The precise question of law posed by appellant’s sole proposition of law is whether the General Assembly’s criminalization of mere private possession of materials which show minors participating or engaging in sexual activity, masturbation, or bestiality violates the First Amendment to the United States Constitution, as made applicable to the states by reason of the Fourteenth Amendment. Although the nation’s highest court has not entertained this exact issue, that court’s pronouncements concerning related settings are germane to the instant cause. We find that “much of the reasoning in these cases is instructive and provides guidance regarding the scope of constitutional restrictions, the competing interests involved, and the attendant public policy con*45cerns.” Gutter v. Dow Jones, Inc. (1986), 22 Ohio St. 3d 286, 288. In light of the constitutional implications and competing societal interests advanced, we believe that Mr. Justice Cardozo’s apt observation that “[a] Judge must be a historian and prophet all in one” is descriptive of our task in this unique case.
Clearly, the genesis for a resolution of the instant cause is the decision of Stanley v. Georgia (1969), 394 U.S. 557. In Stanley, Georgia police entered the defendant’s home to search for evidence of illegal bookmaking activity. While there, the police found two films in the defendant’s desk which depicted obscene matter involving adults. Stanley was arrested, indicted and convicted for knowingly having possession of obscene matter in violation of Georgia law. On appeal, the Supreme Court first recognized that, under its previous interpretations, material which had been determined to be obscene was not protected by the First Amendment. Nevertheless, the Supreme Court reversed the state court judgment by holding that the state could not constitutionally criminalize the mere private possession of obscene material. In striking the state statute, the court’s opinion focused on that aspect of the First Amendment which protects individual freedom of thought or ideas:
“It is now well established that thé Constitution protects the right to receive information and ideas, ‘This freedom [of speech and press] * * * necessarily protects the right to receive ***.’*** This right to receive information and ideas, regardless of their social worth, see Winters v. New York, 333 U.S. 507, 510 (1948), is fundamental to our free society. Moreover, in the context of this case — a prosecution for mere possession of printed or filmed matter jin the privacy of a person’s own home — that right takes on an added dimension. For also fundamental is the right to be free, except in very limited circumstances, from unwanted governmental intrus-tions into one’s privacy.
“These are the rights that appellant is asserting in the case before us. He is asserting the right to read or observe what he pleases — the right to satisfy his intellectual and emotional needs in the privacy of his own home. He is asserting the right to be free from state inquiry into the contents of his library. Georgia coiftends that appellant does not have these rights, that there are certain types of materials that the individual may not read or even possess. Georgia justifies this assertion by arguing that the films in the present case are Obscene. But we think that mere categorization of these films as ‘obscene’ is insufficient justification for such a drastic invasion of personal liberties guaranteed by the First and Fourth Amendments. Whatever may be the justifications for other statutes regulating obscenity, we do not think they reach into the privacy of one’s own home. If the First Amendment means anything, it means that a State has no business telling a man, sitting alone in his own house, what books he may read or what films he may watch. Our whole constitutional heritage rebels *46at the thought of giving government the power to control men’s minds.’ ” (Emphasis added.) Stanley, supra, at 564-565.3
After Stanley, various cases raised the issue of whether this right to receive information (even of an obscene nature) necessarily created a right to distribute or deliver obscene matter to another for purposes of his private possession of such matter. The Supreme Court has consistently rejected this notion and limited Stanley to its facts. See, e.g., United States v. Reidel (1971), 402 U.S. 351; United States v. Orito (1973), 413 U.S. 139; Paris Adult Theatre I v. Slaton (1973), 413 U.S. 49. For example, in Reidel, supra, where the appellant was convicted of using the mail to deliver obscene matter, the court upheld the conviction but noted at 356 that Stanley focused on freedom of mind and thought and the privacy of one’s home:
“The personal constitutional rights of those like Stanley to possess and read obscenity in their homes and their freedom of mind and thought do not depend on * * * whether obscenity is constitutionally protected. Their rights to have and view that material in private are independently saved by the Constitution.”
Thus, Stanley has always stood for — and still stands for — the proposition that -the state may not, consistent with the First Amendment, regulate the mere private possession of material in one’s own home merely because it is obscene. However, it is also significant to our inquiry that Justice Marshall cautioned at fn. 11 of his majority opinion in Stanley that the court did not “* * * mean to express any opinion on statutes making criminal possession of other types of printed, filmed, or recorded materials.” (Emphasis added.) Id. at 568. Rather, it was recognized in the Stanley opinion that there could be cases involving other subjects where *47“* * * compelling reasons may exist for overriding the right of the individual to possess those materials." (Emphasis added.) Id. Appellant herein argues that the state’s interests in this instance constitute the “compelling reasons” or “limited circumstances” envisioned by the Stanley court as justifying government intrusion.
It is notable that in Stanley the state of Georgia unsuccessfully asserted, inter alia, its rights to protect the individual possessor’s mind from the effects of obscenity and to prevent future deviant sexual behavior linked to exposure to obscene materials. Id. at 565-566. If appellant herein was raising the same interests, our query would be over because we could simply apply the solid notions of individual liberty set forth in the Stanley decision to this set of circumstances.4
However, in the instant case the state argues that Ohio’s Legislature is justified in barring possession of materials which visually depict minors engaging in sexual activity because society’s interest in safeguarding the privacy and physical and psychological well-being of its children is paramount.
Because of the great respect historically accorded to free speech, it is essential that we ascertain the precise nature of the state’s interest in protecting its children. Our task, then, is to ascertain if these interests are compelling and, if so, whether they also outweigh the fundamental right to be left alone in one’s home which was so clearly articulated in Stanley et al.
To aid in our understanding of the state’s impetus for the eradication of child pornography through the banning of its possession, as well as the competing interests involved, we turn to the more recent Supreme Court pronouncement in New York v. Ferber (1982), 458 U.S. 747.5 Against a *48backdrop of public indignation over the proliferation of child pornography, the Ferber court defined a new category of unprotected speech. In contrast to Stanley, Ferber dealt specifically with child pornography, not obscenity involving only adults, and upheld the constitutionality of a criminal statute outlawing the promotion of sexual performances by minors through the distribution of material depicting such performances. As such, “the Court unanimously upheld a New York criminal statute that bans the distribution of nonobscene material depicting sexual conduct by children.”6 The decision essentially holds that states can constitutionally define the visual depiction of sexual conduct by children as obscenity without having to satisfy the threshold constitutional test for determining whether the material is obscene. The court ruled that the state’s “compelling” interest in eliminating child pornography was sufficiently great to allow the states to bypass the test for adult obscenity stated in Miller v. California (1973), 413 U.S. 15. Henceforth, states may automatically declare such visual *49depictions of sexual conduct by minors to be obscene and, as such, unprotected by the First Amendment. The Ferber court did not consider the propriety of state criminal sanctions concerning the final stage of the child pornography cycle, i.e., private possession. Nevertheless, the decision does touch on the competing interests involved in this case; the court’s discussion of the state’s goals is instructive. In recognizing New York’s “compelling” interest of safeguarding the physical and mental well-being of its children, the court explained that “[t]he prevention of sexual exploitation and abuse of children constitutes a government objective of surpassing importance.” Id. at 757.
In this vein, the Ferber court set forth a number of important and legitimate state objectives accomplished by the eradication of child pornography. For instance, the court observed that “[t]he legislative judgment, as well as the judgment found in the relevant literature, is that the use of children as subjects of pornographic materials is harmful to the physiological, emotional and mental health of the child.” Id. at 758.7 The Ferber court found that the existence of photographs “depicting sexual activity by juveniles is intrinsically related to the sexual abuse of children in at least two ways. First, the materials produced are a permanent record of the children’s participation and the harm to the child is exacerbated by their circulation. Second, the distribution network for child pornography must be closed if the production of material which requires the sexual exploitation of children is to be effectively controlled.” Id. at 759.
The court also discerned that state efforts directed at the banning of production would not adequately solve the dilemma. The hidden reality of the child pornography industry makes it “difficult, if not impossible, to halt the exploitation of children by pursuing only those who produce * * Id. at 759-760. In this regard, we note that the possessor’s desire to maintain depictions of child abuse also “provide[s] an economic motive for and * * * [is] thus an integral part of the production of such materials, an activity illegal throughout the Nation.” Id. at 761. A flourishing home market for such abusive materials will help guarantee that there will be additional victimization of children. Cf. id. at 761-762, fn. 13.
Against these substantial overriding interests we believe that, like the promotion stage of the child pornography cycle addressed in Ferber, the value of permitting possession of “photographic reproductions of children *50engaged in lewd sexual conduct is exceedingly modest, if not de minimis.” Id. at 762.
*49“* * * It has been found that sexually exploited children are unable to develop healthy affectionate relationships in later life, have sexual dysfunctions, and have a tendency to become sexual abusers as adults. [Citations omitted.] * * * [S]exually exploited children [are] predisposed to self-destructive behavior such as drug and alcohol abuse or prostitution * * *. [Citations omitted.] Sexual molestation by adults is often involved in the production of child sexual performances. [Citation omitted.] When such performances are recorded and distributed, the child’s privacy interests are also invaded.”
*50Unlike the obscene materials considered in Stanley, Miller, et al., child pornography involves, by its nature, the physical, mental and sexual abuse, seduction and harmful exploitation of children. The depictions sought to be banned by the state are but memorializations of cruel mistreatment and unlawful conduct. Additionally, such material would continue to exploit and victimize the children shown by haunting them in the future. Ferber at 759, fn. 10.8 We believe the interests of the state in protecting the privacy, health, emotional welfare and well-rounded growth of its young citizens, together with its undeniable interest of safeguarding the future of society as a whole, comprise exactly the type of “compelling reasons” justifying a “very limited” First Amendment intrusion envisioned by the Stanley court. At the same time, the cost to the individual possessor’s right of free speech, privacy and thought, caused by the state’s banning of visual mementos from an episode of sexual abuse of a child, is slight. Moreover, the content value of such material is trifling and alterr native means of simulation exist.9
*51Ohio’s General Assembly has determined that it is necessary to prohibit possession of such materials in order to halt sexual exploitation and abuse of children.10 It is not our role to pass judgment on whether the legislature has chosen the best course to effect its admittedly admirable goal of combating child pornography. As the Ferber court stated, “[w]e shall not second-guess this legislative judgment.” Id. at 758. Rather, our sacred mandate is to ascertain whether the state’s chosen method runs afoul of, or unnecessarily intrudes on, constitutionally protected First Amendment rights.
“It must be presumed that the legislature, in the enactment of this law, had in mind * * *” the constitutional provision and restrictions involved and only intended to enact legislation which is in accordance with its power. State, ex rel. Bailey, v. George (1915), 92 Ohio St. 344, 346. “* * * When an enactment of the General Assembly is challenged, the challenger must overcome a strong presumption of constitutionality.” State, ex rel. Jackman, v. Ct. of Common Pleas (1967), 9 Ohio St. 2d 159, 161 [38 O.O.2d 404]. As Justice Locher replied in State v. Dorso (1983), 4 *52Ohio St. 3d 60, 61, “courts must apply all presumptions * * * so as to uphold, if at all possible, a statute or ordinance assailed as unconstitutional.” (Followed in Kettering v. State Emp. Relations Bd. [1986], 26 Ohio St. 3d 50, 52.)
In recognition of our discussion above, the presumption of constitutionality which blankets legislative enactments, and in light of the Supreme Court’s admonition in Ferber at 756 that the “States are entitled to greater leeway in the regulation of pornographic depictions of children,” we conclude that the competing public policy and constitutional concerns tilt decidedly in favor of sustaining this statute.
Consistent with our understanding of the Supreme Court’s pronouncements in Stanley and Ferber, and based on the foregoing opinion, we hold that R.C. 2907.322(A)(5), which prohibits the knowing possession or control of material which shows a minor participating or engaging in sexual activity, masturbation, or bestiality, does not violate the First Amendment to the United States Constitution, as made applicable to the states by the Fourteenth Amendment. Ohio’s compelling state interests of preserving its children’s privacy and protecting them from the cruel physiological, mental, and emotional abuse caused by sexual seduction, exploitation, and mistreatment occasioned by child pornography, outweigh appellee’s interest in possessing such visual depictions.
Accordingly, we reverse the judgment of the court of appeals and reinstate the judgment of the trial court.
Judgment reversed.
Sweeney, Locher and C. Brown, JJ., concur. Holmes, Douglas and Wright, JJ., separately concur in the syllabus and judgment. C. Brown, J., concurs separately. Holmes, J.,concurring. I fully agree with the result as well as with the reasoning in the majority opinion. However, I write separately to make several observations regarding the applicable legal standard. I would also add several reasons why the act of privately possessing photographic child pornography is inimical to society’s legitimate and recognized interests.
It should be emphasized that Stanley v. Georgia (1969), 394 U.S. 557 recognized in the facts of that case that a combination of constitutional rights were infringed.11 Consequently, the Stanley court was required to *53fashion a compound resolution which was partly First Amendment analysis and partly the “added dimension” of Fourth Amendment privacy principles. Id. at 564. The court’s First Amendment inquiry was plainly along the lines of the clear and present danger test,12 and was a significant departure from the standard set forth in Roth v. United States (1957), 354 U.S. 476, 486-487 [14 O.O.2d 331]. The state’s interest in controlling obscenity, which seemed sufficient in Roth, was, in Stanley, insufficient without any greater countervailing state interest. The later reaffirmation of Roth, see, e.g., United States v. Thirty-seven Photographs (1971), 402 U.S. 363, demonstrated that the Stanley decision flowed not so much from the content of the material as the fear of consequences which might flow from the privacy intrusion.
There was no justifiable state interest where there was no provable connection between the act of possession and crimes of sexual violence. Nor was there any demonstrable victimization to the participants in production, dissemination, or consumption of obscenity. Although “* * * the circumstances that would make the clear and present danger test applicable were not present,”13 Stanley reserved power to regulate private use and private possession where the state demonstrates a substantial and subordinating state interest.14 See, e.g., Ginsberg v. New York (1968), 390 U.S. 629 [44 O.O.2d 339].
In New York v. Ferber (1982), 458 U.S. 747, child pornography was described as “not entitled to First Amendment protection.” Id. at 765. More significantly, Ferber allowed the state to regulate production and distribution of child pornography without proof of obscenity.15 The material need only visually depict a child, below a certain age, engaged in sexual conduct, which conduct, as in the Ohio statute, was specifically defined. Id. at 761.
While not bearing upon the issue of possession, Ferber stated the *54unanimous belief of the court that child pornography is nothing less than the evil sexual exploitation of children with demonstrable harm to their later lives and which justifies fully the state’s interest in regulating child pornography. Id. at 757-759. Moreover, the Ferber court specifically concluded that: prevention of sexual exploitation of children is a governmental objective of surpassing importance; banning production only does not adequately address the problems posed by a permanent record of the child’s participation and the incentive to produce posed by circulation of the material; selling and advertising child pornography “provide an economic motive for and are thus an integral part of the production of such materials”; the cost to free speech resulting from a ban of child pornography is slight; and content-based classification is permissible when the evil to be restricted “so overwhelmingly outweighs the expressive interests, if any, at stake, that no process of case-by-case adjudication is required.”16 Ferber, supra, at 756-764.
The act of privately possessing photographic child pornography is so inimical to society’s legitimate and recognized interests that a state may constitutionally intrude on those First Amendment and privacy interests set forth in Stanley. Initially, child pornography has several noticeable similarities to contraband drugs, for which possession is also an offense. When drugs are illegally possessed and used, the primary victim is the consumer. Yet the state correctly punishes everyone in the chain for the crime of possession, including the distributor, manufacturer and victim-possessor. There is no logical difference whether the admitted victimization occurs during the production or consumption phase of the process. So also should the state have power to regulate photographic child pornography. Since it is so unlike literature as to possess mere de minimis literary value, its entire chain of possession ought reasonably to be subject to sanction.
The purchaser of child pornography who gives money in exchange for this procured misery is a vital part of the production-distribution system. Such knowing actions give him equal guilt with the procurer, the producer and the distributor. Those who purchase or seek out such materials are at the very core of the problem by knowingly creating a demand for the abuse. It is his ultimate enjoyment of the perverse and harmful acts recorded that fuels the entire industry.
There is nothing in the mere existence of contraband under one’s private control which creates a need for governmental regulation. Instead, it is the subsequent use to which these items are put after possession and the potential for grave harm flowing from such use which justify the regulation.
One of the primary uses of child pornography is for the systematic *55desensitization, as part of an insidious process, to induce children to engage in the acts depicted.17 Apparently the largest amount of child molestation is committed in local communities to feed the “informal cottage industry” which is only partly operated for profit.18 Once a youngster is selected, child pornography is utilized to systematically reduce his inhibitions through calculated exposure to varying degrees of the material. “* * * After the child’s anxiety to the material has been reduced, the pedophile can convince him to participate and be photographed. The child, after having seen ‘all the other kids do it’ and being reassured by a trusted adult friend, will participate in sexual conduct with the pedophile. The pedophile needs the child pornography * * * to facilitate the seduction of other children.”19 Child pornography, with the same techniques, is also used to induce children into child prostitution.20 Consequently, child pornography is a gravely harmful instrumentality.
Laws banning production and distribution are insufficient to halt this abuse of children. “ ‘The act of selling these materials is guaranteeing that there will be additional abuse of children.’ ” Ferber, supra, at 761, fn. 13. It is not enough to pursue the producers and distributors since most of their activities have been forced underground. See id. at 760, fn. 11.
Most readily apparent is that the Ohio statute is not at all concerned with the effect of child pornography, as visual stimulus, on the possessor. Furthermore, it is irrelevant whether society is offended by the idea so transmitted, for the written word is not the subject of this law. By comparison, the privacy interests set forth in Stanley, and acted upon in Ferber, are not nearly so weighty as the clear and present danger posed by the increased activity in child pornography production with its accompanying child molestation and rape.21 These are direct and perceivable harms which directly result from the ability to possess the depictions of such acts. This, I believe, is a significant and subordinating state interest sufficient to justify and uphold the constitutionality of the statute at issue under the standards announced in Stanley, supra, and Ferber, supra.
Locher, J., concurs in the foregoing concurring opinion.A consistent view was set forth by Judge Herbert of this court in State v. Mapp (1960), 170 Ohio St. 427 [11 O.O.2d 169], reversed in Mapp v. Ohio (1961), 367 U.S. 643 [16 O.O.2d 384], Nine years before the Supreme Court’s decision in Stanley, Judge Herbert prophetically dissented as follows in Mapp:
- “It is a basic principle that laws restraining the fundamental liberties of the individual must have as their foundation a broad basic public need which overshadows the rights of the individual. While we agree that the dissemination of obscene literature such as that produced in evidence in the present case is and should be against public morals and policy if for no other reason than that the immature mind which might be exposed to it could be greatly harmed, I cannot agree that mere private possession of such literature by an adult should constitute a crime. The right of the individual to read, to believe or disbelieve, and to think without governmental supervision is one of our basic liberties, but to dictate to the mature adult what books he may have in his own private library seems to the writer to be a clear infringement of his constitutional rights as an individual. Does the state have the power to prohibit the possession of chemistry books because from such books one might learn how to make a bomb or poisonous gas? Is the possession of medical books by a layman to be banned because of the possibility that he might learn about abortion and perhaps put such knowledge to use?” Id. at 437.
See, also, Part I of Justice Harlan’s dissenting opinion in Mapp v. Ohio, supra, at 672-677, and Justice Stewart’s memorandum at 682.
In our view, the utterly loathsome nature of this material, standing alone, would not provide justification for the state’s incursion in this case. The question of whether this criminal statute is unconstitutional does not depend simply on the categorization of this material as child pornography as opposed to obscene material involving adults. The nature of the material was not the point in Stanley. The point was the nature of the First Amendment right to freedom of thought in the privacy of one’s home which outweighed Georgia’s interest in protecting the viewer. As Justice Harlan stated in his concurrence in United States v. Reidel, supra, at 360, Stanley preserves the fundamental “right to a protective zone ensuring the freedom of a man’s inner life, be it rich or sordid.” Our task today is to balance this important First Amendment freedom with the state’s admitted interest of protecting its children from the shocking injuries caused by the sexual abuse of children which the state insists will occur if possession of child pornography is countenanced by the law.
A number of other lower court decisions are of guidance but do not involve the mere private possession of child pornography in the home. For example, in People v. Spargo (1982), 103 Ill. App. 3d 280, 431 N.E. 2d 27, the defendant was convicted of exhibiting child pornography to another. Spargo had showed pictures of nude boys to an undercover policeman while they were seated in Spargo’s car. Spargo contended that, pursuant to Stanley, the state could not punish private non-commercial dissemination or exhibition of child pornography. The court rejected this contention in stating at 285 that “whatever constitutional protections *48Stanley confers were relinquished by * * * [Spargo] when he removed the child pornography from the confines of his own home and exhibited it to another.” The court also noted at 284 that the Supreme Court cases were “consistent in their interpretation of Stanley as protective only of the right to possess obscene material in one’s own home.” (Emphasis added.)
Similarly, in People v. Godek (1982), 113 Misc. 2d 599, 449 N.Y. Supp. 2d 428, defendant was charged with promoting an obscene sexual performance by a child. In this case the defendant brought with him to a hotel room some of the items in his own collection of child pornography material in order to give it to another, who turned out to be a customs inspector. The court found Stanley inapplicable to protect the defendant, who was promoting this material outside his home. The court stated that such private exchanges of child pornography outside the home were not shielded by Stanley. See, also, United States v. Hale (C.A. 9, 1986), 784 F. 2d 1465.
A somewhat closer scenario was presented by the recent case of United States v. Miller (C.A. 11, 1985), 776 F. 2d 978, certiorari denied (1986), _ U.S. _, 90 L. Ed. 2d 201. In Miller the defendant ordered a booklet from Europe which depicted children engaged in sexual conduct. He picked it up at his post office box and then took it home. He was thereafter arrested and convicted under a federal statute which outlaws the knowing receipt of child pornography through the mail. Miller contended that, under Stanley, he had a right to receive such pornography for his own use. Again, this contention was rejected on grounds that Stanley was strictly limited to the mere private possession of such material in the defendant’s own home. Since Miller was outside his home when he received the pornography, the court distinguished Stanley and upheld his conviction, noting at 981 that the crime was complete before the material ever reached the defendant’s home.
Consistent with the foregoing, it can be safely said that the state may permissibly criminalize the promotion, production, preparation, distribution, sale, exchange, delivery, dissemination or exhibition to others (for commercial or non-commercial purposes) of child pornography. The government may further punish the knowing receipt of such material through the mail. Stanley draws a line, at the front door of the home, and holds that the state may not constitutionally cross that line to outlaw the mere private possession of obscene matter without showing an intent to distribute it to others unless other compelling state interests, not advanced in Stanley, justify the intrusion. The unanswered question squarely presented by the instant cause is whether the state may cross the threshold when possession of child pornography is criminalized.
Chayes, The Supreme Court, 1981 Term (1982), 96 Harv. L. Rev. 4, 141 et seq.
The Ferber court at 758, fn. 9, explained, inter alia, as follows:
It is significant that the purposes behind the obscenity doctrine bear no connection to the tragic injuries resulting from child pornography. The Ferber court at 759, fn. 10, noted as follows:
“* * * As one authority has explained:
“ ‘[P]ornography poses an even greater threat to the child victim than does sexual abuse or prostitution. Because the child’s actions are reduced to a recording, the pornography may haunt him in future years, long after the original misdeed took place. A child who has posed for a camera must go through life knowing that the recording is circulating within the mass distribution system for child pornography.’ Shouvlin, Preventing the Sexual Exploitation of Children: A Model Act, 17 Wake Forest L. Rev. 535, 545 (1981).
“See also Child Exploitation 292 (‘[I]t is the fear of exposure and the tension of keeping the act secret that seem to have the most profound emotional repercussions’); Note, Protection of Children from Use in Pornography: Toward Constitutional and Enforceable Legislation, 12 U. Mich. J. Law Reform 295, 301 (1979) (hereafter cited as Use in Pornography) (interview with child psychiatrist) (‘The victim’s knowledge of publication of the visual material increases the emotional and psychic harm suffered by the child’).
“Thus, distribution of the material violates ‘the individual interest in avoiding disclosure of personal matters.’ Whalen v. Roe, 429 U.S. 589, 599 (1977). Respondent cannot undermine the force of the privacy interests involved here by looking to Cox Broadcasting Corp. v. Cohn, 420 U.S. 469 (1975), and Smith v. Daily Mail Publishing Co., 443 U.S. 97 (1979), cases protecting the right of newspapers to publish, respectively, the identity of a rape victim and a youth charged as a juvenile offender. Those cases only stand for the proposition that ‘if a newspaper lawfully obtains truthful information about a matter of public significance then state officials may not constitutionally punish publication, of the information, absent a need * * * of the highest order.’ Id., at 103.”
In this regard, the Ferber majority noted as follows at 762-763:
“We consider it unlikely that visual depictions of children performing sexual acts or lewdly exhibiting their genitals would often constitute an important and necessary part of a literary performance or scientific or educational work. As a state judge in this case observed, if it were necessary for literary or artistic value, a person over the statutory age who perhaps *51looked younger could be utilized. Simulation outside of the prohibition of the statute could provide another alternative. Nor is there any question here of censoring a particular literary theme or portrayal of sexual activity. The First Amendment interest is limited to that of rendering the portrayal somewhat more ‘realistic’ by utilizing or photographing children.”
A number of our sister states have enacted comparable provisions. For example, as a result of studies conducted by the state of Florida’s Child Care Task Force, eight bills targeted at physical and sexual abuse of children became law, including a bill “which deals with child pornography and provides penalties for possession of certain items.” Comment, (1985), 13 Fla. St. U.L. Rev. 633, 634, at fn. 10.
Fla. Stat. Section 827.071(5), effective October 1, 1985, provides as follows:
“It is unlawful for any person to knowingly possess any photograph, motion picture, exhibition, show, representation, or other presentation which, in whole or in part, he knows to include any sexual conduct by a child. Whoever violates this subsection is guilty of a felony of the third degree * *
See, also, e.g., Ala. Code Section 13A-12-192(b) which provides as follows:
“Any person who knowingly possesses any obscene matter containing a visual reproduction of a person under the age of 17 years engaged in any act of sado-masochistic abuse, sexual intercourse, sexual excitement, masturbation, genital nudity, or other sexual conduct shall be guilty of a Class C felony.”
Similarly, 111. Stat., Ch. 38, Section ll-20.1(a) states:
“A person commits the offense of pornography who:
<<* * *
“(2) with the knowledge of the nature or content thereof, reproduces, disseminates, offers to disseminate, exhibits or possesses any film, videotape, photograph or other similar visual reproduction of any child whom the person knows or reasonably should know to be under the age of 18 engaged in [specified sexual activities] * * *.”
Cf. People v. Crowell (Ill. App. 1986), 495 N.E. 2d 1223, fn. 1 (Effective November 18, 1985, “[s]ection 11-20.1 has been amended extending child pornography protection to children under the age of 18 and adding possession of child pornography to the list of criminal conduct in paragraph [2].”). (Emphasis added.)
See, e.g., Comment, Karalexis v. Byrne and The Regulation of Obscenity: “I am Curious (Stanley)" (1970), 56 Va. L. Rev. 1205; Note, The Supreme Court, 1968 Term, Private Possession of Obscene Material (1969), 83 Harv. L. Rev. 147.
*53Comment, Still More Ado About Dirty Books (and Pictures): Stanley, Reidel, and Thirty-seven Photographs (1971), 81 Yale L.J. 309, 310 (hereinafter referred to as “More Ado”).
See, generally, Comment, Private Morality and The Right to Be Free: The Thrust of Stanley v. Georgia (1969), 11 Ariz. L. Rev. 731; Note, Constitutional Law — First Amendment: The New Metaphysics of the Law of Obscenity, Stanley v. Georgia (1969), 57 Cal. L. Rev. 1257.
Engdahl, Requiem for Roth: Obscenity Doctrine Is Changing (1969), 68 Mich. L. Rev. 185, 200 (hereinafter referred to as “Requiem”).
Requiem at 200-201.
More Ado, supra, at 329-331.
See, generally, Comment, First Amendment — Nonobscene Child Pornography and Its Categorical Exclusion From Constitutional Protection (1982), 73 J. of Crim. Law & Criminology 1337; Note, Constitutional Law — Child Pornography and the First Amendment: Abrogation of the Obscenity Doctrine in New York v. Ferber (1983), 16 Creighton L. Rev. 509.
Note, The Supreme Court, 1981 Term, Freedom of Speech and Association (1982), 96 Harv. L. Rev. 141, 143-144.
See, e.g., Shouvlin, Preventing the Sexual Exploitation of Children: A Model Act (1981), 17 Wake Forest L. Rev. 535 (hereinafter referred to as “Exploitation”); Note, Child Protection Act of 1984, Enforceable Legislation to Prevent Sexual Abuse of Children (1985), 10 Okla. City U. L. Rev. 121 (hereinafter referred to as “Child Protection”).
Child Protection, supra, at 133, fn. 60.
Id. at 133.
Id. See, also, Exploitation, supra, at 544.
Exploitation, supra, at 535.