—In Carroll and Wife v. Brumby, (13 Ala. 102,) the testator had by his will declared, that . certain of his slaves should be permitted to go to Africa, .their passage to be paid, &c.; but, if they desired to remain -subject to his daughter, as they had been to him, they -.should be permitted to do so; but in no event to be sold, <or deprived of this privilege, either before or alter the death of his said daughter. “ Should they, or any, or all, prefer ■not to emigrate, then, in that event, they shall be subject to my daughter, as they are to me.” In passing upon this will, this court held, that the testator intended to give the slaves the option of freedom or servitude, but that they had not the legal capacity to malee the choice; and that, the bequest of freedom being void, the title to the slaves was vested in the daughter. The same question has never since *232arisen in this court; -and we are now asked to reconsider it, because, as is alleged, the decision is opposed to the current of< authorities upon the subject, has no solid foundation. -ofxreason to support it, and appears to have been made without-a special discussion of the principle involved.--
It is true that many cases may be found, which silently.' recognize the principle, that a bequest of freedom, which is otherwise valid, is not rendered void by the fact, that'" the election of freedom by the slave is the declared condition on which if is to take effect. The courts of North Carolina, South Carolina, Georgia, Mississippi, Kentucky, and Tennessee, have all treated as valid bequests which-provided for an election by slaves of freedom or servitude. Washington v. Blunt, 8 Ired. Eq. 253 ; Jordan v. Bradley, Dudley’s R. 170 ; Frazier v. Frazier, 2 Hill’s Ch. 305 ; Cleland v. Waters, 19 Geo. 35 ; Ross v. Vertner, 5 How. Miss. 305 ; Leech v. Cooley, 6 Sm. & M. 93 ; Graham’s Ex’r v. Sam, 7 B. Monroe, 403. John v. Moreman, 8 B. Mon. 100 ; Adams v. Adams, 10 B. Mon. 20 ; Isaac v. McGill, 9 Humph. 616 ; Wade v. Am. Col. Society, 7 Sm. & M. 694.
Mr. Cobb, in his work upon the law-of negro Slavery, notices the suggestion made in Carroll v. Brumby, (supra,) tbat a slave is incapable of making a choice between freedom and slavery, and says in reference to it: “The suggestion has not been approved by other courts, and we cannot see the force of it. The theory of a complete annihilation of will in the slave, is utterly inconsistent with all recognition of him-as a person,-especially as responsible criminally for his acts.” — Cobb on Slavery, § 363.
Notwithstanding this long array of authorities, apparently in conflict with it,, we are persuaded that the principle announced by this court in Carroll v. Brumby (supra) is a sound one ; and that any trust for emancipation, in the execution of which the election of the slave between freedom and servitude is prescribed as a necessary step, must ail, because slaves have not the legal capacity to make the election.
It is a remarkable fact, and one which may be thought *233to militate against 'the opinion we have just expressed, that in none of the numerous cases we have cited, except Cleland v. Waters, (19 Geo. 35,) does it appear that the question as to the legal capacity of slaves to make such election, was distinctly made by counsel,, or fully considered, or expressly adjudged by the court. Hence we have spoken of these cases as silently recognizing the validity of bequests providing for an election by slaves- of freedom or servitude. The legal capacity of slaves to make such election has been rather assumed than settled in them. Consequently, with the single exception j ust mentioned, they havp not the weight which would attach to cases in which the question had been directly made and ai-gued by counsel, and fully considered, and distinctly decided by the-court.
Assuming, then, that the trust in this case cannot be executed in the manner pointed out by the testator, unless the slaves choose to be emancipated,- the question is, whether the making of this election is an act which slaves have the legal capacity to perform. Can a master, by his will, clothe his slaves with the irrevocable power of. determining and changing, by an uncontrollable act of their will, their own civil status ? Before we can give an affirmative answer to these questions, we must be prepared to say, that a master may confer upon slaves the legal right to acquire for themselves, by their own unforced and un~ restrainable act, benefits and privileges inconsistent with the condition of slavery, and, at the same time, and by the-same act, to divest the property rights of others.
So far as their civil status is concerned, slaves are mere property, and their condition is that of absolute civil incapacity. Being, in respect of all civil rights and relations, not persons, but things, they ' are incapable of owning, property, or of performing any civil legal act, by which the property of others can be alienated, or the relations of property, or the legal duties or trusts in regard thereto, in any wise affected. In a late case, the supreme court of North Carolina used this language : “Under our system of *234law, a slave can- roa-ke-no contract In the nature of thing» he cannot. He is, jin contemplation of' law, not a person for that purpose. He has.no legal capacity to make a contract ; he has no > legal mind. He is r-the- property of bis-master, and all the proceeds of his labor belong to his owner. ’If property is devised or given >to him, the devise or bequest is void, and the.^personalty given either belongs-to the.giver, .or becomes .the property of the owner. A slave has no -legal status in our courts, except as a criminal, or as a.witness in certain, cases.” — Butler v. Faulk, 4 Jones' L. R. 233.
Chancellor .-Kent, in speaking of the lhws of the southera-States on the subject of negro slavery, says : “They are,, doubtless, as just and as .-mild as is deemed by those governments to be compatible with the public safety, or with-the existence of that species of property.;, antkyet, in conr templation of their laws, --slaves- are considered, in -some-respects, as things, or property, rather than persons, and" are vendible as personal estate. -They cannot, take property by descent or purchase; and all they find, and all they hold, belongs to the master. They cannot make-lawful contracts, and they are deprived of civil rights — 2 Kent, 253. So, in Emerson v. Howland, (1 Mason’s R. 45,) Judge Story says, that the slave “ has.no civil rights or privileges
In the case of Girod v. Lewis, (6 Martin’s R. 559,) it is-s’aid, that slaves have no legal .-capacity ,to assent to any contract ,* that whilst, with the-consent of the master, they have the moral power to enter into such a connection as that of marriage, the .marriage, whilst-.they remain in a state of slavery,. could ,be productive-of no civil effect, because slaves ¡areadeprived-gf all: civil rights.
The-numerous decisions in which it.has been,-held, that a promise made t-o a.-slave, 'or for.his benefit, is not enforce..able,in any legal tribunal.; that a. slave cannot sue orbe .-sued, except that he is clothed .with the statutory right Of instituting a suit for freedom:; that he cannot acquire or ,own property; that he has no 'legal-capacity .to make .a -contract,.not.even that of marriage,- — all,proceed upon the *235fundamental idea, that our slaves have no civil or social rights, and are incapable of performing by their own volition, and as a matter of right, any civil act which can be -.made the lawful foundation of vesting new rights in themselves,.,or of divesting the existing rights, or determining in .any respect the legal duties of others.
According to the legal conception of slavery, as it exists ; in the southern States, a human being endowed with civil .rights cannot be a slave. The possession of these rights is incompatible with the condition of slavery, and any at-vtempt to confer them upon a slave, durante servitutc, is an . effort to accomplish what is legally impossible. Our law recognizes no other status than that of absolute freedom, or ; absolute slavery ; and the courts have uniformly rejected, as a legal solecism, the idea that a slave, while a slave, can ¡ be invested with civil rights or legal capacity. — Abercrombie v. Abercrombie, 27 Ala. 494. Therefore, any attempt of a master to clothe his slave with the-power to perform an act, which involves the exercise of civil rights and legal capacity, must inrthe nature of things fail.
It seems too clear for dispute,,that, where a bequest is ..made to depend upon the declaration by the legatee of his -election to accept the gift, the making of this election is a. -civil act. If a grant, of an estate be made to a free person, -on condition that he -would elect a trade.;- or, if a bequest be made of either one of two named slaves the legatee may .choose, if he will elect between the two, it could not be seriously contended, that the making of the election would’ .not be a civil act. Surely that is a civil act, the performance of which either creates or divests valuable rights, or imposes a legal duty, or perfects a trust, which courts may enforce. So, when,the act of a slave, in choosing between freedom and slavery, is a necessary step in the execution of a trust, the election is a civil act, andrthe trust is void, because it presupposes .and requires that a slave, durante servi~ tute, shall be invested with privileges which do not and ■ cannot belong to one in his condition. Such a bequest is an effort .on the .part of the ..testator .to impart to slaves *236rights which belong exclusively to freemen, — thus placing them in that middle state between absolute freedom and absolute slavery, which our law, upon grounds of- paramount public policy, refuses to recognize as legally possible.
It is true that slaves are human beings, and are endowed with intellect, conscience, and will. Their moral and intellectual qualities determine, to a considerable extent, their value,, and are often looked to in ascertaining the rights and liabilities of others in relation to them as articles of property — -See Young v. Burton, 1 McMull. Eq. 255 , Bean v. Summers, 18 Gratt. 412 ; Boyce v. Anderson, 2 Peters, 150. Being endowed with intelligence, conscience, and volition, they are deemed capable of committing crime; and the same public policy which, so far as the performance of civil acts is concerned, refuses to consider them as persons, gives them a criminal status, and recognizes them as persons in respect of acts involving criminal responsibility. Because they are rational human beings, fhey are capable of committing crimes ; and, in reference to acts which are crimes, are regarded as persons. Because they are slaves, they are necessarily, and, so long as they remain slaves, incurably, incapable of performing civil acts ; and, in reference to all such, they are things, not persons.
This obvious distinction is overlooked by Mr. Cobb, in Iris criticism of the decision in Carroll v. Brumby. — See Cobb on Slavery, § 363. So far as civil acts are concerned, the slave, not being a person, has no legal mind, no will which the law can recognize. But, as soon as we pass into the region of crime, he is treated as a person, as having a legal mind, a will, capable of originating acts for which he may be subjected to punishment as a criminal. Considered in his relation to this latter class of acts, the theory of a complete annihilation of will in the slave, is wholly unfounded ; while in relation to the former class of acts, it is entirely consistent? and, indeed, is-the only theory that can be consistent, with the fundamental idea of negro slavery as--it exists with -us — namely, .that*in respect of civil rights *237and legal capacity to perform acts oí a civil nature, the slave is not a person, but a thing.
It must not be supposed from what lias been said, that our laws fail to afford slaves adequate protection against oppression or injury. This protection is not only secured by the fundamental law, the constitution of the State, (art. 6, §§ 2 and 3,) but many statutes have been enacted with a view to the same end. The law punishes an assault and battery upon them by any third person ; prohibits the infliction upon them of cruel or unusual punishment; punishes the master, or other person standing in that relation, who fails to provide the slave with a sufficiency of healthy food, or necessary clothing, or to provide for him properly in sickness or old age, or treats him in any other way with inhumanity ; and the master cannot relieve himself of the legal obligation to supply the slave’s necessary wants, by voluntarily putting the slave away from him, without providing some one to occupy the relation of master to him. The law also secures to slaves the right of trial by jury, for all offenses above petit larceny, and provides them with counsel, in certain cases, at the public expense. — See Atwood v. Beck, 21 Ala. 609; 4 Ala. 66; Code, §§ 3297, 3300, 3316, 3319, 3329.
There is nothing inconsistent with t]^e views expressed in this opinion, in the fact that a master may make his slave an agent. In that case, the acts of the slave are but the acts of the master; and this it is which gives them all their validity and effect. Hence it has been held, rthat a slave cannot act as the agent of any person but his master. — State v. Hart, 4 Ired. 246. “ The agency .of the .slave, in truth, instead of affording any argument in behalf of the existence of his social or civil rights, is but an instance or illustration of the complete dominion of the •master; of his entire control over all the powers and faculties of the slave; and of his right, consequently, to use him as an instrument or medium through which to make or execute contracts with third persons;” — Bailey v. Poindexter, 14 Grattan, 132, 198.
*238In the case just cited, the question of the legal capacity of slaves to choose between freedom and slavery underwent a most elaborate discussion by eminent counsel, and received the fullest consideration from the court; and the conclusion attained was, that a bequest of freedom, dependent upon the election of the slaves to be free, is void, because slaves have no legal capacity to make the election. To the learned arguments of the counsel, and the able opinion of Daniel, J., in that case, we are chiefly indebted for the line of argument above presented. On that occasion, the question seems to have received for the first time the deliberate consideration which its great importance demands-; and under these circumstances, the opinion pronounced is fairly entitled to outweigh a score of cases on the opposite side, where the point seems to have been rather taken for granted, than expressly decided. — See, also, Williamson v. Coulter, 14 Gratt. 394.
It is said, however, that tire trust in this case is not dependent on the election of the slaves to be free, but is perfect without it; that the election whichihey are authorized to make, is the election to remain in sláveryand that this is prescribed,' not as a necessary step in the execution of the trust, but as a condition by which it may be defeated. The argument- is, |hat' the testator first creates a valid trust, by directing his executor to remove the slaves for the purpose of emancipating them/ and then provides, as the condition which shall defeat it, the election of the slaves -to remain in-slavery. As slaves cannot,rby.any voluntary act -of ’ theirs,,-defeat a complete, any more than they can perfect art - incomplete trusty it' would’follow, if this view-of. the will is-"-corre0t, dba-Dthe condition, would be void, be cause impossible, and the trust would stand unaffected by it. •
We will not* inquire, whether, taking, the whole will together; it does not appear that the electiom-of the slaves-to be free, is-an-act essential to the execution--of the trust in the manner prescribed by the testator. — See Williamson v. Coulter, 14 Gratt. 394. For, however that may be, it is-obvious that the trust is made to depend on the election by-' *239the slaves of the place to which they are to be removed* The direction is, that the executor shall have them “ taken to some non-slaveholding State, or to the republic of Liberia, as the said slaves may prefer.” In trusts of this eharactfer, the rule cypres is not adopted or applied; and until the slaves are carried, in execution of the trust, to the State or country to which the will directs them to be carried, they do not acquire the capacity of freemen, but remain subject to the disabilities of slaves. — Hooper v. Hooper, 32 Ala. 673.
If the direction is for the removal of the slaves to a particular State, and the execution of the provision becomes impossible, from-' the refusal of such State to admit free negroes within its limits,' the bequest fails. — Nancy v. Wright, 9 Humph. 597; Adams v. Bass, 18 Geo. 130. The effect of this "will is, that the executor is to take the slaves to’ that one of two named places which they may select. Unless they make the selection, the direction fails. Unless the executor takes the -slaves a place selected by them, he does not’take them tb the place directed by the testator. The twist cannot' be executed, in the manner provided by the will, unless the e-xecutbr consults with the slaves, and is governed, as a matter of legal duty, by their will. As their election of the place to which they shall be taken is a condition, the performance of which is essential to the execution of the trust im'their favor, the making of that choice is as much a civil act as an election between freedom and slavery. The case of Cleland v. Waters, (L9 Geo. 35,) proceeds upon the idea, that in principle there-is no difference between the capacity of slaves to choose - the place to which they shall be taken, and their capacity to elect whether they will remain slaves or be emancipated. We can perceive no distinction. As the trust cannot be executed, according to the directions of the testator, unless 'this condition (the. selection by the slaves of the place to-which they shall be removed) is performed, and as the condition is one which slaves are legally incapable of performing, the trust is void.
Decree affirmed.