Apple, Inc. v. Pepper

(Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2018 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus APPLE INC. v. PEPPER ET AL. CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT No. 17–204. Argued November 26, 2018—Decided May 13, 2019 Apple Inc. sells iPhone applications, or apps, directly to iPhone owners through its App Store—the only place where iPhone owners may law- fully buy apps. Most of those apps are created by independent devel- opers under contracts with Apple. Apple charges the developers a $99 annual membership fee, allows them to set the retail price of the apps, and charges a 30% commission on every app sale. Respond- ents, four iPhone owners, sued Apple, alleging that the company has unlawfully monopolized the aftermarket for iPhone apps. Apple moved to dismiss, arguing that the iPhone owners could not sue be- cause they were not direct purchasers from Apple under Illinois Brick Co. v. Illinois, 431 U. S. 720. The District Court agreed, but the Ninth Circuit reversed, concluding that the iPhone owners were di- rect purchasers because they purchased apps directly from Apple. Held: Under Illinois Brick, the iPhone owners were direct purchasers who may sue Apple for alleged monopolization. Pp. 4–14. (a) This straightforward conclusion follows from the text of the an- titrust laws and from this Court’s precedent. Section 4 of the Clayton Act provides that “any person who shall be injured in his business or property by reason of anything forbidden in the antitrust laws may sue.” 15 U. S. C. §15(a). That broad text readily covers consumers who purchase goods or services at higher-than-competitive prices from an allegedly monopolistic retailer. Applying §4, this Court has consistently stated that “the immediate buyers from the alleged anti- trust violators” may maintain a suit against the antitrust violators, Kansas v. UtiliCorp United Inc., 497 U. S. 199, 207, but has ruled that indirect purchasers who are two or more steps removed from the violator in a distribution chain may not sue. Unlike the consumer in Illinois Brick, the iPhone owners here are not consumers at the bot- 2 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Syllabus tom of a vertical distribution chain who are attempting to sue manu- facturers at the top of the chain. The absence of an intermediary in the distribution chain between Apple and the consumer is dispositive. Pp. 4–7. (b) Apple argues that Illinois Brick allows consumers to sue only the party who sets the retail price, whether or not the party sells the good or service directly to the complaining party. But that theory suffers from three main problems. First, it contradicts statutory text and precedent by requiring the Court to rewrite the rationale of Illi- nois Brick and to gut its longstanding bright-line rule. Any ambigui- ty in Illinois Brick should be resolved in the direction of the statutory text, which states that “any person” injured by an antitrust violation may sue to recover damages. Second, Apple’s theory is not persua- sive economically or legally. It would draw an arbitrary and unprin- cipled line among retailers based on their financial arrangements with their manufacturers or suppliers. And it would permit a con- sumer to sue a monopolistic retailer when the retailer set the retail price by marking up the price it had paid the manufacturer or suppli- er for the good or service but not when the manufacturer or supplier set the retail price and the retailer took a commission on each sale. Third, Apple’s theory would provide a roadmap for monopolistic re- tailers to structure transactions with manufacturers or suppliers so as to evade antitrust claims by consumers and thereby thwart effec- tive antitrust enforcement. Pp. 7–11. (c) Contrary to Apple’s argument, the three Illinois Brick rationales for adopting the direct-purchaser rule cut strongly in respondents’ fa- vor. First, Apple posits that allowing only the upstream app develop- ers—and not the downstream consumers—to sue Apple would mean more effective antitrust enforcement. But that makes little sense, and it would directly contradict the longstanding goal of effective pri- vate enforcement and consumer protection in antitrust cases. Sec- ond, Apple warns that calculating the damages in successful consum- er antitrust suits against monopolistic retailers might be complicated. But Illinois Brick is not a get-out-of-court-free card for monopolistic retailers to play any time that a damages calculation might be complicated. Third, Apple claims that allowing consumers to sue will result in “conflicting claims to a common fund—the amount of the alleged overcharge.” Illinois Brick, 431 U. S., at 737. But this is not a case where multiple parties at different levels of a distribution chain are trying to recover the same passed-through overcharge initially levied by the manufacturer at the top of the chain, cf. id., at 726–727. Pp. 11–14. 846 F. 3d 313, affirmed. Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 3 Syllabus KAVANAUGH, J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which GINS- BURG, BREYER, SOTOMAYOR, and KAGAN, JJ., joined. GORSUCH, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which ROBERTS, C. J., and THOMAS and ALITO, JJ., joined. Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 1 Opinion of the Court NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 17–204 _________________ APPLE INC., PETITIONER v. ROBERT PEPPER, ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT [May 13, 2019] JUSTICE KAVANAUGH delivered the opinion of the Court. In 2007, Apple started selling iPhones. The next year, Apple launched the retail App Store, an electronic store where iPhone owners can purchase iPhone applications from Apple. Those “apps” enable iPhone owners to send messages, take photos, watch videos, buy clothes, order food, arrange transportation, purchase concert tickets, donate to charities, and the list goes on. “There’s an app for that” has become part of the 21st-century American lexicon. In this case, however, several consumers contend that Apple charges too much for apps. The consumers argue, in particular, that Apple has monopolized the retail mar- ket for the sale of apps and has unlawfully used its mo- nopolistic power to charge consumers higher-than- competitive prices. A claim that a monopolistic retailer (here, Apple) has used its monopoly to overcharge consumers is a classic antitrust claim. But Apple asserts that the consumer- plaintiffs in this case may not sue Apple because they supposedly were not “direct purchasers” from Apple under our decision in Illinois Brick Co. v. Illinois, 431 U. S. 720, 2 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Opinion of the Court 745–746 (1977). We disagree. The plaintiffs purchased apps directly from Apple and therefore are direct purchas- ers under Illinois Brick. At this early pleadings stage of the litigation, we do not assess the merits of the plaintiffs’ antitrust claims against Apple, nor do we consider any other defenses Apple might have. We merely hold that the Illinois Brick direct-purchaser rule does not bar these plaintiffs from suing Apple under the antitrust laws. We affirm the judgment of the U. S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit. I In 2007, Apple began selling iPhones. In July 2008, Apple started the App Store. The App Store now contains about 2 million apps that iPhone owners can download. By contract and through technological limitations, the App Store is the only place where iPhone owners may lawfully buy apps. For the most part, Apple does not itself create apps. Rather, independent app developers create apps. Those independent app developers then contract with Apple to make the apps available to iPhone owners in the App Store. Through the App Store, Apple sells the apps directly to iPhone owners. To sell an app in the App Store, app de- velopers must pay Apple a $99 annual membership fee. Apple requires that the retail sales price end in $0.99, but otherwise allows the app developers to set the retail price. Apple keeps 30 percent of the sales price, no matter what the sales price might be. In other words, Apple pockets a 30 percent commission on every app sale. In 2011, four iPhone owners sued Apple. They allege that Apple has unlawfully monopolized “the iPhone apps aftermarket.” App. to Pet. for Cert. 53a. The plaintiffs allege that, via the App Store, Apple locks iPhone owners “into buying apps only from Apple and paying Apple’s 30% Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 3 Opinion of the Court fee, even if ” the iPhone owners wish “to buy apps else- where or pay less.” Id., at 45a. According to the com- plaint, that 30 percent commission is “pure profit” for Apple and, in a competitive environment with other retail- ers, “Apple would be under considerable pressure to sub- stantially lower its 30% profit margin.” Id., at 54a–55a. The plaintiffs allege that in a competitive market, they would be able to “choose between Apple’s high-priced App Store and less costly alternatives.” Id., at 55a. And they allege that they have “paid more for their iPhone apps than they would have paid in a competitive market.” Id., at 53a. Apple moved to dismiss the complaint, arguing that the iPhone owners were not direct purchasers from Apple and therefore may not sue. In Illinois Brick, this Court held that direct purchasers may sue antitrust violators, but also ruled that indirect purchasers may not sue. The District Court agreed with Apple and dismissed the com- plaint. According to the District Court, the iPhone owners were not direct purchasers from Apple because the app developers, not Apple, set the consumers’ purchase price. The Ninth Circuit reversed. The Ninth Circuit concluded that the iPhone owners were direct purchasers under Illinois Brick because the iPhone owners purchased apps directly from Apple. According to the Ninth Circuit, Illi- nois Brick means that a consumer may not sue an alleged monopolist who is two or more steps removed from the consumer in a vertical distribution chain. See In re Apple iPhone Antitrust Litig., 846 F. 3d 313, 323 (2017). Here, however, the consumers purchased directly from Apple, the alleged monopolist. Therefore, the Ninth Circuit held that the iPhone owners could sue Apple for allegedly monopolizing the sale of iPhone apps and charging higher- than-competitive prices. Id., at 324. We granted certiorari. 585 U. S. ___ (2018). 4 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Opinion of the Court II A The plaintiffs’ allegations boil down to one straightfor- ward claim: that Apple exercises monopoly power in the retail market for the sale of apps and has unlawfully used its monopoly power to force iPhone owners to pay Apple higher-than-competitive prices for apps. According to the plaintiffs, when iPhone owners want to purchase an app, they have only two options: (1) buy the app from Apple’s App Store at a higher-than-competitive price or (2) do not buy the app at all. Any iPhone owners who are dissatis- fied with the selection of apps available in the App Store or with the price of the apps available in the App Store are out of luck, or so the plaintiffs allege. The sole question presented at this early stage of the case is whether these consumers are proper plaintiffs for this kind of antitrust suit—in particular, our precedents ask, whether the consumers were “direct purchasers” from Apple. Illinois Brick, 431 U. S., at 745–746. It is undis- puted that the iPhone owners bought the apps directly from Apple. Therefore, under Illinois Brick, the iPhone owners were direct purchasers who may sue Apple for alleged monopolization. That straightforward conclusion follows from the text of the antitrust laws and from our precedents. First is text: Section 2 of the Sherman Act makes it unlawful for any person to “monopolize, or attempt to monopolize, or combine or conspire with any other person or persons, to monopolize any part of the trade or com- merce among the several States, or with foreign nations.” 26 Stat. 209, 15 U. S. C. §2. Section 4 of the Clayton Act in turn provides that “any person who shall be injured in his business or property by reason of anything forbidden in the antitrust laws may sue . . . the defendant . . . and shall recover threefold the damages by him sustained, and the cost of suit, including a reasonable attorney’s fee.” 38 Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 5 Opinion of the Court Stat. 731, 15 U. S. C. §15(a) (emphasis added). The broad text of §4—“any person” who has been “injured” by an antitrust violator may sue—readily covers consumers who purchase goods or services at higher-than-competitive prices from an allegedly monopolistic retailer. Second is precedent: Applying §4, we have consistently stated that “the immediate buyers from the alleged anti- trust violators” may maintain a suit against the antitrust violators. Kansas v. UtiliCorp United Inc., 497 U. S. 199, 207 (1990); see also Illinois Brick, 431 U. S., at 745–746. At the same time, incorporating principles of proximate cause into §4, we have ruled that indirect purchasers who are two or more steps removed from the violator in a distribution chain may not sue. Our decision in Illinois Brick established a bright-line rule that authorizes suits by direct purchasers but bars suits by indirect purchasers. Id., at 746.1 The facts of Illinois Brick illustrate the rule. Illinois Brick Company manufactured and distributed concrete blocks. Illinois Brick sold the blocks primarily to masonry contractors, and those contractors in turn sold masonry structures to general contractors. Those general contrac- tors in turn sold their services for larger construction projects to the State of Illinois, the ultimate consumer of the blocks. The consumer State of Illinois sued the manufacturer Illinois Brick. The State alleged that Illinois Brick had engaged in a conspiracy to fix the price of concrete blocks. According to the complaint, the State paid more for the concrete blocks than it would have paid absent the price- fixing conspiracy. The monopoly overcharge allegedly flowed all the way down the distribution chain to the —————— 1 Illinois Brick held that the direct-purchaser requirement applies to claims for damages. Illinois Brick did not address injunctive relief, and we likewise do not address injunctive relief in this case. 6 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Opinion of the Court ultimate consumer, who was the State of Illinois. This Court ruled that the State could not bring an anti- trust action against Illinois Brick, the alleged violator, because the State had not purchased concrete blocks directly from Illinois Brick. The proper plaintiff to bring that claim against Illinois Brick, the Court stated, would be an entity that had purchased directly from Illinois Brick. Ibid. The bright-line rule of Illinois Brick, as articulated in that case and as we reiterated in UtiliCorp, means that indirect purchasers who are two or more steps removed from the antitrust violator in a distribution chain may not sue. By contrast, direct purchasers—that is, those who are “the immediate buyers from the alleged antitrust violators”—may sue. UtiliCorp, 497 U. S., at 207. For example, if manufacturer A sells to retailer B, and retailer B sells to consumer C, then C may not sue A. But B may sue A if A is an antitrust violator. And C may sue B if B is an antitrust violator. That is the straightforward rule of Illinois Brick. See Loeb Industries, Inc. v. Sumi- tomo Corp., 306 F. 3d 469, 481–482 (CA7 2002) (Wood, J.).2 In this case, unlike in Illinois Brick, the iPhone owners are not consumers at the bottom of a vertical distribution chain who are attempting to sue manufacturers at the top of the chain. There is no intermediary in the distribution chain between Apple and the consumer. The iPhone owners purchase apps directly from the retailer Apple, who is the alleged antitrust violator. The iPhone owners pay the alleged overcharge directly to Apple. The absence of an intermediary is dispositive. Under Illinois Brick, the —————— 2 Thirty States and the District of Columbia filed an amicus brief supporting the plaintiffs, and they argue that C should be able to sue A in that hypothetical. They ask us to overrule Illinois Brick to allow such suits. In light of our ruling in favor of the plaintiffs in this case, we have no occasion to consider that argument for overruling Illinois Brick. Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 7 Opinion of the Court iPhone owners are direct purchasers from Apple and are proper plaintiffs to maintain this antitrust suit. B All of that seems simple enough. But Apple argues strenuously against that seemingly simple conclusion, and we address its arguments carefully. For this kind of re- tailer case, Apple’s theory is that Illinois Brick allows consumers to sue only the party who sets the retail price, whether or not that party sells the good or service directly to the complaining party. Apple says that its theory ac- cords with the economics of the transaction. Here, Apple argues that the app developers, not Apple, set the retail price charged to consumers, which according to Apple means that the consumers may not sue Apple. We see three main problems with Apple’s “who sets the price” theory. First, Apple’s theory contradicts statutory text and precedent. As we explained above, the text of §4 broadly affords injured parties a right to sue under the antitrust laws. And our precedent in Illinois Brick established a bright-line rule where direct purchasers such as the con- sumers here may sue antitrust violators from whom they purchased a good or service. Illinois Brick, as we read the opinion, was not based on an economic theory about who set the price. Rather, Illinois Brick sought to ensure an effective and efficient litigation scheme in antitrust cases. To do so, the Court drew a bright line that allowed direct purchasers to sue but barred indirect purchasers from suing. When there is no intermediary between the pur- chaser and the antitrust violator, the purchaser may sue. The Illinois Brick bright-line rule is grounded on the “belief that simplified administration improves antitrust enforcement.” 2A P. Areeda, H. Hovenkamp, R. Blair, & C. Durrance, Antitrust Law ¶346e, p. 194 (4th ed. 2014) (Areeda & Hovenkamp). Apple’s theory would require us 8 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Opinion of the Court to rewrite the rationale of Illinois Brick and to gut the longstanding bright-line rule. To the extent that Illinois Brick leaves any ambiguity about whether a direct purchaser may sue an antitrust violator, we should resolve that ambiguity in the direction of the statutory text. And under the text, direct purchas- ers from monopolistic retailers are proper plaintiffs to sue those retailers. Second, in addition to deviating from statutory text and precedent, Apple’s proposed rule is not persuasive econom- ically or legally. Apple’s effort to transform Illinois Brick from a direct-purchaser rule to a “who sets the price” rule would draw an arbitrary and unprincipled line among retailers based on retailers’ financial arrangements with their manufacturers or suppliers. In the retail context, the price charged by a retailer to a consumer is often a result (at least in part) of the price charged by the manufacturer or supplier to the retailer, or of negotiations between the manufacturer or supplier and the retailer. Those agreements between manufacturer or supplier and retailer may take myriad forms, including for example a markup pricing model or a commission pricing model. In a traditional markup pricing model, a hypothet- ical monopolistic retailer might pay $6 to the manufacturer and then sell the product for $10, keeping $4 for itself. In a commission pricing model, the retailer might pay noth- ing to the manufacturer; agree with the manufacturer that the retailer will sell the product for $10 and keep 40 per- cent of the sales price; and then sell the product for $10, send $6 back to the manufacturer, and keep $4. In those two different pricing scenarios, everything turns out to be economically the same for the manufacturer, retailer, and consumer. Yet Apple’s proposed rule would allow a consumer to sue the monopolistic retailer in the former situation but not the latter. In other words, under Apple’s rule a consumer Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 9 Opinion of the Court could sue a monopolistic retailer when the retailer set the retail price by marking up the price it had paid the manu- facturer or supplier for the good or service. But a consumer could not sue a monopolistic retailer when the manufac- turer or supplier set the retail price and the retailer took a commission on each sale. Apple’s line-drawing does not make a lot of sense, other than as a way to gerrymander Apple out of this and simi- lar lawsuits. In particular, we fail to see why the form of the upstream arrangement between the manufacturer or supplier and the retailer should determine whether a monopolistic retailer can be sued by a downstream con- sumer who has purchased a good or service directly from the retailer and has paid a higher-than-competitive price because of the retailer’s unlawful monopolistic conduct. As the Court of Appeals aptly stated, “the distinction between a markup and a commission is immaterial.” 846 F. 3d, at 324. A leading antitrust treatise likewise states: “Denying standing because ‘title’ never passes to a broker is an overly lawyered approach that ignores the reality that a distribution system that relies on brokerage is economically indistinguishable from one that relies on purchaser-resellers.” 2A Areeda & Hovenkamp ¶345, at 183. If a retailer has engaged in unlawful monopolistic conduct that has caused consumers to pay higher-than- competitive prices, it does not matter how the retailer structured its relationship with an upstream manufacturer or supplier—whether, for example, the retailer employed a markup or kept a commission. To be sure, if the monopolistic retailer’s conduct has not caused the consumer to pay a higher-than-competitive price, then the plaintiff ’s damages will be zero. Here, for example, if the competitive commission rate were 10 per- cent rather than 30 percent but Apple could prove that app developers in a 10 percent commission system would always set a higher price such that consumers would pay 10 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Opinion of the Court the same retail price regardless of whether Apple’s com- mission was 10 percent or 30 percent, then the consumers’ damages would presumably be zero. But we cannot as- sume in all cases—as Apple would necessarily have us do—that a monopolistic retailer who keeps a commission does not ever cause the consumer to pay a higher-than- competitive price. We find no persuasive legal or economic basis for such a blanket assertion. In short, we do not understand the relevance of the upstream market structure in deciding whether a down- stream consumer may sue a monopolistic retailer. Apple’s rule would elevate form (what is the precise arrangement between manufacturers or suppliers and retailers?) over substance (is the consumer paying a higher price because of the monopolistic retailer’s actions?). If the retailer’s unlawful monopolistic conduct caused a consumer to pay the retailer a higher-than-competitive price, the consumer is entitled to sue the retailer under the antitrust laws. Third, if accepted, Apple’s theory would provide a roadmap for monopolistic retailers to structure transac- tions with manufacturers or suppliers so as to evade anti- trust claims by consumers and thereby thwart effective antitrust enforcement. Consider a traditional supplier-retailer relationship, in which the retailer purchases a product from the supplier and sells the product with a markup to consumers. Under Apple’s proposed rule, a retailer, instead of buying the product from the supplier, could arrange to sell the prod- uct for the supplier without purchasing it from the sup- plier. In other words, rather than paying the supplier a certain price for the product and then marking up the price to sell the product to consumers, the retailer could collect the price of the product from consumers and remit only a fraction of that price to the supplier. That restructuring would allow a monopolistic retailer to insulate itself from antitrust suits by consumers, even Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 11 Opinion of the Court in situations where a monopolistic retailer is using its monopoly to charge higher-than-competitive prices to consumers. We decline to green-light monopolistic retail- ers to exploit their market position in that way. We refuse to rubber-stamp such a blatant evasion of statutory text and judicial precedent. In sum, Apple’s theory would disregard statutory text and precedent, create an unprincipled and economically senseless distinction among monopolistic retailers, and furnish monopolistic retailers with a how-to guide for evasion of the antitrust laws. C In arguing that the Court should transform the direct- purchaser rule into a “who sets the price” rule, Apple insists that the three reasons that the Court identified in Illinois Brick for adopting the direct-purchaser rule apply to this case—even though the consumers here (unlike in Illinois Brick) were direct purchasers from the alleged monopolist. The Illinois Brick Court listed three reasons for barring indirect-purchaser suits: (1) facilitating more effective enforcement of antitrust laws; (2) avoiding com- plicated damages calculations; and (3) eliminating dupli- cative damages against antitrust defendants. As we said in UtiliCorp, however, the bright-line rule of Illinois Brick means that there is no reason to ask whether the rationales of Illinois Brick “apply with equal force” in every individual case. 497 U. S., at 216. We should not engage in “an unwarranted and counterproductive exer- cise to litigate a series of exceptions.” Id., at 217. But even if we engage with this argument, we conclude that the three Illinois Brick rationales—whether consid- ered individually or together—cut strongly in the plain- tiffs’ favor here, not Apple’s. First, Apple argues that barring the iPhone owners from suing Apple will better promote effective enforcement of 12 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Opinion of the Court the antitrust laws. Apple posits that allowing only the upstream app developers—and not the downstream con- sumers—to sue Apple would mean more effective enforce- ment of the antitrust laws. We do not agree. Leaving consumers at the mercy of monopolistic retailers simply because upstream suppliers could also sue the retailers makes little sense and would directly contradict the longstanding goal of effective private enforcement and consumer protection in antitrust cases. Second, Apple warns that calculating the damages in successful consumer antitrust suits against monopolistic retailers might be complicated. It is true that it may be hard to determine what the retailer would have charged in a competitive market. Expert testimony will often be necessary. But that is hardly unusual in antitrust cases. Illinois Brick is not a get-out-of-court-free card for monop- olistic retailers to play any time that a damages calcula- tion might be complicated. Illinois Brick surely did not wipe out consumer antitrust suits against monopolistic retailers from whom the consumers purchased goods or services at higher-than-competitive prices. Moreover, the damages calculation may be just as complicated in a re- tailer markup case as it is in a retailer commission case. Yet Apple apparently accepts consumers suing monopolis- tic retailers in a retailer markup case. If Apple accepts that kind of suit, then Apple should also accept consumers suing monopolistic retailers in a retailer commission case. Third, Apple claims that allowing consumers to sue will result in “conflicting claims to a common fund—the amount of the alleged overcharge.” Illinois Brick, 431 U. S., at 737. Apple is incorrect. This is not a case where multiple parties at different levels of a distribution chain are trying to all recover the same passed-through overcharge initially levied by the manufacturer at the top of the chain. Cf. id., at 726–727; Hanover Shoe, Inc. v. United Shoe Machinery Corp., 392 U. S. 481, 483–484 Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 13 Opinion of the Court (1968). If the iPhone owners prevail, they will be entitled to the full amount of the unlawful overcharge that they paid to Apple. The overcharge has not been passed on by anyone to anyone. Unlike in Illinois Brick, there will be no need to “trace the effect of the overcharge through each step in the distribution chain.” 431 U. S., at 741. It is true that Apple’s alleged anticompetitive conduct may leave Apple subject to multiple suits by different plaintiffs. But Illinois Brick did not purport to bar multiple liability that is unrelated to passing an overcharge down a chain of distribution. Basic antitrust law tells us that the “mere fact that an antitrust violation produces two different classes of victims hardly entails that their injuries are duplicative of one another.” 2A Areeda & Hovenkamp ¶339d, at 136. Multiple suits are not atypical when the intermediary in a distribution chain is a bottleneck monopolist or monopsonist (or both) between the manufacturer on the one end and the consumer on the other end. A retailer who is both a monopolist and a monopsonist may be liable to different classes of plaintiffs—both to downstream consumers and to upstream suppliers—when the retailer’s unlawful conduct affects both the downstream and upstream markets. Here, some downstream iPhone consumers have sued Apple on a monopoly theory. And it could be that some upstream app developers will also sue Apple on a monop- sony theory. In this instance, the two suits would rely on fundamentally different theories of harm and would not assert dueling claims to a “common fund,” as that term was used in Illinois Brick. The consumers seek damages based on the difference between the price they paid and the competitive price. The app developers would seek lost profits that they could have earned in a competitive retail market. Illinois Brick does not bar either category of suit. In short, the three Illinois Brick rationales do not per- 14 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER Opinion of the Court suade us to remake Illinois Brick and to bar direct- purchaser suits against monopolistic retailers who employ commissions rather than markups. The plaintiffs seek to hold retailers to account if the retailers engage in unlaw- ful anticompetitive conduct that harms consumers who purchase from those retailers. That is why we have anti- trust law. * * * Ever since Congress overwhelmingly passed and Presi- dent Benjamin Harrison signed the Sherman Act in 1890, “protecting consumers from monopoly prices” has been “the central concern of antitrust.” 2A Areeda & Hovenkamp ¶345, at 179. The consumers here purchased apps directly from Apple, and they allege that Apple used its monopoly power over the retail apps market to charge higher-than-competitive prices. Our decision in Illinois Brick does not bar the consumers from suing Apple for Apple’s allegedly monopolistic conduct. We affirm the judgment of the U. S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit. It is so ordered. Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 1 GORSUCH, J., dissenting SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 17–204 _________________ APPLE INC., PETITIONER v. ROBERT PEPPER, ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE NINTH CIRCUIT [May 13, 2019] JUSTICE GORSUCH, with whom THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE THOMAS, and JUSTICE ALITO join, dissenting. More than 40 years ago, in Illinois Brick Co. v. Illinois, 431 U. S. 720 (1977), this Court held that an antitrust plaintiff can’t sue a defendant for overcharging someone else who might (or might not) have passed on all (or some) of the overcharge to him. Illinois Brick held that these convoluted “pass on” theories of damages violate tradi- tional principles of proximate causation and that the right plaintiff to bring suit is the one on whom the overcharge immediately and surely fell. Yet today the Court lets a pass-on case proceed. It does so by recasting Illinois Brick as a rule forbidding only suits where the plaintiff does not contract directly with the defendant. This replaces a rule of proximate cause and economic reality with an easily manipulated and formalistic rule of contractual privity. That’s not how antitrust law is supposed to work, and it’s an uncharitable way of treating a precedent which— whatever its flaws—is far more sensible than the rule the Court installs in its place. I To understand Illinois Brick, it helps to start with the case that paved the way for that decision: Hanover Shoe, Inc. v. United Shoe Machinery Corp., 392 U. S. 481 (1968). Hanover sued United, a company that supplied machinery 2 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER GORSUCH, J., dissenting Hanover used to make shoes. Hanover alleged that United’s illegal monopoly in the shoe-making-machinery market had allowed it to charge supracompetitive prices. As damages, Hanover sought to recover the amount it had overpaid United for machinery. United replied that Han- over hadn’t been damaged at all because, United asserted, Hanover had not absorbed the supposedly “illegal over- charge” but had “passed the cost on to its customers” by raising the prices it charged for shoes. Id., at 487–488, and n. 6. This Court called United’s argument a “ ‘passing- on’ defense” because it suggested that a court should consider whether an antitrust plaintiff had “passed on” the defendant’s overcharge to its own customers when assessing if and to what degree the plaintiff was injured by the defendant’s anticompetitive conduct. Id., at 488. This Court rejected that defense. While §4 of the Clay- ton Act allows private suits for those injured by antitrust violations, we have long interpreted this language against the backdrop of the common law. See, e.g., Associated Gen. Contractors of Cal., Inc. v. Carpenters, 459 U. S. 519, 529–531 (1983). And under ancient rules of proximate causation, the “ ‘general tendency of the law, in regard to damages at least, is not to go beyond the first step.’ ” Hanover Shoe, 392 U. S., at 490, n. 8 (quoting Southern Pacific Co. v. Darnell-Taenzer Lumber Co., 245 U. S. 531, 533 (1918)). In Hanover Shoe, the first step was United’s overcharging of Hanover. To proceed beyond that and inquire whether Hanover had passed on the overcharge to its customers, the Court held, would risk the sort of prob- lems traditional principles of proximate cause were de- signed to avoid. “[N]early insuperable” questions would follow about whether Hanover had the capacity and incen- tive to pass on to its customers in the shoe-making market United’s alleged monopoly rent from the separate shoe- making-machinery market. 392 U. S., at 493. Resolving those questions would, in turn, necessitate a trial within a Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 3 GORSUCH, J., dissenting trial about Hanover’s power and conduct in its own mar- ket, with the attendant risk that proceedings would be- come “long and complicated” and would “involv[e] massive evidence and complicated theories.” Ibid. Illinois Brick was just the other side of the coin. With Hanover Shoe having held that an antitrust defendant could not rely on a pass-on theory to avoid damages, Illi- nois Brick addressed whether an antitrust plaintiff could rely on a pass-on theory to recover damages. The State of Illinois had sued several manufacturers of concrete blocks, alleging that the defendants’ price-fixing conspiracy had enabled them to overcharge building contractors, who in turn had passed on those charges to their customers, including the State. Recognizing that Hanover Shoe had already prohibited antitrust violators from using a “pass- on theory” defensively, the Court declined to “permit offensive use of a pass-on theory against an alleged viola- tor that could not use the same theory as a defense.” 431 U. S., at 735. “Permitting the use of pass-on theories under §4,” the Court reasoned, would require determining how much of the manufacturer’s monopoly rent was ab- sorbed by intermediary building contractors and how much they were able and chose to pass on to their custom- ers like the State. Id., at 737. Allowing pass-on theories would, as well, allow “plaintiffs at each level in the distri- bution chain” to “assert conflicting claims to a common fund,” which would require “massive efforts to apportion the recovery among all potential plaintiffs that could have absorbed part of the overcharge—from direct purchasers to middlemen to ultimate consumers.” Ibid. Better again, the Court decided, to adhere to traditional rules of proxi- mate causation and allow only the first affected custom- ers—the building contractors—to sue for the monopoly rents they had directly paid. There is nothing surprising in any of this. Unless Con- gress provides otherwise, this Court generally reads statu- 4 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER GORSUCH, J., dissenting tory causes of action as “limited to plaintiffs whose inju- ries are proximately caused by violations of the statute.” Lexmark Int’l, Inc. v. Static Control Components, Inc., 572 U. S. 118, 132 (2014). That proximate cause requirement typically bars suits for injuries that are “derivative of misfortunes visited upon a third person by the defendant’s acts.” Id., at 133 (internal quotation marks omitted). So, for example, if a defendant’s false advertising causes harm to one of its competitors, the competitor can sue the false advertiser under the Lanham Act. But if the competitor is unable to pay its rent as a result, the competitor’s landlord can’t sue the false advertiser, because the landlord’s harm derives from the harm to the competitor. Id., at 134; see also, e.g., Bank of America Corp. v. Miami, 581 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2017) (slip op., at 10–11); Dura Pharmaceuticals, Inc. v. Broudo, 544 U. S. 336, 346 (2005); Holmes v. Secu- rities Investor Protection Corporation, 503 U. S. 258, 268– 270 (1992). This Court has long understood Illinois Brick as simply applying these traditional proximate cause principles in the antitrust context. See Associated Gen. Contractors, 459 U. S., at 532–535, 544–545.1 II The lawsuit before us depends on just the sort of pass-on theory that Illinois Brick forbids. The plaintiffs bought apps from third-party app developers (or manufacturers) in Apple’s retail Internet App Store, at prices set by the developers. The lawsuit alleges that Apple is a monopolist —————— 1 For this reason, it’s hard to make sense of the suggestion that Illi- nois Brick may not apply to claims for injunctive relief, ante, at 5, n. 1. Under our normal rule of construction, a plaintiff who’s not proximately harmed by a defendant’s unlawful conduct has no cause of action to sue the defendant for any type of relief. Lexmark Int’l, Inc. v. Static Control Components, Inc., 572 U. S. 118, 135 (2014) (although a plaintiff that “cannot quantify its losses with sufficient certainty to recover damages . . . may still be entitled to injunctive relief,” the requirement of proxi- mate causation “must be met in every case”). Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 5 GORSUCH, J., dissenting retailer and that the 30% commission it charges develop- ers for the right to sell through its platform represents an anticompetitive price. The problem is that the 30% com- mission falls initially on the developers. So if the commis- sion is in fact a monopolistic overcharge, the developers are the parties who are directly injured by it. Plaintiffs can be injured only if the developers are able and choose to pass on the overcharge to them in the form of higher app prices that the developers alone control. Plaintiffs admit- ted as much in the district court, where they described their theory of injury this way: “[I]f Apple tells the devel- oper . . . we’re going to take this 30 percent commission . . . what’s the developer going to do? The developer is going to increase its price to cover Apple’s . . . demanded profit.” App. 143. Because this is exactly the kind of “pass-on theory” Illinois Brick rejected, it should come as no surprise that the concerns animating that decision are also implicated. Like other pass-on theories, plaintiffs’ theory will necessi- tate a complex inquiry into how Apple’s conduct affected third-party pricing decisions. And it will raise difficult questions about apportionment of damages between app developers and their customers, along with the risk of duplicative damages awards. If anything, plaintiffs’ claims present these difficulties even more starkly than did the claims at issue in Illinois Brick. Consider first the question of causation. To determine if Apple’s conduct damaged plaintiffs at all (and if so, the magnitude of their damages), a court will first have to explore whether and to what extent each individual app developer was able—and then opted—to pass on the 30% commission to its consumers in the form of higher app prices. Sorting this out, if it can be done at all, will entail wrestling with “ ‘complicated theories’ ” about “how the relevant market variables would have behaved had there been no overcharge.” Illinois Brick, 431 U. S., at 741–743. 6 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER GORSUCH, J., dissenting Will the court hear testimony to determine the market power of each app developer, how each set its prices, and what it might have charged consumers for apps if Apple’s commission had been lower? Will the court also consider expert testimony analyzing how market factors might have influenced developers’ capacity and willingness to pass on Apple’s alleged monopoly overcharge? And will the court then somehow extrapolate its findings to all of the tens of thousands of developers who sold apps through the App Store at different prices and times over the course of years? This causation inquiry will be complicated further by Apple’s requirement that all app prices end in $0.99. As plaintiffs acknowledge, this rule has caused prices for the “vast majority” of apps to “cluster” at exactly $0.99. Brief for Respondents 44. And a developer charging $0.99 for its app can’t raise its price by just enough to recover the 30-cent commission. Instead, if the developer wants to pass on the commission to consumers, it has to more than double its price to $1.99 (doubling the commission in the process), which could significantly affect its sales. In short, because Apple’s 99-cent rule creates a strong disin- centive for developers to raise their prices, it makes plain- tiffs’ pass-on theory of injury even harder to prove. Yet the court will have to consider all of this when determin- ing what damages, if any, plaintiffs suffered as a result of Apple’s allegedly excessive 30% commission.2 Plaintiffs’ claims will also necessitate “massive efforts to apportion the recovery among all potential plaintiffs that —————— 2 Plaintiffs haven’t argued (and so have forfeited in this Court any argument) that Apple’s imposition of the 99-cent rule was itself an antitrust violation that injured consumers by raising the price of apps above competitive levels. They didn’t mention the 99-cent rule in their complaint in district court or in their briefs to the court of appeals. And, as I’ve noted, they concede that they are seeking damages “based solely on” the 30% commission. Brief in Opposition 5. Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 7 GORSUCH, J., dissenting could have absorbed part of the overcharge,” including both consumers and app developers. Illinois Brick, 431 U. S., at 737. If, as plaintiffs contend, Apple’s 30% com- mission is a monopolistic overcharge, then the app devel- opers have a claim against Apple to recover whatever portion of the commission they did not pass on to consum- ers. Before today, Hanover Shoe would have prevented Apple from reducing its liability to the developers by arguing that they had passed on the overcharge to con- sumers. But the Court’s holding that Illinois Brick doesn’t govern this situation surely must mean Hanover Shoe doesn’t either. So courts will have to divvy up the com- missions Apple collected between the developers and the consumers. To do that, they’ll have to figure out which party bore what portion of the overcharge in every pur- chase. And if the developers bring suit separately from the consumers, Apple might be at risk of duplicative dam- ages awards totaling more than the full amount it col- lected in commissions. To avoid that possibility, it may turn out that the developers are necessary parties who will have to be joined in the plaintiffs’ lawsuit. See Fed. Rule Civ. Proc. 19(a)(1)(B); Illinois Brick, 431 U. S., at 739 (explaining that “[t]hese absent potential claimants would seem to fit the classic definition of ‘necessary parties,’ for purposes of compulsory joinder”).3 —————— 3 The Court denies that allowing both consumers and developers to sue over the same allegedly unlawful commission will “result in ‘con- flicting claims to a common fund’ ” as Illinois Brick feared. Ante, at 12. But Apple charged only one commission on each sale. So even assum- ing for argument’s sake that the 30% commission was entirely illegal, Apple can only be required to pay out in damages, at most, the full amount it received in commissions. To their credit, even plaintiffs have conceded as much, acknowledging that because “there is only one 30% markup,” any claim by the developers against Apple would necessarily be seeking “a piece of the same 30% pie.” Brief in Opposition 12. It’s a mystery why the Court refuses to accept that sensible concession. 8 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER GORSUCH, J., dissenting III The United States and its antitrust regulators agree with all of this, so how does the Court reach such a differ- ent conclusion? Seizing on Illinois Brick’s use of the shorthand phrase “direct purchasers” to describe the parties immediately injured by the monopoly overcharge in that case, the Court (re)characterizes Illinois Brick as a rule that anyone who purchases goods directly from an alleged antitrust violator can sue, while anyone who doesn’t, can’t. Under this revisionist version of Illinois Brick, the dispositive question becomes whether an “in- termediary in the distribution chain” stands between the plaintiff and the defendant. Ante, at 6. And because the plaintiff app purchasers in this case happen to have pur- chased apps directly from Apple, the Court reasons, they may sue. This exalts form over substance. Instead of focusing on the traditional proximate cause question where the al- leged overcharge is first (and thus surely) felt, the Court’s test turns on who happens to be in privity of contract with whom. But we’ve long recognized that antitrust law should look at “the economic reality of the relevant trans- actions” rather than “formal conceptions of contract law.” United States v. Concentrated Phosphate Export Assn., Inc., 393 U. S. 199, 208 (1968). And this case illustrates why. To evade the Court’s test, all Apple must do is amend its contracts. Instead of collecting payments for apps sold in the App Store and remitting the balance (less its commission) to developers, Apple can simply specify that consumers’ payments will flow the other way: directly to the developers, who will then remit commissions to Apple. No antitrust reason exists to treat these contrac- tual arrangements differently, and doing so will only induce firms to abandon their preferred—and presumably more efficient—distribution arrangements in favor of less efficient ones, all so they might avoid an arbitrary legal Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 9 GORSUCH, J., dissenting rule. See Copperweld Corp. v. Independence Tube Corp., 467 U. S. 752, 763, 772–774 (1984) (rejecting an “ ‘artificial distinction’ ” that “serves no valid antitrust goals but merely deprives consumers and producers of the benefits” of a particular business model). Nor does Illinois Brick come close to endorsing such a blind formalism. Yes, as the Court notes, the plaintiff in Illinois Brick did contract directly with an intermediary rather than with the putative antitrust violator. But Illinois Brick’s rejection of pass-on claims, and its explana- tion of the difficulties those claims present, had nothing to do with privity of contract. Instead and as we have seen, its rule and reasoning grew from the “general tendency of the law . . . not to go beyond” the party that first felt the sting of the alleged overcharge, and from the complica- tions that can arise when courts attempt to discern whether and to what degree damages were passed on to others. Supra, at 2–3. The Court today risks replacing a cogent rule about proximate cause with a pointless and easily evaded imposter. We do not usually read our own precedents so uncharitably. Maybe the Court proceeds as it does today because it just disagrees with Illinois Brick. After all, the Court not only displaces a sensible rule in favor of a senseless one; it also proceeds to question each of Illinois Brick’s ration- ales—doubting that those directly injured are always the best plaintiffs to bring suit, that calculating damages for pass-on plaintiffs will often be unduly complicated, and that conflicting claims to a common fund justify limiting who may sue. Ante, at 11–13. The Court even tells us that any “ambiguity” about the permissibility of pass-on damages should be resolved “in the direction of the statu- tory text,” ante, at 8—ignoring that Illinois Brick followed the well-trodden path of construing the statutory text in light of background common law principles of proximate cause. Last but not least, the Court suggests that the 10 APPLE INC. v. PEPPER GORSUCH, J., dissenting traditional understanding of Illinois Brick leads to “arbi- trary and unprincipled” results. Ante, at 8. It asks us to consider two hypothetical scenarios that, it says, prove the point. The first is a “markup” scenario in which a monopo- listic retailer buys a product from a manufacturer for $6 and then decides to sell the product to a consumer for $10, applying a supracompetitive $4 markup. The second is a “commission” scenario in which a manufacturer directs a monopolistic retailer to sell the manufacturer’s product to a consumer for $10 and the retailer keeps a supracompeti- tive 40% commission, sending $6 back to the manufac- turer. The two scenarios are economically the same, the Court asserts, and forbidding recovery in the second for lack of proximate cause makes no sense. But there is nothing arbitrary or unprincipled about Illinois Brick’s rule or results. The notion that the causal chain must stop somewhere is an ancient and venerable one. As with most any rule of proximate cause, reasonable people can debate whether Illinois Brick drew exactly the right line in cutting off claims where it did. But the line it drew is intelligible, principled, administrable, and far more reasonable than the Court’s artificial rule of contrac- tual privity. Nor do the Court’s hypotheticals come close to proving otherwise. In the first scenario, the markup falls initially on the consumer, so there’s no doubt that the retailer’s anticompetitive conduct proximately caused the consumer’s injury. Meanwhile, in the second scenario the commission falls initially on the manufacturer, and the consumer won’t feel the pain unless the manufacturer can and does recoup some or all of the elevated commission by raising its own prices. In that situation, the manufacturer is the directly injured party, and the difficulty of disaggre- gating damages between those directly and indirectly harmed means that the consumer can’t establish proxi- mate cause under traditional principles. Some amici share the Court’s skepticism of Illinois Cite as: 587 U. S. ____ (2019) 11 GORSUCH, J., dissenting Brick. They even urge us to overrule Illinois Brick, assur- ing us that “modern economic techniques” can now miti- gate any problems that arise in allocating damages be- tween those who suffer them directly and those who suffer them indirectly. Brief for State of Texas et al. as Amici Curiae 25. Maybe there is something to these arguments; maybe not. But there’s plenty of reason to decline any invitation to take even a small step away from Illinois Brick today. The plaintiffs have not asked us to overrule our precedent—in fact, they’ve disavowed any such re- quest. Tr. of Oral Arg. 40. So we lack the benefit of the adversarial process in a complex area involving a 40-year- old precedent and many hard questions. For example, if we are really inclined to overrule Illinois Brick, doesn’t that mean we must do the same to Hanover Shoe? If the proximate cause line is no longer to be drawn at the first injured party, how far down the causal chain can a plain- tiff be and still recoup damages? Must all potential claim- ants to the single monopoly rent be gathered in a single lawsuit as necessary parties (and if not, why not)? With- out any invitation or reason to revisit our precedent, and with so many grounds for caution, I would have thought the proper course today would have been to afford Illinois Brick full effect, not to begin whittling it away to a bare formalism. I respectfully dissent.