RECOMMENDED FOR FULL-TEXT PUBLICATION
Pursuant to Sixth Circuit I.O.P. 32.1(b)
File Name: 13a0129p.06
UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT
_________________
X
-
IVY BAILEY, et al.,
-
Plaintiffs-Appellees,
-
-
No. 12-1803
v.
,
>
-
-
EDWARD CALLAGHAN; CHRISTINE
Defendants-Appellants. N-
DERDARIAN; NINO GREEN,
Appeal from the United States District Court
for the Eastern District of Michigan at Detroit.
No. 2:12-cv-11504—Denise Page Hood, District Judge.
Argued: March 6, 2013
Decided and Filed: May 9, 2013
Before: GIBBONS, KETHLEDGE, and STRANCH, Circuit Judges.
_________________
COUNSEL
ARGUED: Debbie K. Taylor, OFFICE OF THE MICHIGAN ATTORNEY GENERAL,
Detroit, Michigan, for Appellants. Philip Hostak, NATIONAL EDUCATION
ASSOCIATION, Washington, D.C., for Appellees. ON BRIEF: Debbie K. Taylor,
William F. Denner, Susan Przekop-Shaw, OFFICE OF THE MICHIGAN ATTORNEY
GENERAL, Detroit, Michigan, for Appellants. Philip Hostak, NATIONAL
EDUCATION ASSOCIATION, Washington, D.C., Arthur R. Przybylowicz,
MICHIGAN EDUCATION ASSOCIATION, East Lansing, Michigan, Andrew
Nickelhoff, SACHS WALDMAN, P.C., Detroit, Michigan, Mark H. Cousens,
Southfield, Michigan, Herbert A. Sanders, THE SANDERS LAW FIRM, P.C., Detroit,
Michigan, for Appellees.
KETHLEDGE, J., delivered the opinion of the court in which GIBBONS, J.,
joined. STRANCH, J. (pp. 7–20), delivered a separate dissenting opinion.
1
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 2
_________________
OPINION
_________________
KETHLEDGE, Circuit Judge. This case presents the question whether the
federal Constitution compels Michigan’s public schools to collect membership dues for
unions that represent public-school employees. Enacted in 2012, Michigan’s Public Act
53 provides: “A public school employer’s use of public school resources to assist a
labor organization in collecting dues or service fees from wages of public school
employees is a prohibited contribution to the administration of a labor organization.”
Thus, under the Act, unions must collect their own membership dues from public-school
employees, rather than have the schools collect those dues for them via payroll
deductions. The Act does not bar public employers other than schools from collecting
membership dues for unions who represent their employees.
The plaintiffs here are a number of unions and union members who think that
Public Act 53 violates their rights under the First Amendment and the Equal Protection
Clause. The district court was inclined to agree with them, and thus entered a
preliminary injunction barring enforcement of the Act. The State appealed.
We measure the validity of the district court’s injunction by reference to four
criteria:
(1) whether the movant has a strong likelihood of success on the merits;
[(2)] whether the movant would suffer irreparable injury without the
injunction; (3) whether issuance of the injunction would cause substantial
harm to others; and (4) whether the public interest would be served by
the issuance of the injunction.
Hunter v. Hamilton Cnty. Bd. of Elections, 635 F.3d 219, 233 (6th Cir. 2011). “When
a party seeks a preliminary injunction on the basis of a potential constitutional violation,
the likelihood of success on the merits will often be the determinative factor.” Obama
for Am. v. Husted, 697 F.3d 423, 436 (6th Cir. 2012) (internal quotation marks omitted).
The likelihood-of-success factor is determinative here; and because that factor presents
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 3
a question of law, we review the district court’s application of it de novo. See Bays v.
City of Fairborn, 668 F.3d 814, 819 (6th Cir. 2012).
The plaintiffs challenge Public Act 53 facially rather than as applied, which
means “they confront a heavy burden in advancing their claim.” Nat’l Endowment for
the Arts v. Finley, 524 U.S. 569, 580 (1998) (internal quotation marks omitted). The
theory behind their First Amendment claim runs as follows: unions engage in speech
(among many other activities); they need membership dues to engage in speech; if the
public schools do not collect the unions’ membership dues for them, the unions will have
a hard time collecting the dues themselves; and thus Public Act 53 violates the unions’
right to free speech.
The problem with this theory is that the Supreme Court has already rejected it.
“The First Amendment prohibits government from ‘abridging the freedom of speech’;
it does not confer an affirmative right to use government payroll mechanisms for the
purpose of obtaining funds for expression.” Ysursa v. Pocatello Educ. Ass’n, 555 U.S.
353, 355 (2009). Here, Public Act 53 does not restrict the unions’ speech at all: they
remain free to speak about whatever they wish. Moreover, “nothing in the First
Amendment prevents a State from determining that its political subdivisions may not
provide payroll deductions” for union activities, id.; and payroll deductions are all that
Public Act 53 denies the unions here. Seldom is precedent more binding than Ysursa is
in this case.
But the plaintiffs try to circumvent Ysursa in two ways. First, citing the Court’s
decision in Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense & Educational Fund, Inc., 473 U.S. 788
(1985), the plaintiffs say that the schools’ payroll-deduction process is a “nonpublic
forum,” from which the unions cannot be excluded. But forums, real or virtual, are
places where “some form of communicative activity occurs.” Perry Educ. Ass’n v. Perry
Local Educators’ Ass’n, 460 U.S. 37, 44 (1983). And not even the plaintiffs allege that
a payroll deduction—the ministerial act of deducting a particular sum from an
employee’s paycheck—is itself expressive activity. The administrative process in which
that deduction occurs, therefore, is not a forum of any kind. Compare Am. Freedom Def.
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 4
Initiative v. Suburban Mobility Auth. for Reg’l Transp., 698 F.3d 885, 892 (6th Cir.
2012) (advertisement space on a city bus was a nonpublic forum).
Cornelius only illustrates what is missing from this case. Cornelius involved a
challenge to the exclusion of certain groups from the federal government’s Combined
Federal Campaign, through which nonprofit groups solicited donations from federal
employees. Groups participating in the Campaign were allowed to disseminate 30-word
written statements about their cause. If an employee decided to donate through the
Campaign, the donation could be made through a lump-sum payment or through payroll
deductions. But nobody in Cornelius argued that the payroll deductions were speech;
the issue was whether the 30-word solicitations were. See 473 U.S. at 797. Indeed, the
Court said at the outset of its analysis that, if the 30-word solicitations were not speech,
“we need go no further.” Id. at 797. Ysursa makes clear that payroll deductions are not
speech, so we need go no further with the argument here. (That Public Act 53 does not
restrict speech distinguishes this case from every one of the cases relied upon by the
dissent.)
The plaintiffs also assert that Public Act 53 is viewpoint-discriminatory in a way
that the statute in Ysursa was not. There, the challenged statute applied to unions across
the board, whereas here, the plaintiffs say, Public Act 53 applies only to unions that
represent public-school employees. But there are several problems with this argument.
The first—even if one assumes that viewpoint discrimination would be problematic with
respect to payroll deductions—is that Public Act 53 by its terms does not discriminate
based upon viewpoint. It does not, for example, grant certain unions access to the
payroll-deduction process, and deny access to others, based upon whether a union
supports or opposes a particular policy position. To the contrary, the Act says nothing
about speech of any kind. The Act is therefore facially neutral as to viewpoint, which
goes a long ways towards defeating the plaintiffs’ facial challenge. Accord Wis. Educ.
Ass’n Council v. Walker, 705 F.3d 640, 648 (7th Cir. 2013).
The plaintiffs respond that the Act denies access to the payroll-deduction process
based upon who the speaker is—i.e., it denies access to certain unions—which the
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 5
plaintiffs say is a proxy for viewpoint discrimination. But again the contention is belied
by the Act’s terms. The Act does not deny payroll-access to particular unions. (Quite
the contrary: the State almost certainly continues to collect membership dues for a
number of the plaintiff-unions here—e.g., local chapters of AFSCME and the Service
Employees International Union—albeit from employees in agencies other than public
schools.) Instead, Public Act 53 bars public-school employers from using their resources
to collect membership dues on behalf of any union. The particular union to which an
employee belongs, therefore, is irrelevant to whether a public employer can collect the
employee’s membership dues. What matters, instead, is who the employer is. And
thus—even if one accepts the plaintiffs’ speaker-as-proxy-for-viewpoint theory—the Act
is as neutral to speaker identity as it is to viewpoint.
What the plaintiffs are left with, then, is an argument that we should look past the
Act’s facial neutrality as to viewpoint and union identity, and conclude nonetheless that
the Act’s real purpose is to suppress speech by teachers’ unions. But the law forecloses
this kind of adventure. In another speech case, the Supreme Court said: “It is a familiar
principle of constitutional law that this Court will not strike down an otherwise
constitutional statute on the basis of an alleged illicit legislative motive.” United States
v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 383 (1968). That principle binds us here; and thus, like the
Seventh Circuit in a virtually identical case, we will not “peer[] past” the text of Public
Act 53 “to infer some invidious legislative intention.” Walker, 705 F.3d at 649–50.
So Public Act 53 does not restrict speech; it does not discriminate against or even
mention viewpoint; and it has nothing to do with a forum of any kind. Instead, the Act
merely directs one kind of public employer to use its resources for its core mission rather
than for the collection of union dues. That is not a First Amendment concern. See
Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Washington, 461 U.S. 540, 546 (1981) (“We
again reject the notion that First Amendment rights are somehow not fully realized
unless they are subsidized by the State”) (internal quotation marks omitted).
Only the plaintiffs’ equal-protection claim remains. “[A] classification neither
involving fundamental rights nor proceeding along suspect lines is accorded a strong
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 6
presumption of validity.” Heller v. Doe, 509 U.S. 312, 319 (1993). Such a classification
is constitutional “so long as it bears a rational relation to some legitimate end.” Vacco
v. Quill, 521 U.S. 793, 799 (1997) (internal quotation marks omitted). This test is highly
deferential: “any conceivable legitimate governmental interest will do; and even then it
is constitutionally irrelevant whether the conceivable interest actually underlay the
enactment of the challenged provision.” Fednav, Ltd. v. Chester, 547 F.3d 607, 624–25
(6th Cir. 2008) (emphasis in original) (citations, brackets, and internal quotation marks
omitted).
The applicability of rational-basis review is a strong signal that the issue is one
for resolution by the democratic process rather than by the courts. This case is no
exception. Public Act 53 proscribes the “use of public school resources” for collection
of union dues, but does not bar other state or local employers from using their resources
for that same purpose. See Mich. Comp. Laws § 423.210(1)(b). The question here is
whether there is any conceivable legitimate interest in support of this classification. We
hold that there is: the Legislature could have concluded that it is more important for the
public schools to conserve their limited resources for their core mission than it is for
other state and local employers. The plaintiffs’ equal-protection claim therefore fails.
We hold that the plaintiffs’ claims under the First Amendment and the Equal
Protection Clause are both without merit. The plaintiffs therefore have no chance of
success on those claims, which means the injunction should not have issued.
The district court’s June 11, 2012 order granting the plaintiffs’ motion for a
preliminary injunction is reversed, and the case remanded for further proceedings
consistent with this opinion.
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 7
__________________
DISSENT
__________________
STRANCH, Circuit Judge, dissenting. The majority spills little ink in its
dismissal of the school unions’ free-speech challenge. In doing so, it mischaracterizes
the First Amendment interests at stake, glosses over key distinctions the Supreme Court
requires us to observe, and averts its gaze from Act 53’s blatant viewpoint
discrimination. Most concerning to me, however, is the majority’s refusal to engage in
an analysis of viewpoint discrimination in light of Michigan’s explicit statement that the
law’s purpose is to put a “check on union power.” The foundational requirement of
viewpoint neutrality means little if a state may legislate with impunity to cripple the
power of an unpopular group whose political views are objectionable to the state. The
unanswered constitutional question in this case is whether the government may burden
expression it disagrees with by selectively restricting access to public resources that
facilitate that expression. The answer is no. The majority wrongly concludes otherwise.
I. Background
A fuller description of the context in which this dispute arises is needed.
Plaintiffs here are unions that represent school-district employees, including teachers and
support personnel, in Michigan’s public schools. Like other unions, the school unions
represent their members’ interests at the bargaining table. But because issues in public-
school workplaces depend so heavily on legislative policy choices, they also engage in
political action and public-advocacy efforts. The school unions fund their work through
membership dues and service fees that teachers are contractually obligated to pay to
share in the costs of supporting their organizations.1
1
Technically, union members pay dues and “non-members” pay fees. The latter are individuals
in the bargaining unit who receive the benefits the union negotiates but decline full membership in the
organization. See Mich. Comp. Laws § 423.210(2). The distinction is not important to this case, so I use
the term “dues” to refer to both dues and fees, and “members” to refer to both members and non-members.
Also, although the school unions represent several types of employees, I call them “teachers” for ease.
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 8
Teachers pay dues by remitting small amounts of money on a regular basis. The
transaction costs involved in collecting dues from tens of thousands of individuals every
month or two can be great. So the school unions have negotiated provisions in their
contracts with school districts to allow teachers to choose to have their dues deducted
directly from their paychecks and transmitted to their unions. A teacher’s dues
deduction choice is just one part—or, more accurately, just one database field—in a
school district’s payroll-deduction system that is used to remit voluntary payments to
many organizations, including charities, insurance carriers, retirement plans, and
financial-investment institutions.
For teachers, payroll deduction is a convenience akin to the auto-pay option
many banks offer customers to pay recurring bills. For school districts, the costs
associated with directing funds to the school unions via the automated payroll system
are minimal or, where reimbursed by school unions, nonexistent. And for school unions,
payroll deduction enables them to devote their resources to core functions—political
action, collective bargaining, and member representation—rather than collections work.
Michigan’s Public Employment Relations Act (PERA) has regulated collective
bargaining between governmental employers and public-employee unions since 1966.
See Public Act 379 of 1965, codified as amended at Mich. Comp. Laws
§§ 423.201–423.217. PERA covers a wide range of employees besides teachers,
including municipal workers, police officers, firefighters, healthcare providers, and
higher-education employees. See Cent. Mich. Univ. Faculty Ass’n v. Cent. Mich. Univ.,
273 N.W.2d 21, 26 (Mich. 1978)). It restricts public employers and unions from
engaging in certain “unfair labor practices.” See Mich. Comp. Laws § 423.210.
Relevant here, Section 10(1)(b) makes it an unfair labor practice for public employers
to “[i]nitiate, create, dominate, contribute to, or interfere with the formation or
administration of any labor organization.” Id. § 423.210(1)(b). In the 46 years of its
existence, payroll deductions have never been thought to violate this provision.
Act 53 intended to change all of that. With its passage in March 2012,
Michigan’s legislature declared that “a public school employer’s use of public school
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 9
resources to assist a labor organization in collecting dues or service fees from the wages
of public school employees is a prohibited contribution to the administration of a labor
organization.” Id. Michigan explained that the statute would save money, promote
union accountability, and provide a “check on union power.”
Act 53 affects only unions that represent school employees. Unions whose
members work for any other PERA-regulated public employer remain free to collect
dues using public-payroll systems. So the school unions filed suit, alleging that Act 53’s
selective ban violates the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, and
discriminates against disfavored speakers in violation of the First Amendment. The
district court granted the preliminary injunction they sought to bar Act 53’s
implementation. It reasoned that Act 53 “necessarily diminishes” the school unions’
ability to fund expressive speech, and so cuts into a protected speech interest. And it
concluded that the rationales the state advanced for this underinclusive law did not
answer the charge that Michigan targeted school unions because of its disagreement with
their viewpoint.
I, too, think the school unions’ First Amendment challenge can succeed. Here
is why.
II. Ysursa does not control
From the start, the majority veers off course in its insistence that the Supreme
Court has already rejected the school unions’ First Amendment theory. See Maj. Op. at
3. Ysursa v. Pocatello Education Association, 555 U.S. 353 (2009), which the majority
believes resolves this matter, concerned a First Amendment challenge to Idaho’s ban on
payroll deductions for political activities. In it, the Court held that the First Amendment
“does not confer an affirmative right to use government payroll mechanisms for the
purpose of obtaining funds for expression.” Id. at 355. “Idaho’s law does not restrict
political speech, but rather declines to promote that speech by allowing public employee
checkoffs for political activities.” Id.
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 10
Two observations were integral to the Court’s resolution of the case. First,
Idaho’s law applies to all deductions for political activities, not just a disfavored few. Id.
at 361 n.3. Second, there was no suggestion that the law is “aim[ed] at the suppression
of dangerous ideas.” Id. at 359 (internal quotation marks omitted); in other words, the
law does not impermissibly discriminate on the basis of viewpoint.2 The Court
concluded that Idaho’s ban does not infringe the First Amendment and only requires the
state to “demonstrate a rational basis to justify” it. Id.; but see id. at 361 n.3 (noting that
a First Amendment challenge could be brought to Idaho’s evenhanded ban if it were not
enforced evenhandedly).
Little controversy, then, surrounds Ysursa’s holding that the Constitution does
not require a state to facilitate all union speech by providing for universal payroll
deductions, or to decline to do so for all—evenhandedness is the operative requirement.
But Ysursa does not answer what happens when an enactment evades this requirement.
And that, of course, is the question before us—whether Michigan’s choice to exclude
just one subset of unions from the speech-facilitating mechanism of payroll deduction
violates the First Amendment.
In such a case, Ysursa teaches that restrictions based on an excluded party’s
disfavored viewpoint can infringe the First Amendment. To Justice Breyer’s concern
that Idaho’s ban might be applied inequitably, the Ysursa majority reiterated that the law
“by its terms” applies across-the-board, prohibiting “all employers” from using the
payroll-deduction system to remit funds to all political organizations for all political
issues, “regardless of viewpoint or message.” Id. at 361 n.3. But if “the ban is not
2
The Supreme Court uses the phrase “aim[ed] at the suppression of dangerous ideas,” 555 U.S.
at 359, interchangeably with the term “viewpoint discrimination,” as well as other formulations in the
government-subsidy context. See, e.g., Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819,
834 (1995) (“Although acknowledging that the Government is not required to subsidize the exercise of
fundamental rights, we reaffirmed the requirement of viewpoint neutrality in the Government’s provision
of financial benefits by observing that the case would be different if Congress were to discriminate
invidiously in its subsidies in such a way as to aim at the suppression of dangerous ideas.”) (internal
quotation marks, alterations, and citation omitted); Nat’l Endowment for the Arts v. Finley, 524 U.S. 569,
587 (1998) (noting the Court’s prior formulations of “invidious viewpoint discrimination” in the provision
of subsidies that “raises concern about the suppression of disfavored viewpoints” include a government’s
“leverag[ing] its power to award subsidies on the basis of subjective criteria into a penalty on disfavored
viewpoints”; “aim[ing] at the suppression of dangerous ideas”; “manipulat[ing]” subsidies to have a
“coercive effect”; and “impos[ing] . . . a disproportionate burden calculated to drive certain ideas or
viewpoints from the marketplace”) (internal quotation marks omitted).
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 11
enforced evenhandedly,” the Court allowed, plaintiffs could “bring an as-applied
challenge.”3 Id. As the parties in Ysursa agreed that no viewpoint discrimination was
afoot, the Court had no occasion to apply this principle. Id.
Thus, the majority’s conclusion here that precedent is “[s]eldom . . . more
binding than Ysursa is in this case,” Maj. Op. at 3, is true only to the extent that Ysursa
expressly acknowledges the long-standing prohibition on viewpoint discrimination in
the provision of government subsidies, while recognizing its inapplicability in that case.
But Ysursa does not control analysis of a law that selectively prohibits access to payroll
deductions to one group—school unions—allegedly to stifle expression of their
disfavored viewpoint, but permits it to every other PERA-regulated union. The First
Amendment interests here are clearly different than in Ysursa, where the parties agreed
that there was no viewpoint-discrimination claim. And, more, the school unions’
allegation that Act 53 seeks to suppress their political viewpoint is precisely the kind of
claim of impermissible discrimination we are duty-bound to scrutinize. The majority
ignores this fundamental distinction, and mistakenly concludes that hidden viewpoint
discrimination that may inhere in a selective payroll-deduction ban is not a First
Amendment concern. I disagree.
Before addressing whether Act 53 is or is not impermissibly discriminatory, the
viewpoint-neutrality requirement as understood in our circuit must be explained.
III. Viewpoint neutrality
I begin with the basics of the viewpoint-neutrality requirement. The government
may violate the First Amendment if it regulates speech based on its substantive content
or the message it conveys. Police Dep’t of Chi. v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 96 (1972). But
when it suppresses “particular views . . . on a subject,” the violation is “all the more
blatant.” Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 829 (1995).
3
Ysursa’s conclusion that a party may bring a First Amendment challenge to a law that selectively
bars access to payroll deductions, allegedly on the basis of viewpoint, should resolve the majority’s doubts
that the viewpoint-neutrality requirement applies in this context. See Maj. Op at 4 (“even if one assumes
that viewpoint discrimination would be problematic with respect to payroll deductions”).
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 12
Such viewpoint discrimination occurs when the government restricts speech because of
“the specific motivating ideology or the opinion or perspective of the speaker,” id., or
“solely to suppress the point of view he espouses,” Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Def. &
Educ. Fund, Inc., 473 U.S. 788, 806 (1985).
Sometimes viewpoint discrimination is obvious. If, for example, the government
permits anti-war speakers to protest in a public building, but prohibits pro-war speakers
from doing the same, few would deny the viewpoint-based discrimination in that
scenario. Often, though, the issue is more nuanced because many debatable public
issues do not reduce to a simple “pro” and “con” dichotomy. Recognizing this, the
Supreme Court has rejected the “insupportable assumption that all debate is bipolar.”
Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 831 (“Our understanding of the complex and multifaceted
nature of public discourse has not embraced such a contrived description of the
marketplace of ideas.”). Instead, the Court’s capacious conception of viewpoint requires
sensitivity to the danger that speech restrictions may skew the contest of ideas. See id.
at 832.
The prohibition on viewpoint discrimination operates as a check on the
government’s ability to prefer one point of view over others on the same topic. It serves
to snuff out official actions calculated to drive “certain ideas or viewpoints from the
marketplace.” Simon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N.Y. State Crime Victims Bd., 502
U.S. 105, 116 (1991). And it applies both when the government selectively restricts
speech, see, e.g., Brown v. Entm’t Merchs. Ass’n, 131 S. Ct. 2729, 2740 (2011), and
when it selectively facilitates it, see, e.g., Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 834 (government
“may not discriminate based on the viewpoint of private persons whose speech it
facilitates”). Of course, the government has no obligation to promote the expressive
activities of private actors. But when it does so on behalf of those who advance a
favored political, ideological, or philosophical perspective, its denial of the same
promotion to others who advance a disfavored view comes at the cost of raising a
suspicion of viewpoint discrimination.
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 13
The majority observes that Act 53 is “facially neutral as to viewpoint, which goes
a long ways towards defeating the plaintiffs’ facial challenge.” Maj. Op. at 4. But the
facial neutrality of a speech regulation does not resolve its legitimacy. We have never
been so naive as to expect the government to admit it is engaging in viewpoint
discrimination. And so our precedents have long recognized the possibility of hidden
viewpoint discrimination. Even when a justification for a speech restriction is facially
neutral, “the government nevertheless violates the First Amendment when its stated
purpose in reality conceals a bias against the viewpoint advanced by the excluded
speakers.” United Food & Commercial Workers Union, Local 1099 v. Sw. Ohio Reg’l
Transit Auth., 163 F.3d 341, 355–56 (6th Cir. 1998) (citing Cornelius, 473 U.S. at 811).
Moreover, it is the court’s duty to ferret out hidden viewpoint bias by
“independent[ly] determin[ing] . . . whether the government’s rules and [their]
application . . . are reasonably related to the government’s policy objectives.” Id. at 357.
We can fulfill this duty only if we assure that the state proves “the links in its chain of
reasoning.” Id. (internal quotation marks omitted).
How does a court accomplish its task? Precedent suggests at least three attributes
of a law impacting speech that can help us identify whether a seemingly neutral
justification masks impermissible viewpoint exclusion. First, “the underinclusiveness
of a law—i.e., the failure of the government to regulate other, similar activity—may give
rise to a conclusion that the government has in fact made an impermissible distinction
on the basis of the content of the regulated speech.” DLS, Inc. v. City of Chattanooga,
107 F.3d 403, 411 (6th Cir. 1997). “Underinclusiveness raises serious doubts about
whether the government is in fact pursuing the interest it invokes, rather than disfavoring
a particular speaker or viewpoint.” Brown, 131 S. Ct. at 2740.
Second, official statements and actions justifying a viewpoint-neutral enactment
may evidence a facade for viewpoint-based discrimination. As every law student
quickly learns, and the majority points out, courts do not simply “strike down an
otherwise constitutional statute on the basis of an alleged illicit legislative motive.”
United States v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. 367, 383 (1968). But the Supreme Court has made
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 14
clear that we may examine motive when considering speech restrictions that allegedly
discriminate on the basis of viewpoint. In Cornelius, for example—a case in which the
plaintiffs’ allegation of viewpoint discrimination was not decided by the district court
or fully briefed before the Supreme Court—the Court remanded the case in part for the
district court to decide whether the contested regulation was “impermissibly motivated
by a desire to suppress a particular point of view.” 473 U.S. at 812–13. And in Perry
Education Association v. Perry Local Educators’ Association, 460 U.S. 37, 49 n.9
(1983), another case in which viewpoint discrimination was alleged, the Court scoured
the record before finding “no indication . . . that the policy was motivated by a desire to
suppress” the excluded group’s views.
Third, suspicion of hostility to a particular viewpoint arises if a speech restriction
poorly serves the viewpoint-neutral ground; “where, in other words, the fit between
means and ends is loose or nonexistent.” Ridley v. Mass. Bay Transp. Auth., 390 F.3d
65, 87 (1st Cir. 2004); see also Elena Kagan, Private Speech, Public Purpose: The Role
of Governmental Motive in First Amendment Doctrine, 63 U. Chi. L. Rev. 413, 455
(1996) (“[T]he looser the fit between the interest asserted and the contours of the law,
the greater the cause for suspicion. . . . [W]hen the asserted interest is insubstantial or
when it does not fit the scope of the challenged regulation[,] the usual presumption of
proper purpose topples[.]”).
The majority refuses to “look past the Act’s facial neutrality” because it believes
“the law forecloses this kind of adventure.” Maj. Op. at 5. But applying our precedents
is hardly a foray into adventure. And we cannot close our eyes when those precedents
instruct us to determine whether viewpoint discrimination hides behind a facially neutral
law. At a minimum, this means putting the state through its paces by assessing its
justifications for Act 53’s selective ban. I understand this examination to be our
obligation.
Against this backdrop, I turn to whether Act 53 is, in fact, viewpoint neutral.
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 15
IV. Act 53 discriminates on the basis of viewpoint
While Act 53 is facially neutral as to viewpoint, it impermissibly discriminates
against school unions because Michigan disagrees with the positions they advocate.
School unions have a particular viewpoint that Act 53 seeks to muzzle. They are large
and well-funded advocacy organizations that actively push for spending allocations and
legislative enactments that other PERA-regulated unions do not share—and, in fact,
often oppose when it comes to deciding how to split the pie of finite public resources.
The priorities of unions representing firefighters, transit workers, or hospital employees,
for example, do not include increasing school funding or safeguarding teacher-tenure
protections. The school unions’ colorable theory is that the state’s distaste for the pro-
teacher viewpoint they strongly and consistently espouse in funding and legislative
debates led Michigan to enact Act 53 to mute their voice.
The majority refuses to acknowledge that school unions have a particular
viewpoint, and that Act 53’s burden falls only on speakers who advance that viewpoint.
Instead, it concludes the law is neutral as to the identity of a union, as it regulates only
the ability of certain public employers (school districts) to collect dues on behalf of any
union. Maj. Op. at 5. This argument begs the question. The identity of the entity the
law regulates does not define the identity of the entity on whom its burden falls. Imagine
a law that prohibited public-school employers from allowing anti-abortion organizations
to distribute literature on school grounds, but did not bar the employers from allowing
pro-abortion advocates to do the same. Observing that the rule only regulates what
certain public-school employers may do without reference to the speaker’s identity
would do nothing to quiet an anti-abortion organization’s claim of viewpoint
discrimination. Here, too, the fact that Act 53 technically regulates school districts does
not answer a charge that it functionally burdens the expression of a group of speakers
bound together by a single shared viewpoint.
We analyze the school unions’ claim of hidden viewpoint bias by “engag[ing]
in an independent determination of whether [Act 53] . . . [is] reasonably related to
[Michigan’s] policy objectives.” United Food, 163 F.3d at 357. An examination of the
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 16
three allegedly neutral justifications for Act 53 that Michigan offers—saving money,
promoting union accountability, and providing a “check on union power”—makes plain
that the state’s selective ban is not viewpoint neutral.
Michigan’s first justification is that Act 53 saves money spent administering a
payroll-deduction system. This justification suffers from three flaws as an explanation
for Michigan’s differential treatment of school unions. The first is that Michigan
“cannot justify viewpoint discrimination among private speakers on the economic fact
of scarcity.” Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 835. Instead, it must “ration or allocate
. . . scarce resources on some acceptable neutral principle.” Id. “[S]carcity [does not]
give the State the right to exercise viewpoint discrimination that is otherwise
impermissible.” Id.
The second is that this justification highlights the underinclusiveness of the law.
Michigan may deny all organizations access to its payroll-deduction system solely to
save the state money. But it cannot justify unequal access to this speech-facilitating
mechanism to a group that is indistinguishable from another group to whom access is
given. “When speakers and subjects are similarly situated, the state may not pick and
choose.” Perry, 460 U.S. at 55. Act 53’s underinclusiveness does not help to dispel an
allegation of viewpoint discrimination.
Finally, the cost-savings justification has a factual problem. Although Michigan
is not required to produce irrefutable proof, “mere conjecture [is] [in]adequate to carry
a First Amendment burden.” Nixon v. Shrink Mo. Gov’t PAC, 528 U.S. 377, 392 (2000).
The trouble is that Michigan’s nonpartisan House Fiscal Agency determined the bill
would have “no significant fiscal impact on school districts” because the deduction
process is largely automated and, in some cases, its costs are reimbursed by the school
unions. The district court also found Michigan failed to show that Act 53 would save
money. Given that Act 53 does not eliminate existing payroll-deduction systems, but
only removes the one field in a database that earmarks school union dues, the state’s
inability to substantiate its justification is unsurprising.
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 17
Michigan’s second justification for Act 53—that it enhances a union’s
accountability to its members—fares no better. The state reasons that if dues are not
deducted from teachers’ paychecks, unions will be forced to make affirmative efforts to
collect those funds, and union leaders will be more accountable to their members. The
accountability justification does not assure me that Act 53 is viewpoint neutral for two
reasons. The first, again, is its underinclusiveness. If not deducting dues from employee
paychecks conceivably makes unions more accountable—which is not at all clear—then
surely members of other PERA-regulated employers would similarly benefit from more
answerable organizations. Michigan’s failure to similarly promote the accountability of
those employees’ unions suggests that Act 53 targets teachers because the state disagrees
with their point of view.
Moreover, consider how specious the logic of the accountability justification is.
How exactly can teachers hold union leaders more accountable if they have to pay their
dues in person or by mail, rather than by payroll deduction? Michigan’s argument
ignores two key facts. First, whatever method teachers use to remit dues, they are still
obligated to pay them. If a credit card company no longer allows customers to pay their
bills by automatically deducting monthly payments from their checking accounts, its
customers still have to pay their bills. Michigan’s accountability rationale also is blind
to the fact that paying dues via payroll deduction is entirely voluntary. Only teachers
who choose to do so use it to pay dues. Eliminating one method by which a teacher can
elect to pay a bill does not make the organization she must pay it to any more
accountable.
Michigan’s third justification for Act 53 is that it puts a “check on union power.”
The school unions suggest that this justification is bound up with evidence they
presented to show that Act 53 was enacted in retaliation for the unions’ political
activities against the state’s Republican-controlled legislature. The Speaker of
Michigan’s House of Representatives, for example, told the press that the Michigan
Education Association had “declared war” by supporting the recall of backers of
legislation the unions opposed. And later, the leader of the state senate opined that the
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 18
union had “lost [its] way,” and that teachers “should no longer be forced to join” it.
Where, as here, “the speech restricted is speech critical of the government,” hidden
viewpoint discrimination plausibly lurks precisely because “there is a strong risk that the
government will act to censor ideas that oppose its own.” Ridley, 390 F.3d at 86 (citing
Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 411–17 (1989)).
The legislative proponents of Act 53 explained the check-on-union-power
justification in the following way. Without Act 53, they warned, “unsustainable public
employee benefits and compensation will continue to threaten the financial integrity of
[Michigan’s] public institutions.” The cause of this problem is that the management
team that negotiates with school unions is “often made up of elected officials, some of
whom have won their elected offices with the assistance—both personal and
financial—of public sector union members.” Thus compromised, the management team
“does not take a tough stance” on salaries and working conditions, leading to
compensation for teachers that increases “beyond the ability of taxpayers to pay.”
I see at least two problems with this justification. The obvious one is that this
rationale, like the others Michigan offers, is “wildly underinclusive.” Brown, 131 S. Ct.
at 2740. It invokes an oft-repeated criticism that presumably applies to all public-
employee unions, not just school unions. See, e.g., Jarrett Skorup, The Public
Employee Union Problem, Michigan Capitol Confidential, Jan. 12, 2013,
http://www.michigancapitolconfidential.com/13387 (last visited May 7, 2013).
The bigger problem is that this justification reveals what Michigan probably
hoped to hide behind the curtain. To take Michigan at its word is to recognize that Act
53 directly seeks to curtail the ability of school unions to support elected officials—and
so to interpose the state into the marketplace of ideas to silence one point of view over
others on the same topic. Query how it is that eliminating payroll deduction for school
unions alleviates the perceived conflict-of-interest that compromises a school employer’s
ability to negotiate “tough” contracts with teachers. Logically, the only way that
prohibiting payroll deductions can rein in compensation levels negotiated by elected
officials “beholden to union supporters” is to make them less beholden by reducing their
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 19
reliance on the school unions’ political support. And a prohibition on payroll deduction
can accomplish that only if it reduces the resources the school unions have to contribute
to elected officials. Instead of rebutting a charge of viewpoint discrimination, this
justification directly supports the school unions’ argument that Act 53 is an attempt to
silence their viewpoint.
To the extent Act 53’s purpose is to cripple the school unions’ ability to raise
funds for political speech because Michigan’s legislature finds that speech undesirable,
it is plainly impermissible. Political speech, of course, is a core First Amendment
activity that “must prevail against laws that would suppress it, whether by design or
inadvertence.” Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm’n, 130 S. Ct. 876, 898 (2010).
And “restrictions distinguishing among different speakers, allowing speech by some but
not others,” run afoul of the First Amendment precisely because they are “all too often
simply a means to control content.” Id. at 898–99.
This doctrinal prohibition applies not only to laws that directly burden speech,
but also to those that diminish the amount of speech by making it more difficult or
expensive to speak. See, e.g., Citizens United, 130 S. Ct. at 897 (noting that political-
action-committee exemption from a corporate-expenditure ban “does not alleviate the
[ban’s] First Amendment problems [because] . . . PACs are burdensome alternatives;
they are expensive to administer and subject to extensive regulations”); Meyer v. Grant,
486 U.S. 414, 424 (1988) (striking down on First Amendment grounds a Colorado law
that prohibited paying individuals to circulate petitions to qualify ballot initiatives
because it “restricts access to the most effective, fundamental, and perhaps economical
avenue of political discourse,” and observing that merely “leav[ing] open ‘more
burdensome’ avenues of communication[] does not relieve its burden on First
Amendment expression”).
Michigan minces few words explaining that it seeks to diminish the funds
available to the school unions to cut back on how much speaking they can do. The
state’s check-on-union-power rationale lays bare its desire to reduce the resources school
unions have to express their viewpoint because of Michigan’s aversion to what they have
No. 12-1803 Bailey, et al. v. Callaghan, et al. Page 20
to say. Like Michigan’s other justifications, this one provides no answer to the charge
that Act 53 is impermissibly “aimed at the suppression of dangerous ideas.” Ysursa,
555 U.S. at 359 (internal quotation marks and alteration omitted).
V. Conclusion
The school unions allege that Act 53 is a viewpoint-neutral restriction on its face
that is a facade for viewpoint-based discrimination in fact. A court’s job in such a
circumstance is to determine if the law is “impermissibly motivated by a desire to
suppress a particular point of view.” Cornelius, 473 U.S. at 812–13. This is
accomplished by combing the record and scrutinizing the viewpoint-neutral justifications
the state offers for the enactment. Doing so convinces me that Act 53 is motivated by
a desire to suppress the school unions’ viewpoint, and that Michigan cannot “prove the
links in its chain of reasoning” to dispel this claim. United Food, 163 F.3d at 357.
Based on a determination that the school unions’ First Amendment claim is likely to
succeed, and otherwise satisfies the requirements for a preliminary injunction, I would
affirm the district court’s order granting the preliminary injunction. Because I believe
that the majority’s refusal to engage in the analysis our precedents require has led it to
wrongly reverse that order, I respectfully dissent.