes a debt to society" and "must now atone for his sins by
suffering punishment for his transgression." Peter W. Low et. al.,
future criminal behavior").
46
That some of Article 120's proponents considered this
possibility is evident from statements such as that of Governor
Celucci in his letter in support of the disenfranchisement
amendment:
The time has come to tell would be criminals
in Massachusetts that committing crimes has
serious consequences, not only in terms of
prison time, but also in terms of the right to
participate in deciding how society should be
run.
(Emphasis added). This language suggests that the proposal was
intended to deter "would be" criminals from committing crimes.
-93-
Criminal Law 2 (1982). "This . . . conception of punishment . . .
makes primary the meting out to a responsible wrongdoer of his just
deserts." H.L.A. Hart, Punishment and Responsibility, 158-59
(1968). Other scholars have characterized the retributive aim of
criminal punishment as predicated upon the notion of restoring the
status quo after an offender, by his contravention of the law, has
usurped from his victim or from society generally, something to
which he is not fairly entitled. See, e.g., Herbert Morris, Guilt
and Innocence, 33-36 (1976) (characterizing punishment as restoring
the fair distribution of benefits and burdens that is displaced when
a person violates the rules that others have assumed, thereby
gaining an unfair advantage); Jean Hampton, Retributivism and Its
Critics (1992) (characterizing retributive punishment as a message
that restores the prior status hierarchy between victim and offender
which was violated by an offender's degradation of a victim's worth
through criminality).
In the context of the retributive purposes of criminal
punishment, it becomes apparent how fundamentally intertwined
criminal disenfranchisement laws generally, and Article 120 in
particular, are with this punitive objective. The statement from
Governor Cellucci's letter, referenced supra, that the
disenfranchisement proposal would "ensure that criminals pay their
debt to society" is the textbook articulation of the retributive
theory. Similarly, Representative Frost's statement that felons do
-94-
not "deserve to vote" is fundamentally linked to the retributive
notion of "just deserts." And Representative Marini's promise that
the law would apply to those who did "despicable things" is
consistent with theory of retributive punishment as a means by which
society expresses its moral denunciation of unlawful conduct.
Moreover, even the statements contained in the
Information for Voters guide, cited by the Commonwealth as
evidencing a regulatory non-punitive purpose, in fact, reveal the
opposite when considered in the context of criminal punishment
theory. For example, the statement that Article 120 would change
the law that "allows criminals to continue to exercise control over
our lives by voting from prison," is consistent with Morris' and
Hampton's notions of retributive punishment as a means of restoring
the proper hierarchy between the offender and society, unfairly
tipped in the offender's favor by his desecration of society's
rules. By preventing offenders from benefitting further, at
society's expense, through their political participation,
disenfranchisement helps to restore that lost equilibrium. Finally,
felon disenfranchisement laws, by "deny[ing] the civic and human
dignity of persons who have been convicted of doing wrong," are
emblematic of the denunciatory function of criminal law. See Bell,
441 U.S. at 592-93 n.26 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (citing letter
from Learned Hand to the University of Chicago Law Review).
-95-
5. Connection to Non-Punitive Purpose
The sixth Mendoza-Martinez factor asks "whether an
alternative purpose to which [the challenged sanction] may
rationally be connected is assignable for it." 372 U.S. at 168-69.
I note, as a threshold matter and as discussed above,
that there was no legitimate non-punitive purpose expressly assigned
to Article 120, and that the purpose of the statute as revealed by
its legislative history is primarily punitive. But even if we were
to speculate as to non-punitive rationales potentially assignable
to the provision, I simply cannot agree with the majority that there
is an "obvious rational non-punitive purpose for
disenfranchisement." The reality is that "[c]ourts have been hard
pressed to define the state interest served by laws disenfranchising
persons convicted of crimes." Dillenburg v. Kramer, 469 F.2d 1222,
1224-25 (9th Cir. 1972) ("Appellee does not explain why
disenfranchisement of those convicted of offenses that can result
in confinement in state prison is 'necessary' to vindicate any
identified state interest."); see also Stephens v. Yeomans, 327 F.
Supp. 1182, 1188 (D.N.J. 1970) (striking down New Jersey felon
disenfranchisement law because court "perceive[d] no rational basis
for the . . . classification" of felons as a group that could not
vote).
My reading of the legislative history of Article 120,
much of which indicates a punitive motivation, and the lack of a
-96-
sufficient rational nexus to any non-punitive purpose, suggest that
any purported regulatory motivations are, in fact, disingenuous.
Moreover, the potential non-punitive rationales for felon
disenfranchisement are, in many cases, now regarded as illegitimate
grounds for restricting the vote, and as such, should not be
credited. See Trop, 356 U.S. at 96 (holding that a statute is
non-penal "if it imposes a disability, not to punish but to
accomplish some other legitimate governmental purpose." (emphasis
added)). That leaves criminal punishment as the only legitimate
discernible "legislative aim" behind Article 120. I will consider,
in turn, the various non-punitive justifications potentially
assignable to Article 120 and explain why each cannot be rationally
assignable to it.
First, the majority suggests that the "obvious rational
non-punitive purpose for disenfranchisement" is the concern about
felons "exercis[ing] control over [people's] lives by voting from
prison." But as explained supra, this concern actually boils down
to the punitive sentiment that felons do not "deserve" to do so.
Second, the Commonwealth argues, on appeal, that the
purpose of Article 120, evidenced by its placement alongside other
valid voter qualifications in the Massachusetts constitution, was
to exempt from the franchise those persons "deem[ed] unfit to vote,"
such as minors, persons under guardianships, and persons convicted
of corrupt election practices. That argument rests on the principle
-97-
that, due to their lack of respect for the criminal law, felons,
like minors and mentally incompetent persons, "have raised questions
about their ability to vote responsibly," and therefore, "cannot be
trusted" to do so. Given the absence of any reference to voter
"competence" in the legislative history of Article 120, and the weak
connection between disenfranchising incarcerated felons and the
alleged interest in responsible voting, I am inclined to dismiss
this explanation as a pre-textual rationale masking a punitive
purpose. See Hendricks, 521 U.S. at 371 (Kennedy, J., concurring)
("If the object or purpose of the Kansas law had been to provide
treatment but the treatment provisions were adopted as a sham or
mere pretext, there would have been an indication of the forbidden
purpose to punish."). This is because disenfranchising felons is
both under and over-inclusive of this alleged rationale. It is
under-inclusive because if persons who violate the law have shown
that they cannot vote responsibly, then not only incarcerated
felons, but all persons who commit any kind of crime should be
disenfranchised, whether they are serving a custodial sentence or
not. Moreover, all citizens who for any reason have shown
themselves to be irresponsible voters should be disenfranchised as
well. It is over-inclusive because some incarcerated felons,
despite their prior transgressions, may have, through the
rehabilitative elements of their sentence, developed great respect
for society's rules. While it is true that "[a] statute is not
-98-
deemed punitive simply because it lacks a close or perfect fit with
the non-punitive aims it seeks to advance," Smith, 538 U.S. at 102-
03 (emphasis added), the connection here seems especially
attenuated, especially in light of the fundamental right that is at
stake. This suggests that the concern with felons being
"unqualified" is "simply a fictional concern advanced to mask a
punitive purpose." United States v. Brown, 381 U.S. 437, 446-47
(White, J., dissenting).
More importantly, I question whether the Commonwealth can
rely on a felon's purported incapacity to vote responsibly as the
"non-punitive rationale" for Article 120 given that neither the
ability to vote responsibly nor respect for the existing law remain
"reasonable ground[s] of eligibility for voting." See Trop, 356 U.S.
at 96-97. Rather, the idea that a particular group may be
disqualified from voting based on a lack of respect for existing
criminal law now constitutes a form of viewpoint discrimination that
has been expressly rejected. See, e.g., Romer, 517 U.S. at 634 (see
parenthetical, supra, n.19); Dunn v. Blumstein, 405 U.S. 330, 354-56
(1972) (rejecting durational residency requirements that rested on
claims about the desirability of ensuring that citizens understood,
and shared, community values before they were permitted to vote);
see also Carrington v. Rash, 380 U.S. 89, 94 (1965) ("'Fencing out'
from the franchise a sector of the population because of the way
they may vote is constitutionally impermissible."). Thus, according
-99-
to one scholar, "contemporary voting rights doctrine casts a serious
shadow on the central traditional non-penal justification for felon
disenfranchisement: the claim that ex-offenders should not be
permitted to vote because they lack the qualities of mind or
character voters ought to possess." Karlan, supra, at 1152.
Third, a similar analysis applies to the purported non-
punitive "regulatory" purpose arbitrarily assigned to Article 120
by the district court. The district court suggested that prisoners
are somehow unqualified to participate in the "participatory and
collegial process" of "representative democracy" because they "have
limited access to information and little opportunity to discuss
issues with individuals who are not also being punished for breaking
the law." Not only is this "inability-to-become-informed" rationale
entirely absent from the discussions motivating the enactment of
Article 120, but it is simply not rationally connected with
disenfranchising the entire convicted felon population, many of whom
may very well have access to newspapers, media, and contact to
outside visitors, as well as the leisure time to become politically
informed, and thereby, even more knowledgeable voters than law-
abiding persons on the "outside." But again, and more importantly,
the Supreme Court has consistently rejected restrictions on the
franchise in order to further "knowledgeable or intelligent voting."
See, e.g., Dunn, 405 U.S. at 356. Thus, "[i]f neither good
character nor intelligent use of the ballot nor support for existing
-100-
criminal laws are generally permissible prerequisites for voting,
then it would be perverse to rely on criminal convictions as
evidence that individuals lack qualities that voters are not
required to have." Karlan, supra, at 1155. "The obvious
alternative is to conclude that disenfranchisement is indeed
punitive and that if it is to be justified, it must be justified as
a legitimate form of punishment, rather than as a species of
political regulation." Id.
Finally, that this "alternative purpose" factor of the
Mendoza-Martinez analysis weighs in favor of deeming Article 120 a
punitive sanction is bolstered by examining what has been found to
constitute a "legitimate non-punitive purpose" in prior Mendoza-
Martinez cases, and what has not. That examination reveals that
those cases holding particular sanctions to constitute non-punitive
regulatory measures have served far clearer and more substantial
societal interests than the attenuated justifications provided for
felon disenfranchisement. For example, in Hendricks, the state
civil commitment law held to be non-punitive was intended to protect
the public from dangerous mentally ill persons "likely to engage in
'predatory acts of sexual violence.'" 521 U.S. at 350. Similarly,
Alaska's sexual offender registration requirement, held to be
non-punitive in Smith, had the express purpose of "protecting the
public from sex offenders" who "pose a high risk of reoffending."
538 U.S. at 93; see also United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 747
-101-
(1987) (holding that preventative detention under Bail Reform Act,
justified by the need to prevent "danger to the community," was
regulatory and preventative, rather than punitive).
On the other hand, the provision being challenged before
us bears a far greater resemblance to the one at issue in Mendoza-
Martinez itself. In Mendoza-Martinez, where "there was no reference
to the societal good that would be wrought by the legislation," the
Supreme Court concluded that "the obvious inference" was that
"Congress was concerned solely with inflicting effective retribution
upon this class of draft evaders and, no doubt, on others similarly
situated." Mendoza-Martinez, 372 U.S. at 182; see also Trop, 356
U.S. at 97-98 (holding that statute stripping military deserters of
citizenship rights cannot rationally be treated other than as a
penal law). Finding no legitimate non-penal interest served by the
legislation, the Supreme Court in Mendoza-Martinez did not go on to
speculate as to potential alternative justifications. But even if
it had, the conceivable legitimate non-penal justification for
stripping an American of his citizenship rights for violating a
criminal statute prohibiting the evasion of military service, as in
Mendoza-Martinez and Trop, is no more substantial than the
conceivable justifications for stripping a U.S. citizen of an
essential component of those rights (i.e. voting), for violating
another criminal statute. Of course, one could argue that by
abandoning the obligations of citizenship by evading the military
-102-
obligations attendant thereto, a person shows that he is not
"competent" to exercise the benefits and burdens of citizenship,
just like one could argue that a person who breaches the criminal
law shows that he is not competent to exercise the responsibility
of aiding in its enactment. But the Supreme Court has refused to
make this leap, and neither should we here. Given the similarities
between the respective sanctions47 -- deprivation of citizenship and
deprivation of voting rights -- the lack of any clear non-punitive
interest for either sanction, and the similar triggering event for
the imposition of each, namely, violation of a criminal law, I think
we are compelled by Mendoza-Martinez to hold Article 120 to be a
penal measure. Finding Article 120 to be a penal measure, its
constitutionality is subject to the constraints of the Ex Post Facto
Clause, and violates that clause as retroactively applied to the
plaintiffs.
To be abundantly clear, I see nothing constitutionally
impermissible about disenfranchising felons as a form of criminal
punishment. Criminals who are convicted of serious offenses
pursuant to a legitimate process are properly deprived by the state
47
See Nw. Austin, 557 U.S. at ___, 2009 WL 1738645 at *7
(describing "the right to vote" as "one of the most fundamental
rights our citizens"); Tashjian, 479 U.S. at 217; Wolfish, 441
U.S. at 589-90 & n.22 (Stevens, J. dissenting) (noting that "[t]he
withdrawal of rights is itself among the most basic punishments
that society can exact, for such a withdrawal qualifies the
subject's citizenship and violates his dignity" and citing
disenfranchisement as the "classic example of the coincidence of
punishment and the total deprivation of rights").
-103-
of a panoply of fundamental individual and civil rights. But
"punishment" must be labeled what it is, and imposed only in
compliance with the time-honored constitutional guarantees that
legitimate the exercise of that practice. Central among these
guarantees is the prohibition against the enactment of ex post facto
laws. As Article 120 inflicts a greater punishment upon convicted
felons than the law annexed to their crimes when committed, see
Calder v. Bull, 3 Dall. 386, 390 (1798), I would invalidate its
retroactive application. Thus, I would reverse the decision of the
district court as to the ex post facto claim, and order that
judgment be entered for plaintiffs.
For the reasons herein stated, I respectfully dissent.
-104-