IN THE SUPREME COURT OF IOWA
No. 14–0455
Filed May 27, 2016
STATE OF IOWA,
Appellee,
vs.
ISAIAH RICHARD SWEET,
Appellant.
Appeal from the Iowa District Court for Delaware County,
Michael J. Shubatt, Judge.
A juvenile offender convicted of first-degree murder appeals from
the district court’s order sentencing him to life in prison without the
possibility of parole. DISTRICT COURT SENTENCE REVERSED AND
CASE REMANDED WITH INSTRUCTIONS.
Mark C. Smith, State Appellate Defender, and Shellie L. Knipfer,
Assistant Appellate Defender, for appellant.
Thomas J. Miller, Attorney General, Tyler J. Buller and Denise A.
Timmins, Assistant Attorneys General, and John Bernau, County
Attorney, for appellee.
2
APPEL, Justice.
In this case, we consider whether a juvenile who committed first-
degree murder may be committed to life in prison without the possibility
of parole, consistent with article I, section 17 of the Iowa Constitution.
After a sentencing hearing, the district court in this case sentenced the
defendant to life in prison without the possibility of parole. For the
reasons expressed below, we reverse and remand the case to the district
court for resentencing consistent with this opinion.
I. Factual and Procedural Background.
A. Overview of the Crime. On May 11, 2012, seventeen-year-old
Isaiah Sweet shot and killed Richard and Janet Sweet. Richard and
Janet had cared for Sweet since he was four years old, as his biological
mother was unable to do so. Richard was Sweet’s biological grandfather.
Richard and Janet had been married for thirty years.
Sweet was arrested three days after the murder. After being given
Miranda warnings, Sweet described events leading to the murders, the
details of the murders themselves, and his activities in the days after the
murders.
According to Sweet, Janet was dying of cancer. His grandfather,
he stated, “called [him] a piece of shit every night of [his] life and every
day.” Sweet contended, “[Richard] constantly told [him] to just kill
[himself] and fall off the earth” and “they treated [him] like shit.”
According to Sweet,
[he] tried so hard to help [his] grandma with everything, but
[his] grandpa made everything so hard because [he was]
always stressin’ [Sweet] out, would scream at [him] for no
reason and [he] didn’t know what to do anymore, so [he] just
snapped.
3
Sweet described events on the day of the murders. According to
Sweet, he retrieved an assault rifle he had taken from his grandparents’
room and loaded the rifle with hollow-point rounds because he knew that
they would do the most damage, but also because he did not want his
grandparents to go through any pain. He put on earmuffs to protect his
own hearing. He shot his grandfather in the head from behind because
he “hate[d] him [and because he] made [Sweet’s] life a living hell.” He
then shot his grandmother twice in the head. After he shot them, he
walked over to them and kissed them, told them he was sorry, and
prayed for forgiveness. Sweet stated he knew right away what he did was
wrong and he wanted to take it back.
After the murders, Sweet picked up a friend, and they went back to
the house. He took a sawed-off shotgun, a knife, the assault rifle, a TV,
some clothes, and nine dollars from his grandparents’ wallets and left the
house. Sweet then left the assault rifle and shotgun with some friends
and drove to Cedar Rapids where he “party hopped to like eight different
apartments” and engaged in drug transactions. Sweet told police that he
told a number of persons about the murders, including his former
girlfriend.
The next day, May 12, Sweet attended a birthday party for a
friend’s sister and then drove to Iowa City to “some big ass party.” After
the party, the police arrested Sweet for driving with a suspended license,
and the car was impounded. At the police station, Sweet told authorities
his grandparents were at the Mayo Clinic. Police allowed Sweet to call
his counselor, and Sweet was released to the counselor the following day.
Sweet thereafter continued his drug usage and spent the evening in a
tent in the woods. The next day, May 14, authorities arrested him after
spotting him at a Hardee’s restaurant.
4
B. Initial Legal Proceedings. The State charged Sweet with two
counts of first-degree murder. Sweet pled not guilty, and his case came
to trial in October 2013. At the conclusion of the State’s case, Sweet
reached a plea agreement with the State. Sweet agreed to plead guilty to
two counts of first-degree murder. The State agreed to recommend that
the sentences run concurrently. The State and Sweet agreed a
sentencing hearing would occur based on Sweet’s “age and the state of
[the] law.” Upon being informed of the plea agreement, the court engaged
Sweet in a colloquy in which Sweet stated that the witnesses would
truthfully testify to facts stated in the minutes of testimony. The district
court accepted the guilty plea and entered an order for a presentence
investigation (PSI) report to be prepared. In the order, the court noted
that the basis for the request was “the Iowa Supreme Court’s decisions in
Null, Pearson, and Ragland.”
C. PSI Report. Pursuant to the court’s order, a PSI report was
prepared by the department of correctional services. The PSI report
outlined the facts surrounding the crimes. The juvenile arrest history in
the PSI report included a curfew violation, possession of illegal drugs,
possession of drug paraphernalia, possession of alcohol under eighteen,
minor using tobacco, assault with intent to commit sexual abuse, and
operating a vehicle without consent.
With respect to his education, the PSI report indicated Sweet had
dropped out of high school in his junior year with a grade point average
of 1.061. The PSI report noted Sweet claimed he was “really intelligent”
but did not apply himself and was too busy with friends to worry about
grades. According to Sweet, he passed three of the GED pretests. He
planned to move to Pennsylvania when he turned eighteen and live with
5
his mother so he could attend Penn State University. The PSI report
indicated he had been suspended from school on numerous occasions.
The PSI report included an extended discussion of Sweet’s family
dynamics. Sweet’s parents, Stacy Sweet and Christopher Galli, never
married but were together for about five years. Stacy reported both she
and Christopher had histories of substance abuse, with Stacy admitting
to cocaine addiction. After Sweet was born, Stacy gave birth to another
child by Ronald Kempinski. Kempinski at one point left Stacy and took
the two children, thereafter leaving Sweet with Richard; however Stacy
stated she took Sweet back at some point.
Events leading up to the placement of Sweet with Richard and
Janet are unclear. Sweet reported his parents’ rights were terminated
because he was raped by a neighbor when he was about four. Stacy
maintained her parental rights were never terminated, but she could not
pursue custody because she was involved in a relationship in which
there was domestic violence. Stacy reported she had been physically and
verbally abused by Richard and Janet when she was a child and wanted
her son placed in foster care instead of with her parents. What is clear is
that Sweet came to live with Richard and Janet when he was
approximately four.
The PSI report further indicated that Richard and Janet moved to
Iowa when Sweet was seven to attend to Richard’s mother who was in
poor health. Richard and Janet did not allow Sweet to talk to his mother
until he became a teenager, when Stacy gave him a cell phone. When
Stacy moved back to Iowa in 2010, the family fought constantly. Sweet
wanted to live with her but Richard and Janet would not allow it. Stacy
moved back to Pennsylvania in 2012.
6
The family dynamics between Richard, Janet, and Sweet were
tumultuous, with frequent arguments and screaming. Sweet reported he
was diagnosed with Attention Deficit Disorder (ADD) at the age of four.
Counseling was sought from Families, Inc. in early 2011, which was
unsuccessful. Sweet reported the family therapist recommended
inpatient committal for drug abuse, which occurred, followed by
outpatient support from the ABBE Center in Manchester. At the ABBE
Center, Sweet was diagnosed with Attention Deficit Hyperactivity
Disorder and Conduct Disorder. The therapist characterized Sweet’s
insight and judgment as “limited” and noted he “may be experiencing
symptoms of mania and [the] diagnosis may be Bipolar Disorder, as
evidenced by [the] impulsive behaviors displayed and [the] behavior with
risk for consequences.”
Sweet was first referred to Juvenile Court Services (JCS) in March
2011 and again in December 2011. His cooperation with JCS was
inconsistent. After being accused of a sexual assault in April 2012, he
again met with JCS. On their way home from the meeting, Sweet jumped
from his grandparents’ moving vehicle.
Regarding his emotional and personal health, the PSI report
indicated Sweet reported he had attempted suicide several times in the
past, with the most recent attempt being in the tent just prior to his
arrest for the murder of his grandparents.
The PSI report noted that Richard had legal difficulties with Stacy
and his other daughter, Alysia, arising from the distribution of assets
from his mother’s estate. The dispute led to Richard’s arrest on a theft
charge and the loss of his job as a result of the arrest. Stacy reported
Richard took his anger at his two daughters out on Sweet and was
abusive towards Sweet.
7
The PSI report also provided information regarding drug abuse in
the Sweet household. Richard’s daughter told therapists that Richard
was an alcoholic, while Sweet indicated he sold Adderall to Richard.
Beginning at age fourteen, Sweet began using marijuana. At the time of
his arrest, he was using marijuana daily. He also abused “all kinds of
pain killers and prescription drugs” but denied use of methamphetamine
or needle-injected substances. His grandparents had Sweet committed
because of suspected drug abuse in July 2011. Sweet also began using
alcohol at age fifteen and engaged in binge drinking from time to time.
Sweet, however, denied having an alcohol or drug abuse problem.
Lastly, the PSI report contained information about risk-taking
behavior. Sweet told a psychiatrist that he enjoyed reckless activities
with friends, such as doing a back flip off a bridge into shallow water or
playing games that involved dropping burning cigarettes between two
friends’ arms. Sweet also recalled drinking to excess and having a friend
burn him fifteen times with cigarettes.
D. Sentencing Hearing. A sentencing hearing occurred on
February 26, 2014. The court was provided with the PSI report, which
was admitted into evidence without objection and without correction or
elaboration by either party. The court also admitted Sweet’s juvenile
records, a video recording of an interview with Sweet following the
murders, a transcript of that interview, a transcript of the State’s case in
chief in the murder trial prior to the plea agreement, and photographs of
the crime scene and the weapon used to commit the crime.
The court heard victim impact statements from Matthew Camlin,
the son of Janet and stepson of Richard; Amanda Sichra, Jane and
Richard’s granddaughter; and Angie Camlin, daughter of Janet and
stepdaughter of Richard.
8
The State offered the testimony of John McEnany, a juvenile court
officer. McEnany generally described information gleaned from
approximately ten meetings with Sweet that commenced in December
2011 after Sweet was charged with possession of drug paraphernalia.
McEnany recounted a history of Sweet’s unstable family life, previous
counseling services that Richard and Janet had sought for Sweet’s
behavioral and mental health issues, and his lengthy juvenile record.
At the close of the State’s evidence, the defense offered and the
court heard a victim impact statement from Stacy, Sweet’s mother, but
also the daughter of one of the deceased, Richard. Like the victims
providing impact statements in the State’s case, Stacy’s testimony ranged
beyond the impact of the crime on her. Although Stacy testified broadly
about the nature of the crime and the kind of punishment she desired,
the court emphasized that it would consider the victim impact statement
only to the extent it related to the impact of the crime on her and nothing
else.
Sweet then offered the testimony of Dr. Stephen Hart, a highly
qualified expert witness in the field of clinical psychology with a special
focus on the assessment of violence, risk, and psychopathic personality
disorder. Dr. Hart reviewed extensive documentation regarding Sweet
and also interviewed Sweet prior to preparing his report.
Dr. Hart generally summarized advancements in the past twenty to
thirty years regarding the understanding of the development of the
adolescent brain. He noted it is now understood that up until the age of
about twenty-five there is a period of rapid change or development in the
adolescent brain. Regarding the maturation of the adolescent brain, he
noted that when individuals are young they are impulsive, and as people
get older, “[they] learn . . . the skills to inhibit behavior.”
9
With respect to Sweet, Dr. Hart concluded he had severe
developmental problems, serious problems related to mental health,
serious problems with personal relationships, and serious problems with
educational adjustment. He asserted Sweet’s decision-making was
destabilized by disturbed attention and also by impulsivity. Dr. Hart
concluded Sweet was psychologically and socially immature (in terms of
self-concept, empathy, and insight) and impetuous at least in part due to
early onset, severe ADD. He testified that while Sweet was
chronologically seventeen, his psychological or social maturation was
somewhere around twelve, thirteen, or fourteen. Dr. Hart noted that
although Sweet’s actions appeared highly planned or premeditated, they
were a “pretty bad plan” and not the “well executed plan of a common
criminal.”
Dr. Hart concluded by noting Sweet’s prospects for rehabilitation
were “mixed.” According to Dr. Hart, there was some chance Sweet
would experience a spontaneous partial or even full remission of his
symptoms. However, he testified it was simply not possible to determine
whether Sweet would develop a full-blown psychopathic personality
disorder as an adult, and even if he did, psychologists could not say
whether it would be untreatable. According to Dr. Hart, the earliest a
determination could be made regarding Sweet’s potential for
rehabilitation was age thirty. According to Dr. Hart, “[W]e won’t even be
in a position to make a decision [about whether Sweet will get better or
not] for many years because of his youth.”
Sweet was last to testify. He expressed remorse and discussed his
tumultuous relationship with his grandparents, which created “trust
issues.” Sweet asked the court to consider his youth and his desire to be
rehabilitated when imposing its sentence.
10
The district court rendered its sentencing decision on March 11.
After listing the Miller/Ragland factors, the district court sentenced
Sweet to life in prison without the possibility of parole. The district court
noted that Sweet was seventeen years and three months old at the time
of the murder. While his maturity was debatable, the district court
stressed that the crimes were premeditated. The district court felt that
Dr. Hart’s characterization of Sweet’s possibility of rehabilitation as
mixed was overly optimistic. Further, the district court found Sweet’s
case was the rare case in which a sentence of life without the possibility
of parole was warranted, as the murders were horrific and showed utter
lack of humanity. The district court concluded that Sweet was currently,
and will continue to be, a threat to society and that the interests of
justice and community safety outweighed mitigating factors.
II. Standard of Review.
Our standard of review when a defendant attacks his or her
sentence on constitutional grounds is de novo. State v. Seats, 865
N.W.2d 545, 553 (Iowa 2015); State v. Lyle, 854 N.W.2d 378, 382 (Iowa
2014); State v. Ragland, 836 N.W.2d 107, 113 (Iowa 2013); State v.
Pearson, 836 N.W.2d 88, 94 (Iowa 2013); State v. Null, 836 N.W.2d 41, 48
(Iowa 2013); State v. Bruegger, 773 N.W.2d 862, 869 (Iowa 2009).
III. Discussion.
A. Positions of the Parties.
1. Sweet. Sweet raises two related but distinct arguments in this
appeal. First, Sweet argues the district court erred in holding that this is
a rare or uncommon case for which life imprisonment without parole
may be imposed on a juvenile. Citing the Roper–Graham–Miller trilogy,
the leading United States Supreme Court cases under the Eighth
Amendment, Sweet asserts his age, his immaturity and impetuousness,
11
his family and home environment, and his prospects for rehabilitation
make a life-without-parole sentence constitutionally impermissible. 1 See
Miller v. Alabama, 567 U.S. ___, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 183 L. Ed. 2d 407
(2012); Graham v. Florida, 560 U.S. 48, 130 S. Ct. 2011, 176 L. Ed. 2d
825 (2010); Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 125 S. Ct. 1183, 161
L. Ed. 2d 1 (2005).
Sweet does not expressly state whether he is proceeding under the
cruel and unusual punishment provision of the United States
Constitution or the Iowa Constitution. Along with citing the Supreme
Court cases, Sweet also cites recent Iowa cases decided under the cruel
and unusual punishment provision of the Iowa Constitution, article I,
section 17. See Lyle, 854 N.W.2d at 378; Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at 107;
Null, 836 N.W.2d at 41. When a party does not specifically indicate
whether a claim is based under the Iowa or Federal Constitution, both
the state and federal claims are preserved. See State v. Harrington, 805
N.W.2d 391, 393 n.3 (Iowa 2011); King v. State, 797 N.W.2d 565, 571
(Iowa 2011). When a different standard is not presented under the Iowa
Constitution, however, we apply the federal framework, reserving the
right to apply that framework in a fashion different from federal
precedents. See State v. Breuer, 808 N.W.2d 195, 200 (Iowa 2012); State
v. Pals, 805 N.W.2d 767, 771–72 (Iowa 2011).
Next, Sweet contends life without the possibility of parole should
be categorically banned for juvenile offenders under the Iowa
Constitution. He argues the rationale of Graham, namely, that it is
1Sweet suggests the standard of review on his Miller-type claim is abuse of
discretion. This is incorrect. Review of Miller-type constitutional claims is de novo.
See, e.g., Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 553 (explaining various standards for challenges to
sentences, including de novo review for constitutional claims).
12
impossible to determine the future behavior of juvenile offenders,
supports a categorical ban on life without the possibility of parole in
homicide cases. He notes the United States is the only country in the
world that imposes life-without-the-possibility-of-parole sentences on
juveniles, see Scott R. Hechinger, Juvenile Life Without Parole: An
Antidote to Congress’s One-Way Criminal Law Ratchet, 35 N.Y.U. Rev. L.
& Soc. Change 408, 411 (2011), and the abandonment of such sentences
has been supported by professional organizations such as the American
Bar Association, the American Psychological Association, the American
Psychiatric Association, and the National Association of Social Workers.
See Brief for Am. Bar Ass’n as Amicus Curiae Supporting Petitioners,
Miller, 567 U.S. ___, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 183 L. Ed. 2d 407 (Nos. 10–9647,
10–9646), 2012 WL 166269 [hereinafter ABA Brief]; Brief for Am.
Psychological Ass’n et al. as Amici Curiae in Supporting Petitioners,
Miller, 567 U.S. ___, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 183 L. Ed. 2d 407 (Nos. 10–9646,
10–9647), 2012 WL 174239 [hereinafter APA Brief].
The United States Supreme Court left this issue open in Miller.
Although Sweet mentions the Eighth Amendment to the United States
Constitution in passing, he does not expressly ground his claim on the
Eighth Amendment in his brief. Sweet explicitly brings his claim under
the Iowa Constitution. Because we decide this case on other grounds, we
need not consider whether Sweet waived any categorical challenge under
the United States Constitution.
2. The State. The State asserts the district court did not abuse its
discretion, as it appropriately analyzed the Miller factors. The State
contends Sweet murdered his grandparents in cold blood and that he is
an “uncommon” juvenile offender who warrants a sentence of life without
the possibility of parole. The State notes the murders were premeditated
13
and were heinous in nature. According to the State, nothing in Sweet’s
background, including his chronological age, his family and home
environment, or the incompetencies of youth, support a lesser sentence
than life without the possibility of parole. With respect to rehabilitation,
the State argues there was no evidence the defendant can ever be
rehabilitated. The State further argues that the Iowa and the United
States Constitutions permit the sentence of life without the possibility of
parole for some juvenile murderers.
The State further rejects the notion that this court should adopt a
categorical approach to life without the possibility of parole for juvenile
offenders. According to the State, our cases since Miller—Null, Ragland,
Pearson, and Lyle—have all embraced the notion of individualized
hearings to determine whether a life-in-prison sentence meets
constitutional muster. The State emphasizes that in Miller the United
States Supreme Court did not embrace a categorical approach banning
life-in-prison sentences for juveniles. The State rejects the reliance on
the fact that the United States is an international outlier, asserting that
American law must be based on American values.
B. United States Supreme Court Precedents.
1. Introduction. We begin our consideration of the issues with a
review of United States Supreme Court precedents under the Cruel and
Unusual Punishment Clause of the Eighth Amendment. In Weems v.
United States, the Supreme Court held that a twelve-year jail term in
irons at hard labor for the crime of falsifying records was excessive,
emphasizing “that it is a precept of justice that punishment for crime
should be graduated and proportioned to [the] offense.” 217 U.S. 349,
367, 30 S. Ct. 544, 549, 54 L. Ed. 793, 798 (1910). Later, in Trop v.
Dulles, the Supreme Court emphasized that the Eighth Amendment
14
“must draw its meaning from the evolving standards of decency that
mark the progress of a maturing society.” 356 U.S. 86, 101, 78 S. Ct.
590, 598, 2 L. Ed. 2d 630, 642 (1958). The teachings of Weems and
Trop, namely that the Eighth Amendment embraces a proportionality
principle that draws meaning from “the evolving standards of decency,”
have been repeatedly cited in more recent cruel and unusual punishment
cases of the United States Supreme Court. See, e.g., Montgomery v.
Louisiana, 577 U.S. ___, 136 S. Ct. 718, 742, 193 L. Ed. 2d 599, 629
(2016) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Hall v. Florida, 572 U.S. ___, 134 S. Ct.
1986, 1992, 188 L. Ed. 2d 1007, 1016 (2014); Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132
S. Ct. at 2463, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 417; Graham, 560 U.S. at 58–59, 130
S. Ct. at 2021, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 835; Kennedy v. Louisiana, 554 U.S.
407, 419, 128 S. Ct. 2641, 2649, 171 L. Ed. 2d 525, 538 (2008); Roper,
543 U.S. at 560–61, 125 S. Ct. at 1190, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 16; Atkins v.
Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 311–12, 122 S. Ct. 2242, 2247, 153 L. Ed. 2d
335, 344 (2002).
2. Developing caselaw regarding the death penalty and vulnerable
classes. Beginning in the 1970s, the Supreme Court began to consider
whether the Cruel and Unusual Punishment Clause should be
interpreted to categorically bar the death penalty generally or, in the
alternative, with respect to certain vulnerable classes of people. In a
series of cases, the Supreme Court considered the merits of broad
categorical prohibitions as compared to more precise case-by-case
adjudications where, at least in theory, the law’s most severe
punishment was reserved for the most culpable or most deserving. While
this case deals with life in prison without parole rather than the death
penalty, the death-penalty cases provide a backdrop for the Supreme
Court’s later consideration of the implications of the Eighth Amendment
15
on the sentence of life in prison without parole for juvenile offenders. In
particular, the death-penalty cases show the tension between categorical
rules, which prohibit imposition of the death penalty for certain classes
or cases, and a more finely tuned case-by-case approach, which seeks to
identify the most culpable of offenders who might be deserving of severe
punishment.
The Supreme Court considered the constitutionality of the death
penalty in murder and rape cases in Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 92
S. Ct. 2726, 33 L. Ed. 2d 346 (1972) (per curiam) (plurality opinion). In
Furman, a 5–4 majority of a highly fractured Supreme Court held that
the imposition of the death penalty in the cases before the court would
constitute cruel and unusual punishment in violation of the Eighth
Amendment. Id. at 239–40, 92 S. Ct. at 2727, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 350.
The crucial opinion in Furman was provided by Justice Stewart,
who declined to reach the question of whether the death penalty was
categorically barred, but found the arbitrary and capricious nature of the
application of the death penalty made it unconstitutional as applied in
the cases before the court. Id. at 306, 309–10, 92 S. Ct. at 2760, 2762–
63, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 388, 389–90. According to Justice Stewart, the rarity
of the death penalty in cases where it might theoretically be imposed
made the sentences under consideration “cruel and unusual in the same
way that being struck by lightning is cruel and unusual.” Id. at 309, 92
S. Ct. at 2762, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 389–90.
All in all, two justices in Furman found the death penalty
categorically unconstitutional for all purposes, 2 three justices found the
2Furman, 408 U.S. at 305–06, 92 S. Ct. at 2760, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 387–88
(Brennan, J., concurring); id. at 358–59, 92 S. Ct. at 2787, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 417–18
(Marshall, J., concurring).
16
statutes before the court unconstitutional as applied but declined to
reach the categorical question, 3 and four dissenting justices found the
death penalty not subject to categorical challenge. 4 While the categorical
issue thus remained open in Furman, the Supreme Court majority was
clearly concerned about the arbitrary nature of the imposition of the
death penalty and the need to focus its application on only the most
deserving offenders.
The Supreme Court next considered whether the death penalty
should be categorically barred under the Cruel and Unusual Punishment
Clause in Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 96 S. Ct. 2909, 49 L. Ed. 2d
859 (1976) (plurality opinion). In Gregg, the statutory provision
authorizing the death penalty bifurcated the question of guilt from
penalty; the jury was instructed regarding aggravating and mitigating
factors; the prosecution had to prove an aggravating factor beyond a
reasonable doubt to support the death penalty; and the district court
was required to complete an extensive report on the trial proceedings. Id.
at 163–66, 96 S. Ct. at 2920–22, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 869–70. In addition, the
statute provided detailed procedures regarding appeals of death
sentences. Id. at 166–68, 96 S. Ct. at 2922, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 870–71. The
statute provided that the Georgia Supreme Court would automatically
review any death sentence to determine if it was imposed under the
3Furman, 408 U.S. at 257, 92 S. Ct. at 2735–36, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 359–60
(Douglas, J., concurring); id. at 309–10, 92 S. Ct. at 2762–63, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 390
(Stewart, J., concurring); id. at 312–13, 92 S. Ct. at 2764, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 392 (White,
J., concurring).
4Furman, 408 U.S. at 375, 92 S. Ct. at 2796–97, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 428 (Burger,
C.J., dissenting); id. at 414, 92 S. Ct. at 2816, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 450–51 (Blackmun, J.,
dissenting); id. at 461–65, 92 S. Ct. at 2840–42, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 478–80 (Powell, J.,
dissenting); id. at 468, 92 S. Ct. at 2843, 33 L. Ed. 2d at 486 (Rehnquist, J.,
dissenting).
17
influence of passion and prejudice, to determine if the evidence
supported statutory aggravating circumstances, and to determine
whether the sentence was disproportionate compared to sentences
imposed in similar cases. Id. at 166–67, 96 S. Ct. at 2922, 49 L. Ed. 2d
at 871.
In Gregg, Justice Stewart joined the four dissenters in Furman to
uphold the Georgia death-penalty statute and the resulting convictions.
Id. at 168–69, 96 S. Ct. at 2922–23, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 872. In an opinion
joined by Justices Powell and Stevens, Justice Stewart characterized the
Furman decision as holding that the death penalty could not be imposed
“under sentencing procedures that created a substantial risk that it
would be inflicted in an arbitrary and capricious manner.” Id. at 188, 96
S. Ct. at 2932, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 883. As in Furman, the Gregg Supreme
Court plurality was plainly concerned with ensuring that the death
penalty was focused only on the most deserving offenders. Id. at 183, 96
S. Ct. at 2930, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 880. Justice Stewart found that the
detailed procedures in the Georgia statute rendered the death penalty
constitutional in the case before the court. Id. at 207, 96 S. Ct. at 2941,
49 L. Ed. 2d at 893.
The same day the Supreme Court decided Gregg, it also handed
down its decision in Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280, 96 S. Ct.
2978, 49 L. Ed. 2d 944 (1976) (plurality opinion). In Woodson, the North
Carolina legislature responded to concerns in Furman about the arbitrary
and capricious nature of the application of the death penalty by enacting
a statute in which the death penalty was mandatory for the crime of first-
degree murder. Id. at 286–87, 96 S. Ct. at 2982–83, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 950–
51. This amounted to categorization in reverse: instead of categorically
barring the death penalty for those found guilty of first-degree murder,
18
the statute categorically imposed the death penalty on all found guilty of
the crime. Id.
In a plurality opinion by Justice Stewart, the Supreme Court found
the reverse categorical North Carolina statute unconstitutional. Id. at
305, 96 S. Ct. at 2991–92, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 961–62. The Woodson
plurality found the statute defective for three reasons. First, in practice
the United States’ evolving standards of decency reject mandatory
imposition of the death penalty for all persons convicted of a particular
offense as “unduly harsh and unworkably rigid.” Id. at 292–93, 96 S. Ct.
at 2985–86, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 953–54. Second, the Woodson plurality
noted that juries had no standards to guide their exercise of power and
that juries might be willing to act lawlessly to avoid the imposition of a
death sentence. Id. at 302–03, 96 S. Ct. at 2990–91, 49 L. Ed. 2d at
959–60. Finally, the plurality emphasized that the statute failed to allow
“particularized consideration of relevant aspects of the character and
record of each convicted defendant before the imposition upon him of a
sentence of death.” Id. at 303, 96 S. Ct. at 2991, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 960–61.
Read together, the opinions in Gregg and Woodson stand for the
proposition that a statutory death penalty, if appropriately structured,
could survive a categorical constitutional challenge under the Eighth
Amendment. The emphasis in Woodson on particularized, case-by-case
exploration of mitigation gave rise, however, to an important development
in the law, namely, the development in capital cases of a body of law
related to the proper presentation of a mitigation defense. See, e.g.,
Lockett v. Ohio, 438 U.S. 586, 604–05, 98 S. Ct. 2954, 2964, 57 L. Ed. 2d
973, 989–90 (1978) (plurality opinion).
It has long been recognized that those offenders facing severe
penalties are often poorly represented in their underlying criminal trials.
19
See Powell v. Alabama, 287 U.S. 45, 52, 53 S. Ct. 55, 58, 77 L. Ed. 158,
162 (1932). The American Bar Association (ABA) took the lead in
developing mitigation guidelines for the defense of criminal defendants
facing the death penalty.
As early as 1970, the ABA developed its generally applicable ABA
Standards Relating to the Prosecution Function and the Defense Function.
In response to the evolving death-penalty jurisprudence, the ABA
developed more specific guidelines relevant to representation in death-
penalty cases in the ABA Guidelines for the Appointment and
Performance of Defense Counsel in Death Penalty Cases (rev. ed. 2003),
reprinted in 31 Hofstra L. Rev. 913 (2003) [hereinafter ABA Guidelines],
and Supplementary Guidelines for the Mitigation Function of Defense
Teams in Death Penalty Cases, 36 Hofstra L. Rev. 677 (2008) [hereinafter
Supplementary Guidelines].
The later Supplementary Guidelines require the assembly of a
mitigation specialist to investigate potential mitigation defenses and
present them to the sentencer. Supp. Guidelines, Guideline 4.1, 36
Hofstra L. Rev. at 680–81. The guidelines and supplement require,
among other things, the establishment of a relationship of trust between
the defense team and the accused; thorough exploration of a defendant’s
family and social history, including extensive interviews; the
participation in the defense of a trained mitigation expert experienced in
the psychological and social sciences; and the hiring of other experts to
assist the defense. ABA Guidelines, Guideline 10.5, 31 Hofstra L. Rev. at
1005–06; Supp. Guidelines, Guideline 10.11, 36 Hofstra L. Rev. at 689–
92. The scope and manner of investigation and the advocacy
contemplated by the guidelines and supplement are at great variance
from the routine sentencing practices often employed in the courts. See
20
ABA Guidelines, 31 Hofstra L. Rev. at 928 (describing the need for the
guidelines due to problems with the quality of defense being “profound
and pervasive” in death-penalty cases). Under the guidelines and
supplement, the mass-produced, routine Model-A defense of offenders
facing the death penalty was abandoned in favor of a new, highly intense
individualized process that harnessed recent developments in behavioral
and psychological sciences. See ABA Guidelines, Guideline 10.5, 31
Hofstra L. Rev. at 1005–06; Supp. Guidelines, Guideline 10.11, 36
Hofstra L. Rev. at 689–92.
Although the Supreme Court has never held that the ABA
Guidelines or Supplementary Guidelines are mandatory, they have
nonetheless served as a guide for determining whether counsel has been
ineffective in death-penalty cases. Even though the federal standard of
ineffective assistance established in Strickland v. Washington, 466 U.S.
668, 686, 104 S. Ct. 2052, 2064, 80 L. Ed. 2d 674, 692–93 (1984), has
often been regarded as a difficult standard to meet, the Supreme Court,
citing ABA Standards and Guidelines, has found ineffective assistance in
a number of death-penalty cases. See, e.g., Rompilla v. Beard, 545 U.S.
374, 387–90, 125 S. Ct. 2456, 2465–67, 162 L. Ed. 2d 360, 375–77
(2005); Wiggins v. Smith, 539 U.S. 510, 524, 123 S. Ct. 2527, 2536–37,
156 L. Ed. 2d 471, 486 (2003); Williams v. Taylor, 529 U.S. 362, 396,
120 S. Ct. 1495, 1514–15, 146 L. Ed. 2d 389, 420 (2000) (plurality
opinion).
The upshot of the Supreme Court’s Gregg–Woodson line of cases is
that in states where the death penalty is authorized with an
appropriately detailed statute, a highly specialized “death penalty bar”
has arisen to ensure that death-penalty defendants obtain the kind of
representation necessary to prevent arbitrary and capricious application
21
of the sanction and allow the death penalty to be imposed only on the
most culpable offenders.
While the Woodson approach has generated a new and substantial
body of law regarding the process of case-by-case determinations in
death-penalty cases, the notion that the death penalty might be
categorically barred in certain types of cases remained viable. In Coker v.
Georgia, the Supreme Court considered the constitutionality of the death
penalty in connection with the rape of an adult woman. 433 U.S. 584,
97 S. Ct. 2861, 53 L. Ed. 2d 982 (1977) (plurality opinion). The Supreme
Court, by another 5–4 vote, took a categorical approach, finding that the
death penalty could not constitutionally be imposed for the crime of rape.
Id. at 600, 97 S. Ct. at 2870, 53 L. Ed. 2d at 994.
In a plurality opinion, Justice White surveyed the attitudes of state
legislatures and sentencing juries and concluded that they weigh against
the death penalty for the crime of rape. Id. at 593–97, 97 S. Ct. at 2866–
68, 53 L. Ed. 2d at 990–92. Justice White, however, stated that the
attitude of state legislatures and sentencing juries did not wholly resolve
the controversy as the Constitution contemplated that the Court brings
its own independent judgment to bear on the question. Id. at 597, 97
S. Ct. at 2868, 53 L. Ed. 2d at 992. In applying independent judgment,
Justice White concluded that the death penalty for rape was categorically
unconstitutional. Id. at 600, 97 S. Ct. at 2870, 53 L. Ed. 2d at 994. In
reaching this conclusion, he noted that rape was not the equivalent of
murder and yet under Georgia law, a rapist could face the death penalty
while a person who deliberately murdered a victim without aggravating
circumstances would escape a death sentence. Id. at 599–600, 97 S. Ct.
at 2869–70, 53 L. Ed. 2d at 993–94.
22
The Supreme Court came to a similar categorical conclusion in
Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.S. 782, 102 S. Ct. 3368, 73 L. Ed. 2d 1140
(1982) (plurality opinion). In Enmund, the Supreme Court held that the
death penalty could not constitutionally be applied to persons convicted
on an aiding and abetting theory when the defendant did not kill or
intend to kill the victim. Id. at 801, 102 S. Ct. at 3378, 73 L. Ed. 2d at
1154. As in the plurality opinion in Coker, the plurality canvassed
objective factors, including legislative judgments and international
opinion, but also noted that the Court was required to apply its
independent judgment in making the ultimate determination. Id. at 797,
102 S. Ct. at 3376, 73 L. Ed. 2d at 1151. In rejecting the death penalty
categorically when the defendant did not kill or intend to kill the victim,
the Enmunds plurality emphasized the role of moral guilt as “critical to
‘the degree of . . . criminal culpability.’ ” Id. at 800, 102 S. Ct. at 3378,
73 L. Ed. 2d at 1153 (quoting Mullaney v. Wilbur, 421 U.S. 684, 698, 95
S. Ct. 1881, 1889, 44 L. Ed. 2d 508, 519 (1975)).
In sum, the Supreme Court in Furman arguably came close to
abolishing the death penalty categorically in all circumstances, but then
retreated into a bifurcated approach as seen in Gregg, Woodson, Coker,
and Enmund. In some cases involving certain offenses, the Supreme
Court held that the death penalty was categorically barred as “excessive”
for the crime and therefore contrary to the Eighth Amendment. Enmund,
458 U.S. at 801, 102 S. Ct. at 3378, 73 L. Ed. 2d at 1154; Coker, 433
U.S. at 598, 97 S. Ct. at 2869, 53 L. Ed. 2d at 993. On the other hand,
for the heinous crime of murder, the Supreme Court held that death
penalty is not barred in all circumstances, but instead must be applied
pursuant to specific standards and procedures designed to ensure that
the death penalty is not administered in an arbitrary or capricious
23
manner and to ensure that the harsh penalty is reserved for the most
culpable offenders. Woodson, 428 U.S. at 303, 96 S. Ct. at 2990–91, 49
L. Ed. 2d at 960; Gregg, 428 U.S. at 188, 206–07, 96 S. Ct. at 2932,
2940–41, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 883, 893. The possibility of individualized
consideration of moral culpability gave rise to the development by the
American Bar Association of detailed and intensive standards for the
representation of persons subject to the death penalty and a new era of
representation in death-penalty cases.
3. Post-Furman Supreme Court caselaw regarding death penalty
and life in prison for juveniles and vulnerable classes. We now turn our
attention to post-Furman cases of the United States Supreme Court
dealing with the constitutionality under the Eighth Amendment of the
death penalty for juvenile offenders or vulnerable classes. The focus here
is not on the nature of the crime, as in Coker or Enmund, but on the
character or qualities of the defendant that arguably lessen the
culpability of the defendant and make that defendant less deserving of
harsh criminal penalties.
We begin our discussion with Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.S. 104,
102 S. Ct. 869, 71 L. Ed. 2d 1 (1982). In Eddings, the Supreme Court
considered whether a sixteen-year-old juvenile convicted of murder could
receive the death penalty. Id. at 105, 102 S. Ct. at 872, 71 L. Ed. 2d at
5. In Eddings, the trial court recognized that although Eddings had “a
personality disorder,” he still knew the difference between right and
wrong and therefore his personality disorder could not be considered in
determining his criminal responsibility. Id. at 109–10, 102 S. Ct. at 874,
71 L. Ed. 2d at 7–8. The trial court further held that while his family
history was “useful in explaining” his offense, it did not offer an excuse.
Id. at 110, 102 S. Ct. at 874, 71 L. Ed. 2d at 8.
24
In a five-member-majority opinion by Justice Powell, the Supreme
Court concluded that the death penalty was not constitutionally applied
to the defendant in this case. Id. at 117, 102 S. Ct. at 878, 71 L. Ed. 2d
at 12. The Court rejected the trial court’s determination that as a matter
of law the mitigating factors of a difficult family history and emotional
disturbance should not be considered by the jury. Id. at 112–15, 102
S. Ct. at 876–77, 71 L. Ed. 2d at 9–11. Further, the Eddings Court
observed that while “[e]ven the normal 16-year-old customarily lacks the
maturity of an adult,” the evidence suggested that Eddings’ mental and
emotional development were “at a level several years below his
chronological age.” Id. at 116, 102 S. Ct. at 877, 71 L. Ed. 2d at 12. The
Eddings Court noted that not only was the minority of the offender “a
mitigating factor of great weight,” the mental and emotional development
of a youthful defendant must be considered as well in sentencing. Id. at
108, 116, 102 S. Ct. at 873, 877, 71 L. Ed. 2d at 7, 12. Consistent with
Furman, Gregg, and Woodson, the Court emphasized that the state
statutes must ensure that “the sentencing authority is given adequate
information and guidance.” Id. at 111, 102 S. Ct. at 875, 71 L. Ed. 2d at
8–9 (quoting Gregg, 428 U.S. at 195, 96 S. Ct. at 2935, 49 L. Ed. 2d at
887).
The Supreme Court next considered the death penalty for a fifteen-
year-old offender in Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.S. 815, 108 S. Ct.
2687, 101 L. Ed. 2d 702 (1988) (plurality opinion). The defendant urged
the Court to categorically conclude that the death penalty could not be
applied against defendants under the age of sixteen. Id. at 818–19, 108
S. Ct. at 2690, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 708.
In an opinion by Justice Stevens, a plurality of the Court began by
emphasizing that in many legal contexts, children are treated differently
25
from adults. Id. at 823–25, 108 S. Ct. at 2692–93, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 711–
12. While the age of majority varied among the states, no state set the
age lower than sixteen. Id. at 824, 108 S. Ct. at 2963, 101 L. Ed. 2d at
711. The plurality noted that most states did not expressly establish an
age for the death penalty, but merely provided that certain juveniles
could be waived into adult court. Id. at 826–27, 108 S. Ct. at 2694–95,
101 L. Ed. 2d at 712–14. These statutes, according to the plurality, did
not focus on the question of what chronological age the line should be
drawn. Id. at 827–29, 108 S. Ct. at 2695, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 713–14. The
plurality observed that of all the persons sentenced to death, only five
were less than sixteen years old at the time of the offense. Id. at 832–33,
108 S. Ct. at 2697, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 717. Further, the plurality noted
that less culpability should attach to a crime committed by a juvenile
than to a comparable crime committed by an adult. Id. at 835, 108
S. Ct. at 2698, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 718. Finally, the plurality found that
retribution did not justify the execution of a less culpable fifteen-year-old
offender and that deterrence did not justify the death penalty as teenage
minds were not likely to engage in the kind of cost-benefit analysis that
attaches any weight to the remote possibility of execution. Id. at 836–37,
108 S. Ct. at 2699–700, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 719–20. While the plurality
categorically would invalidate the death penalty for all fifteen-year-old
offenders, it declined to consider the invitation of the offender and
various amici curiae to draw the line at eighteen. Id. at 838, 108 S. Ct.
at 2700, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 720.
The deciding Thompson opinion, however, was written by Justice
O’Connor who concurred in the judgment of the Court. Id. at 848, 108
S. Ct. at 2706, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 728 (O’Connor, J., concurring in
judgment). While concurring in the judgment, Justice O’Connor did not
26
embrace the plurality’s discussion of objective factors or proportionality.
Id. at 848–49, 108 S. Ct. at 2706, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 728–29. She
concurred in result only because the Oklahoma legislature did not
directly consider whether a fifteen year old should be eligible for the
death penalty. Id. at 857, 108 S. Ct. at 2710–11, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 734.
Justice O’Connor declined to embrace a broader rule that the death
penalty for fifteen year olds was always unconstitutional, but only that
the Oklahoma statute as applied to fifteen year olds was invalid. Id. at
857–58, 108 S. Ct. at 2711, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 734.
In Penry v. Lynaugh, the Supreme Court considered the
constitutionality of the death penalty when the accused was intellectually
disabled. 492 U.S. 302, 307, 109 S. Ct. 2934, 2941, 106 L. Ed. 2d 256,
271 (1989) (plurality opinion), abrogated by Atkins, 536 U.S. at 307, 321,
122 S. Ct. at 2244, 2252, 153 L. Ed. 2d at 341, 350. In Penry, the jury
did not receive an instruction that it could consider and give effect to the
mental characteristics of the offender as a mitigating circumstance. Id.
at 310–11, 109 S. Ct. at 2942–43, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 273. The jury
convicted Penry of murder, and he was sentenced to death. Id. at 310–
11, 109 S. Ct. at 2942–43, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 272–73.
Justice O’Connor wrote the main opinion for the Penry Court.
Writing for a five-member majority, she wrote that the Texas sentencing
procedure did not adequately afford the defendant with an individualized
hearing. Id. at 328, 109 S. Ct. at 2952, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 284. Because
punishment “should be directly related to the personal culpability of the
defendant,” the jury must be allowed to consider and give effect to the
defendant’s mental status. Id. at 327–28, 109 S. Ct. at 2951, 106
L. Ed. 2d at 284. As a result, Justice O’Connor concluded for a majority
27
of the Court that Penry’s sentence must be reversed. Id. at 328, 109
S. Ct. at 2952, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 284.
Justice O’Connor further concluded that a categorical bar could
not be adopted “today.” Id. at 340, 109 S. Ct. at 2958, 106 L. Ed. 2d at
292. She emphasized that Penry was found competent to stand trial and
knew the difference between right and wrong. Id. at 333, 109 S. Ct. at
2954–55, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 288. Further, Justice O’Connor, relying
largely on the fact that only two legislatures had barred the death
penalty for intellectually disabled offenders, found there was no objective
evidence of an emerging national consensus in support of a categorical
ban. Id. at 334–35, 109 S. Ct. at 2955, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 288–89.
Justices Brennan and Marshall dissented on this point, finding
sufficient basis to support a categorical bar. Justice Brennan wrote that
in order to be classified as intellectually disabled, an individual must
have “significantly subaverage general intellectual functioning existing
concurrently with deficits in adaptive behavior [which manifest] during
the developmental period.” Id. at 344, 109 S. Ct. at 2960, 106 L. Ed. 2d
at 295 (Brennan, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (quoting
Am. Ass’n on Mental Retardation, Classification in Mental Retardation 11
(H. Grossman ed. 1983)). As a result, Justice Brennan saw no need for
individualized determination as members of the class necessarily lack a
degree of culpability. Id. at 347–48, 109 S. Ct. at 2962, 106 L. Ed. 2d at
297. Justice Brennan further doubted that the individualized
consideration afforded at sentencing will ensure that only exceptional
intellectually disabled individuals with near normal capabilities will be
picked to receive the death penalty. Id. at 346, 109 S. Ct. at 2961, 106
L. Ed. 2d at 296. In particular, Justice Brennan feared that the
heinousness of the crime would overpower any mitigation effect of
28
intellectual disability. Id. at 347, 109 S. Ct. at 2962, 106 L. Ed. 2d at
296–97. Further, Justice Brennan feared that a prosecutor could argue
that an intellectually disabled offender should be more severely punished
than an ordinary defender. Id. Because the death penalty for
intellectually disabled individuals, who lack the same degree of
culpability as nondisabled adult offenders, did not advance the penal
goals of deterrence and retribution, Justice Brennan concluded that the
death penalty should be categorically barred for such offenders. Id. at
348–49, 109 S. Ct. at 2962–63, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 297–98.
Justice Stevens filed a short concurring and dissenting opinion.
He concluded, based upon the medical facts, that executions of the
intellectually disabled are unconstitutional notwithstanding Justice
O’Connor’s analysis of objective indicators showing a lack of national
consensus. Id. at 350, 109 S. Ct. at 2963, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 298–99
(Stevens, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part).
The Supreme Court decided Sanford v. Kentucky, 492 U.S. 361,
109 S. Ct. 2969, 106 L. Ed. 2d 306 (1989) (plurality opinion), abrogated
by Roper, 543 U.S. at 574, 125 S. Ct. at 1198, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 25, on
the same day it decided Penry. In Sanford, the Court considered the
imposition of the death penalty on two youths aged sixteen and
seventeen respectively. Id. at 364–65, 109 S. Ct. at 2972, 106 L. Ed. 2d
at 315. Justice Scalia delivered the opinion for the Court. Justice Scalia
found that a majority of jurisdictions whose laws allowed capital
punishment still permitted execution of sixteen and seventeen year olds
and that, as a result, the offenders had not demonstrated a national
consensus against the death penalty. Id. at 372–73, 109 S. Ct. at 2976–
77, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 320. While noting that the death penalty in fact was
rarely imposed upon juveniles, Justice Scalia regarded it as
29
“overwhelmingly probable” that this was a result of prosecutors and
juries exercising discretion to ensure that the death penalty is rarely
imposed upon juvenile defendants. Id. at 374, 109 S. Ct. at 2977, 106
L. Ed. 2d at 321.
Speaking for four members of the Court, Justice Scalia went on to
indicate that the fact that youth were treated differently for purposes of
driving, drinking alcohol, and voting had no impact on the constitutional
analysis. Id. at 374–75, 109 S. Ct. at 2977–78, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 321. He
also wrote that in determining a national consensus, the only relevant
materials were legislative action; public opinion polls, views of interest
groups, and positions adopted by various professional associations were
irrelevant. Id. at 377, 109 S. Ct. at 2979, 106 L. Ed. 2d at 323.
On balance, Eddings, Thompson, Penry, and Sanford demonstrate
that the Supreme Court in the immediate aftermath of Furman was
repeatedly sharply divided on issues related to the imposition of capital
punishment. In the aggregate, however, the majority of the Supreme
Court usually elected a demanding process with particularized showings
of culpability of the individual defendant over categorical rules that
would exclude certain types of defendants from receiving the death
penalty. On the other hand, the Court was receptive to categorical rules
relating to the type of offenses for which the death penalty might be
imposed.
These cases, however, were often decided by narrow majorities or
plurality opinions with majorities shifting depending upon the peculiar
facts of the case. The cases reflect difficult decision-making when the
Supreme Court was called upon to decide whether to adopt a “bright
line” categorical approach or a “case by case” process that depended
upon the provision of adequate information and an appropriate structure
30
to ensure that the fact finder reserved the death penalty for only truly
culpable defendants.
4. Supreme Court caselaw revisits the death penalty and explores
life in prison for juveniles and vulnerable classes. Since 2000, however,
the United States Supreme Court has reconsidered the implications,
under the Cruel and Unusual Punishment Clause, of the death penalty
and life without the possibility of parole for juveniles or vulnerable
classes in a number of cases. As will be seen below, these cases
significantly departed from past precedent and embarked on a new
analysis of cruel and unusual punishment issues in the context of
vulnerable classes, particularly juveniles.
The first case signaling the shift is Atkins. In Atkins, the Supreme
Court revisited the question of whether intellectually disabled persons
may be sentenced to death. 536 U.S. at 306–07, 122 S. Ct. at 2242, 153
L. Ed. 2d at 341. The Supreme Court had considered the same issue
only thirteen years before in Penry, 492 U.S. at 302, 109 S. Ct. at 2934,
106 L. Ed. 2d at 256.
In Atkins, however, the Supreme Court reversed course, overruled
Penry, and held that imposition of the death penalty on intellectually
disabled persons violated the Eighth Amendment. Atkins, 536 U.S. at
321, 122 S. Ct. at 2252, 153 L. Ed.2d at 350. In an opinion written by
Justice Stevens, the Court in Atkins emphasized that “the American
public, legislators, scholars, and judges” had deliberated over the
question of the death penalty for the intellectually disabled and had
come to a consensus that it should be prohibited. Id. at 307, 316, 122
S. Ct. at 2244, 2249, 153 L. Ed. 2d at 341, 347. Justice Stevens noted
that while a number of states still imposed the death penalty on
intellectually disabled individuals convicted of heinous crimes, the
31
consistency of the direction of change is more important than simply
tallying the number. Id. at 315, 122 S. Ct. at 2249, 153 L. Ed. 2d at
346–47. Justice Stevens noted further that the practice of executing the
intellectually disabled was “uncommon.” Id. at 316, 122 S. Ct. at 2249,
153 L. Ed. 2d at 347. In any event, Justice Stevens emphasized that
objective evidence of consensus, though important, did not “wholly
determine” the controversy as the Court was required to bring its own
judgment to bear by asking whether there is reason to disagree with the
judgment reached by the citizenry and its legislators. Id. at 312–13, 122
S. Ct. at 2247–48, 153 L. Ed. 2d at 345.
Justice Stevens wrote that for the intellectually disabled, the case
for retribution was diminished. Id. at 319, 122 S. Ct. at 2251, 153
L. Ed. 2d at 349. Further, deterrence is also undermined by the
diminished ability of the intellectually disabled “to understand and
process information, to learn from experience, to engage in logical
reasoning, [and] to control impulses.” Id. at 320, 122 S. Ct. at 2251, 153
L. Ed. 2d at 349.
Justice Stevens also noted that if left to case-by-case
determinations, there was “[t]he risk ‘that the death penalty [would] be
imposed in spite of factors which may call for a less severe penalty.’ ” Id.
at 320, 122 S. Ct. at 2251, 153 L. Ed. 2d at 350 (quoting Lockett, 438
U.S. at 605, 98 S. Ct. at 2965, 57 L. Ed. 2d at 990). Justice Stevens
further noted that intellectually disabled defendants might be less able to
assist in their defense, thereby undermining the accuracy of the fact-
finding process that would lead to the imposition of the death penalty.
Id. at 320–21, 122 S. Ct. at 2252, 153 L. Ed. 2d at 350.
The tea leaves in Atkins did not go unnoticed. A few years later in
Roper, the Supreme Court departed from its narrow approach in Eddings
32
and Thompson and held the death penalty unconstitutional as applied to
juveniles in all cases “no matter how heinous the crime.” Roper, 543
U.S. at 568, 125 S. Ct. at 1195, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 21.
In Roper, the Supreme Court cited several factors supporting its
conclusion that juveniles are categorically different for purposes of
imposing capital punishment. Id. at 569–70, 125 S. Ct. at 1195–96, 161
L. Ed. 2d at 21–22. First, the Roper Court noted that juveniles have a
“lack of maturity and an underdeveloped sense of responsibility.” Id. at
569, 125 S. Ct. at 1195, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 21 (quoting Johnson v. Texas,
509 U.S. 350, 367, 113 S. Ct. 2658, 2668, 125 L. Ed. 2d 290, 306
(1993)). Second, the Roper Court emphasized juveniles are more
susceptible than adults to “negative influences and outside pressures”
and juveniles “have less control, or less experience with control, over
their own environment.” Id. at 569, 125 S. Ct. at 1195, 161 L. Ed. 2d at
22. Third, the Roper Court noted juvenile personality and character
traits are still being formed. Id. at 570, 125 S. Ct. at 1195, 161 L. Ed. 2d
at 22.
In light of the differences between adults and juveniles, the Roper
Court held that juveniles categorically cannot suffer the death penalty
“no matter how heinous the crime.” Id. at 568, 125 S. Ct. at 1195, 161
L. Ed. 2d at 21. The Roper Court stressed that “[i]t is difficult even for
expert psychologists to differentiate between the juvenile offender whose
crime reflects unfortunate yet transient immaturity, and the rare juvenile
offender whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.” Id. at 573, 125
S. Ct. at 1197, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 24.
Five years after Roper, the Supreme Court decided Graham. In
Graham, the Supreme Court considered the constitutionality of life in
prison without parole for juvenile offenders who commit nonhomicide
33
offenses. 560 U.S. at 52–53, 130 S. Ct. at 2017–18, 176 L. Ed. 2d at
832. In Graham, the state in effect sought to uphold the life-without-the-
possibility-of-parole sentence on the ground that Roper was a death-
penalty case and “death is different” for purposes of constitutional
analysis. See id. at 69, 130 S. Ct. at 2027, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 842.
As in Roper, however, the Graham Court developed a categorical
rule, namely, that when nonhomicide offenses are involved, juveniles
may not be sentenced to life without the possibility of parole regardless of
the nature of the underlying crimes. Id. at 82, 130 S. Ct. at 2034, 176
L. Ed. 2d at 850. The Graham Court cited the reasoning of Roper and
prior precedents, noting that because of the lack of maturity, a juvenile
offense “is not as morally reprehensible as that of an adult.” Id. at 68,
130 S. Ct. at 2026, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 841 (quoting Thompson, 487 U.S. at
835, 108 S. Ct. at 2699, 101 L. Ed. 2d at 719). Reasoning that the
principles articulated in Roper applied fully in the context of juvenile
nonhomicide offenses, the Graham Court categorically declared that life
without the possibility of parole could never be applied to such offenses,
regardless of their nature or heinousness. Id. at 68, 82, 130 S. Ct. at
2026, 2034, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 841, 850. As in Roper, the Graham Court
doubted “that courts taking a case-by-case . . . approach could with
sufficient accuracy distinguish the few incorrigible juvenile offenders
from the many that have the capacity for change.” Id. at 77, 130 S. Ct.
at 2032, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 847.
The result in Graham was consistent with the position advanced by
the American Medical Association (AMA) in an amicus brief with
extensive citations to scientific and medical authorities. Brief for Am.
Med. Ass’n et al. as Amici Curiae Supporting Neither Party, Graham, 560
U.S. at 48, 130 S. Ct. at 2011, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 825 (No. 08–7412, 08–
34
7621), 2009 WL 2247127. The AMA noted that “[s]cientists have found
that adolescents as a group, even in the later stages of adolescence, are
more likely than adults to engage in risky, impulsive, and sensation-
seeking behavior.” Id. at *2. The AMA asserted that modern science
demonstrated that “the structural and functional immaturities of the
adolescent brain provide a biological basis for the behavioral
immaturities exhibited by adolescence” and that “adolescent brains are
structurally immature in areas of the brain associated with enhanced
abilities of executive behavioral control.” Id. at *4, 16.
The third case in the quartet of recent juvenile cases is Miller. In
Miller, the Supreme Court considered two heinous murder cases
involving juvenile defendants. 567 U.S. at ____, 132 S. Ct. at 2461–62,
183 L. Ed. 2d at 415–17. The defendants, and various amici including
the ABA and the American Psychology Association (APA), urged the court
to adopt the categorical approach of Roper and Graham. See ABA Brief,
2012 WL 166269; APA Brief, 2012 WL 174239.
The ABA noted that it had long been interested in matters affecting
juvenile justice. ABA Brief at *2. As far back as 1980, the ABA had
concluded that when compared to adults, the reduced capacity of
juveniles—“in moral judgment, self-restraint and the ability to resist the
influence of others, among other factors—rendered [juveniles] less
morally culpable than adults.” Id. at *7. Citing the principles enunciated
by the Supreme Court in Roper and Graham, the ABA urged that the
Court adopt a categorical rule barring life in prison without parole for
juveniles. Id. at *6–7.
The ABA added two additional observations based “on its study,
research and experience of its members.” Id. at *13. First, the ABA
stressed that “juveniles are less capable than adults of communicating
35
with and giving meaningful assistance to their counsel.” Id. Second, the
ABA observed that “juveniles convicted of murder in the United States
were more likely to enter prison with a life without parole sentence than
adult murder offenders.” Id. In conclusion, the ABA stressed that it was
not asserting that all juveniles should be entitled to parole, but only that
they should not be denied the opportunity to be considered for parole
before they die in prison. Id. at *23.
The brief of the APA addressed the inability of professionals to
predict the course of juvenile development. APA Brief at *21. The APA
brief bluntly stated that “[t]he positive predictive power of juvenile
psychotherapy assessments . . . remains poor.” Id. The APA cited a
research study that found only sixteen percent of the young adolescents
who scored in the top fifth on a juvenile psychopathy measurement tool
would eventually be assessed as psychopathic at age twenty-four. Id.
Another study that attempted to use psychological testing to predict
future homicide offenders yielded a very high false positive rate of eighty-
seven percent. Id. at *22. According to the APA, “those who have
dedicated their careers to identifying risk factors associated with
persistent criminality” acknowledge the “very imperfect predictions of
which offense trajectory individuals will follow over time” and warn
against the “danger that policy makers will start to use less than good
predictions as a rationale for harsh punishments and severe legal
sanctions.” Id. (quoting Rolf Loeber et al., Violence and Serious Theft:
Development and Prediction from Childhood to Adulthood 333 (2008)).
Yet, the Supreme Court in Miller stopped short of a categorical
rule. See Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 424
(“Although we do not foreclose a sentencer’s ability to make [a life-
without-the-possibility-of-parole] judgment in homicide cases, we require
36
it to take into account how children are different, and how those
differences counsel against irrevocably sentencing them to a lifetime in
prison.”). In Miller, the Supreme Court recognized the applicability of
Roper–Graham principles to juvenile homicide offenders, noting that the
differences between children and adults “diminish the penological
justifications for imposing the harshest sentences on juvenile offenders,
even when they commit terrible crimes.” Id. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2465,
183 L. Ed. 2d at 419. The Miller Court, like the Court in Graham and
Roper, recognized the difficulty in distinguishing “between ‘the juvenile
offender whose crime reflects unfortunate yet transient immaturity, and
the rare juvenile offender whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.’ ”
Id. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 424 (quoting Roper, 543
U.S. at 573, 125 S. Ct. at 1183, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 24).
Yet, the Miller Court did not reach the question of whether a
categorical ban was required. Id. Instead, the Court reserved judgment
on the categorical approach, noting ambiguously that “appropriate
occasions,” possibly including parole hearings and posttrial proceedings,
“for sentencing juveniles to this harshest possible penalty will be
uncommon.” Id.
Finally, the Supreme Court recently has provided further
illumination of the contours of its cruel and unusual punishment
jurisprudence in Montgomery, 577 U.S. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 718, 193
L. Ed. 2d at 599. In Montgomery, the Court considered whether the
decision in Miller applied retroactively to cases on collateral review. Id. at
___, 136 S. Ct. at 725, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 610. The Court concluded that
its holding in Miller should be given retroactive effect because Miller
announced a substantive rule of law excluding a category of punishment
from a class of offenders. Id. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 736, 193 L. Ed. 2d at
37
622. The Montgomery Court stressed that Miller barred life in prison
without the possibility of parole for “all but the rarest of juvenile
offenders, those whose crimes reflect permanent incorrigibility.” Id. at
___, 136 S. Ct. at 734, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 620. The Court emphasized that
Miller applied retroactively because it was based upon the risk that “the
vast majority of juvenile offenders” face a punishment that the law
cannot impose upon them, namely, life without possibility of parole. Id.
at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 734, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 620.
The Court noted that giving retroactive effect to Miller did not
require states to relitigate sentences “in every case where a juvenile
offender received mandatory life without parole.” Id. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at
736, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 622. Citing a Wyoming statute, the Court
emphasized that a state may remedy Miller violations by permitting
juvenile offenders to be considered for parole. Id. Allowing offenders to
be considered for parole “ensures that juveniles whose crimes reflected
only transient immaturity—and who have since matured—will not be
forced to serve a disproportionate sentence in violation of the Eighth
Amendment.” Id. The Court held that extending parole eligibility to
juvenile offenders does not impose an onerous burden on the states. Id.
Those persons who show an “inability to reform will continue to serve life
sentences.” Id. But, the Court emphasized, under a life-with-parole
approach “[t]he opportunity for release will be afforded to those who
demonstrate the truth of Miller’s central intuition—that children who
commit even heinous crimes are capable of change.” Id.
5. Summary of principles of United States Supreme Court cases
involving juveniles facing death or life in prison. As is apparent, the
United States Supreme Court’s approach to the Eighth Amendment has
evolved substantially in recent years. The Supreme Court’s current
38
approach to the Eighth Amendment’s Cruel and Unusual Punishment
Clause in the context of juvenile offenders may be summarized as
follows:
i. Juveniles are constitutionally different than adults for purposes
of sentencing. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2464, 183 L. Ed. 2d
at 418; Graham, 560 U.S. at 68, 130 S. Ct. at 2026, 176 L. Ed. 2d at
841; Roper, 543 U.S. at 569–71, 125 S. Ct. at 1195–96, 161 L. Ed. 2d at
21–22.
ii. Because of these differences, ordinary criminal culpability is
diminished when the offender is a youth, and the penological objectives
behind harsh sentences are diminished. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132
S. Ct. at 2465, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 419; Graham, 560 U.S. at 74, 130 S. Ct.
at 2030, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 845; Roper, 543 U.S. at 571, 125 S. Ct. at
1196, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 22; cf. Atkins, 536 U.S. at 316, 122 S. Ct. at
2250, 153 L. Ed. 2d at 348.
iii. The traits of youth that diminish ordinary criminal culpability
are not crime specific and are present even in juveniles who commit
heinous crimes. Montgomery, 577 U.S. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 735–36, 193
L. Ed. 2d at 621–22; Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2465, 183 L.
Ed. 2d at 420.
iv. Imposition of life in prison without parole shares some of the
characteristics with death sentences that are shared by no other
sentences. Life without the possibility of parole is “a forfeiture that is
irrevocable,” depriving the convict of the most basic liberties without
hope of restoration except in the remote possibility of executive clemency.
Life in prison is especially harsh for juveniles, who will almost inevitably
serve more years and a greater percentage of life in prison than adult
offenders. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2466, 183 L. Ed. 2d at
39
421; Graham, 560 U.S. at 69–70, 130 S. Ct. at 2027, 176 L. Ed. 2d at
842.
v. The qualities that distinguish juveniles from adults do not
disappear when an individual turns eighteen, but society has generally
drawn the line at eighteen for the purposes of distinguishing juveniles
from adults. Graham, 560 U.S. at 74–75, 130 S. Ct. at 2030, 176
L. Ed. 2d at 845; Roper, 543 U.S. at 574, 125 S. Ct. at 1197, 161
L. Ed. 2d at 24.
vi. Because the signature qualities of youth are transient,
incorrigibility is inconsistent with youth. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132
S. Ct. at 2465, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 419; Graham, 560 U.S. at 73, 130 S. Ct.
at 2029, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 844; Roper, 543 U.S. at 570, 125 S. Ct. at
1195, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 22.
vii. While juveniles who prove irredeemably corrupt may be
subject to life in prison, “appropriate occasions” for sentencing juveniles
to this harshest possible penalty will be “uncommon” or “rare.”
Montgomery, 577 U.S. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 733–34, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 619;
Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 424.
viii. Even trained and experienced professionals find it very
difficult to predict which youthful offenders might ultimately fit into this
small group of incorrigible offenders. Graham, 560 U.S. at 72–73, 130
S. Ct. at 2029, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 844; Roper, 543 U.S. at 573, 125 S. Ct.
at 1197, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 24.
ix. An unacceptable likelihood exists that the brutality or cold-
blooded nature of a particular crime will overcome mitigating arguments
based on youth when the objective immaturity, vulnerability, and lack of
true depravity should require a lesser sentence. Graham, 560 U.S. at
40
77–78, 130 S. Ct. at 2032, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 847; Roper, 543 U.S. at 573,
125 S. Ct. at 1197, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 24.
x. Juveniles are less able to provide meaningful assistance to their
lawyers than adults, a factor that can impact the development of the
defense and gives rise to a risk of erroneous conclusions regarding
juvenile culpability. Graham, 560 U.S. at 78, 130 S. Ct. at 2032, 176
L. Ed. 2d at 847–48; cf. Atkins, 536 U.S. at 320, 122 S. Ct. at 2252, 153
L. Ed. 2d at 350.
xi. Because of the transient characteristics of youth that diminish
criminal culpability, life-without-the-possibility-of-parole sentences
“pose[] too great a risk” of disproportionate punishment. Miller, 567 U.S.
at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 424.
xii. Accurate assessment of whether a youth is incorrigible is
particularly important when a sentence of life in prison is involved,
because such sentences share some of the characteristics of death
sentences―characteristics that are shared by no other sentences. Miller,
567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2466–67, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 421–22;
Graham, 560 U.S. at 69–70, 130 S. Ct. at 2027, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 842.
xiii. Even if the state’s judgment that a juvenile offender is
incorrigible is later corroborated by prison misbehavior or failure to
mature, the sentence was still disproportionate because that judgment
was made at the outset. Graham, 560 U.S. at 73, 130 S. Ct. at 2029,
176 L. Ed. 2d at 844–45.
xiv. Even if life in prison without the possibility of parole at the
time of sentence is no longer available, nothing guarantees that a
juvenile offender will be entitled to release. Graham, 560 U.S. at 75, 130
S. Ct. at 2030, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 845–46.
41
C. Iowa Supreme Court Precedents.
1. Relationship between state and federal law. We, of course,
follow the decisions of the United States Supreme Court interpreting the
Federal Constitution, and they are binding upon us on questions of
federal law. Thus, in Iowa, the United States Constitution as interpreted
by the Supreme Court prevents the state from imposing life without the
possibility of parole in most homicide cases involving juveniles. If life
without the possibility of parole may be imposed at all under federal law,
which is unclear at this point, it may be imposed only in cases where
irretrievable corruption has been demonstrated by the “rarest” of juvenile
offenders. Montgomery, 577 U.S. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 734, 193 L. Ed. 2d
at 620.
In any event, the rulings of the United States Supreme Court
create a floor, but not a ceiling, when we are called upon to interpret
parallel provisions of the Iowa Constitution. In interpreting provisions of
the Iowa Constitution, we may find federal authority persuasive, but it is
certainly not binding. In the development of our own state constitutional
analysis, we may look to decisions of the United States Supreme Court,
dissenting opinions of the Supreme Court, cases from other states, and
other persuasive authorities. State v. Short, 851 N.W.2d 474, 481 (Iowa
2014); State v. Ochoa, 792 N.W.2d 260, 267 (Iowa 2010).
2. Recent Iowa caselaw utilizing Roper–Graham–Miller principles.
We now turn to Iowa cases in which we considered the application of
Roper–Graham–Miller reasoning under article I, section 17 of the Iowa
Constitution. 5 See Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 553–57; Lyle, 854 N.W.2d at
5The Iowa Constitution provides, “Excessive bail shall not be required; excessive
fines shall not be imposed, and cruel and unusual punishment shall not be inflicted.”
Iowa Const. art. I, § 17. The Eighth Amendment to the United States Constitution
42
384–86; Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at 113–17; Pearson, 836 N.W.2d at 95–97;
Null, 836 N.W.2d at 50–51, 60–66. In these cases, we primarily
embraced the reasoning in the United States Supreme Court’s trilogy
under the Iowa Constitution but also built upon it and extended its
principles. See Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 553–57; Lyle, 854 N.W.2d at 383–
84; Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at 113–17; Pearson, 836 N.W.2d at 95–98; Null,
836 N.W.2d at 70.
Our Iowa constitutional cases elaborate on the Roper–Graham–
Miller trilogy in several important ways. We emphasized in Pearson and
Null that immaturity, impetuosity, and poor risk assessment are to be
treated as mitigating, not aggravating factors, in sentencing. Pearson,
836 N.W.2d at 97; Null, 836 N.W.2d at 75. In Ragland, Pearson, and
Null, we extended the reasoning of the Roper–Graham–Miller trilogy to
require individualized hearings in cases involving long prison sentences
for juvenile defendants short of life in prison without the possibility of
parole. Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at 122; Pearson, 836 N.W.2d at 97; Null,
836 N.W.2d at 76–77. In Lyle, we noted that death is no longer
irreconcilably different for juveniles and extended the requirement of an
individualized hearing when sentencing juveniles for lesser crimes for
which the legislature has prescribed mandatory adult sentences. 854
N.W.2d at 396–98; see also Bruegger, 773 N.W.2d at 883–84 (applying
Roper concepts outside the death-penalty context).
Last term we decided Seats. In Seats, we reviewed the developing
jurisprudence regarding life sentences for juvenile homicide offenders.
865 N.W.2d at 553–57. As in Miller and our prior cases, we reserved the
provides, “Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel
and unusual punishments inflicted.” U.S. Const. amend. VIII.
43
question of whether life sentences without the possibility of parole should
be categorically barred. Id. at 558. Instead, we noted that if a life
sentence without parole could ever be imposed on a juvenile offender, the
burden was on the state to show that an individual offender manifested
“irreparable corruption.” Id. at 556 (quoting Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132
S. Ct. at 2469, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 424). In making such a determination,
we noted that findings of such irreparable corruption should be “rare and
uncommon.” Id. at 555. We thus concluded the presumption for any
sentencing judge is that a juvenile should be sentenced to life with the
possibility of parole even for homicide offenses. Id. In considering
whether the state had overcome the presumption, we observed that the
district court was required to recognize that “children are constitutionally
different from adults.” Id. at 556 (quoting Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132
S. Ct. at 2464, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 418). Specifically, the district court
must consider “the family and home environment that surrounds” the
juvenile, including “childhood abuse, parental neglect, personal and
family drug or alcohol abuse, prior exposure to violence, lack of parental
supervision, lack of an adequate education, and the juvenile’s
susceptibility to psychological or emotional damage.” Id. (first quoting
Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2468, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 423).
In addition, the district court must consider the nature of the
offense “including the extent of [the juvenile’s] participation in the
conduct and the way the familial and peer pressures may have affected
[the juvenile],” and whether “substance abuse played a role in the
juvenile’s commission of the crime.” Id. (first quoting Miller, 567 U.S. at
___, 132 S. Ct. at 2468, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 423). Finally, we stressed the
district court must recognize that “ ‘[j]uveniles are more capable of
change than are adults’ and that as a result, ‘their actions are less likely
44
to be evidence of “irretrievably depraved character.” ’ ” Id. (quoting
Graham, 560 U.S. at 68, 130 S. Ct. at 2026, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 841). We
cited Null for the proposition that because “incorrigibility is inconsistent
with youth, care should be taken to avoid irrevocable judgment about [an
offender’s] place in society.” Id. (quoting Null, 836 N.W.2d at 75).
3. Summary of Iowa cases applying Roper–Graham–Miller
principles. Based on our recent cases, we distill the following principles:
i. We have generally accepted the principles enunciated by the
United States Supreme Court in the Roper–Graham–Miller trilogy in our
interpretation of article I, section 17 of the Iowa Constitution. See Seats,
865 N.W.2d at 555–57; Null, 836 N.W.2d at 70–76.
ii. We have regarded the constitutional holding in Miller as applied
by this court under article I, section 17 as broadly substantive and not
narrowly procedural, a view subsequently adopted by the United States
Supreme Court under the Eighth Amendment in Montgomery. See State
v. Louisell, 865 N.W.2d 590, 594 (Iowa 2015); Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at
114–16.
iii. Using our independent judgment under article I, section 17,
we have applied the principles of the Roper–Graham–Miller trilogy outside
the narrow factual confines of those cases, including cases involving de
facto life sentences, very long sentences, and relatively short sentences.
See Lyle, 854 N.W.2d at 402–03; Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at 122; Null, 836
N.W.2d at 71–72.
D. Application.
1. Categorical rules vs. case-by-case basis. Sweet asks us to adopt
a categorical rule, namely, that juvenile offenders may never be
sentenced to life without the possibility of parole. See Graham, 560 U.S.
at 77, 139 S. Ct. 2032, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 847 (doubting “that courts
45
taking a case-by-case . . . approach could with sufficient accuracy
distinguish the few incorrigible juvenile offenders from the many that
have the capacity for change”); Roper, 543 U.S. at 573, 125 S. Ct. at
1197, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 24 (“It is difficult even for expert psychologists to
differentiate between the juvenile offender whose crime reflects
unfortunate yet transient immaturity, and the rare juvenile offender
whose crime reflects irreparable corruption.”). In our earlier cases,
however, we found it unnecessary to address this larger proposition. See
Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 558; Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at 122; Null, 836 N.W.2d
at 76.
We could continue to opt for the narrower, more incremental
approach, by simply addressing the question of whether the State proved
in this case that Sweet is one of the “extremely rare” juveniles who is
“irredeemably corrupt.” Such a minimalist approach would allow for the
development of additional caselaw before the larger categorical issue is
confronted. Based on our experience and the caselaw developments, we
think there is little to be gained by allowing further caselaw development
on the question of whether a juvenile may ever receive a sentence of life
without the possibility of parole.
The Supreme Court in Roper and its progeny has declared that for
juvenile offenders the opportunity for parole can be denied, if at all, only
to “irretrievably depraved” 6 or irreparably corrupt juvenile offenders. See
Roper, 543 U.S. at 570, 125 S. Ct. at 1195, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 22. The
Court further narrowed the window of potential situations involving life
in prison without the possibility of parole in Montgomery, 577 U.S. at ___,
6Thephrase “irretrievably depraved” debuted in Roper, 543 U.S. at 570, 125
S. Ct. at 1195, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 22, and reappeared in Graham, 560 U.S. at 68, 130
S. Ct. at 2026, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 841.
46
136 S. Ct. at 736, 193 L. Ed.2d at 622. In light of Miller, as elaborated
by Montgomery, the United States Constitution allows life without the
possibility of parole for juveniles, if at all, only in “the rarest” of cases.
Id. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 726, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 726. Thus, the United
States Supreme Court, under the Federal Constitution, has preserved life
without the possibility of parole for juveniles, even those who commit
heinous crime, only for a very small category of cases. And, the
suggestion in Montgomery that the states could avoid constitutional
questions by adopting statutes that do not impose life without the
possibility of parole for juvenile offenders indicates that this narrow
exception may be rapidly closing under federal law. See id. at ___, 136
S. Ct. at 736, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 622.
So, the Supreme Court has already established that except in very
rare cases, life without the possibility of parole is not available under the
Federal Constitution even for heinous crimes committed by juvenile
offenders. The only marginal issue remaining under the Iowa
Constitution is whether we should continue to reserve the possibility that
a juvenile offender may be identified as “irretrievable” at the time of
sentencing, or whether that determination must be made by the parole
board at a later time after the offender’s juvenile brain has been fully
developed and a behavior pattern established by a substantial period of
incarceration. If the death-penalty jurisprudence developed after Furman
has any application to cases involving life in prison without parole, the
process for making the determination of which offenders are most
culpable would be resource intensive, require expert testimony, and
would not be a matter left to the unguided discretion of the sentencer.
2. Consideration of categorical approach. In considering whether
to adopt a categorical approach to the class of offenders or offenses
47
under the cruel and unusual punishment clause of the Iowa
Constitution, we have referred to the two-step process found in the cases
of the United States Supreme Court. Applying this test, we look to
whether there is a consensus, or at least an emerging consensus, to
guide the court’s consideration of the question. Second, we exercise our
independent judgment to determine whether to follow a categorical
approach. Lyle, 854 N.W.2d at 386.
In considering the question of consensus, we note the United
States Supreme Court has emphasized that its decisions impose a
nationwide standard on all the states and that its decisions limit the
range of options available for states in a federalist system. In considering
its cruel and unusual punishment jurisprudence, the Court has
emphasized this federalism consideration. See Gregg, 428 U.S. at 186–
87, 96 S. Ct. at 2931, 49 L. Ed. 2d at 882. For us, however, these
federalism concerns are entirely absent.
In any event, there is an argument that a consensus does, in fact,
exist even under the standards of the United States Supreme Court. For
example, an amicus brief in Montgomery noted that after Miller was
decided, nine states have abolished life-without-the-possibility-of-parole
sentences for juveniles, thereby establishing a clear direction toward
abolition of the life-in-prison death penalty for juveniles. Brief for
Charles Hamilton Houston Inst. for Race & Justice & Criminal Justice
Inst. as Amici Curiae Supporting Neither Party, Montgomery, 577 U.S.
___, 136 S. Ct. 718, 193 L. Ed. 2d 599 (No. 14–280), 2015 WL 4624172,
at *4–5 [hereinafter Charles Hamilton Houstin Brief]. Further, many of
the states that do allow life in prison for juveniles do so only through
statutes that allow the transfer of juveniles to adult court. See Graham,
560 U.S. at 67, 130 S. Ct. at 2025–26, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 840–41. The
48
amicus brief noted that since Miller, the number of juveniles actually
sentenced to life without the possibility of parole has dramatically
decreased—describing thirteen additional states as having functionally
barred the practice. Charles Hamilton Houston Brief, at *7–10.
In addition, various professional groups urge that we categorically
bar life-in-prison-without-parole sentences for juveniles. The Supreme
Court has recognized the role of such groups in evaluating cruel and
unusual punishment claims. See Graham, 560 U.S. at 68, 130 S. Ct. at
2026–27, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 841–42; Roper, 543 U.S. at 573, 125 S. Ct. at
1197, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 24. Finally, as noted by the ABA in its amicus
brief for Miller, the United States is the only country in the world to
impose life in prison without the possibility of parole on its juvenile
offenders. ABA Brief at *24.
Yet, many states have sanctioned life in prison without parole for
juvenile murder offenders. And, while one post-Miller state supreme
court categorically barred life in prison without possibility of parole for
juveniles under its state constitution, Diatchenko v. District Attorney, 1
N.E.3d 270, 276 (Mass. 2013), several other state supreme courts, over
strong dissents, have come to the opposite conclusion. See, e.g., Bun v.
State, 769 S.E.2d 381, 383–84 (Ga. 2015), disapproved on other grounds
by Veal v. State, ___ S.E.2d ___, ___, 2016 WL 1085360, at *9 (Ga.
Mar. 21, 2016); Conley v. State, 972 N.E.2d 864, 879–80 (Ind. 2012);
State v. Houston, 353 P.3d 55, 76–77 (Utah 2015).
All this gives us pause. Yet, while we regard evidence of consensus
on the general proposition that “youth are different” is not subject to
dispute, we do not find a consensus today on the very narrow question
before us: whether the small number of juvenile offenders convicted of
murder may be sentenced at time of trial to life in prison without the
49
possibility of parole or whether such a determination must be made at a
later date by a parole board.
The fact that we have not found a consensus, however, does not
end the inquiry. Although examination of statutes, sentencing practices,
professional opinion, and other sources may inform our analysis, in the
end we must make an independent judgment. See, e.g., Graham, 560
U.S. at 61, 130 S. Ct. at 2022, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 837 (“[T]he Court must
determine in the exercise of its own independent judgment whether the
punishment in question violates the Constitution.”); Kennedy, 554 U.S.
at 421, 128 S. Ct. at 2650, 171 L. Ed. 2d at 539–40 (“Consensus is not
dispositive” but the outcome “depends on the standards elaborated by
controlling precedents, and on the Court’s own understanding and
interpretation of the Eighth Amendment’s text, history, meaning, and
purpose.”); Roper, 543 U.S. at 564, 125 S. Ct. at 1192, 161 L. Ed. 2d at
18 (“We then must determine, in the exercise of our own independent
judgment, whether the death penalty is a disproportionate punishment
for juveniles.”); Atkins, 536 U.S. at 321, 122 S. Ct. at 2252, 153 L. Ed. 2d
at 350 (independently evaluating whether death is a suitable punishment
for an intellectually disabled criminal). In Miller, for instance, the
Supreme Court did not believe a demonstration of community consensus
was necessary but simply demonstrated that there was no consensus
contrary to the result advanced by the Court. Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132
S. Ct. at 2471–73, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 425–29.
We find our approach in Lyle instructive. In that case, we made it
clear that the existence or nonexistence of a consensus did not relieve
this court of its duty to exercise independent judgment. Lyle, 854
N.W.2d at 387. In Lyle, we extended application of the Roper–Graham–
50
Miller principles to mandatory minimum adult prison terms imposed on
juveniles. Id. at 402.
In reviewing the caselaw development, we believe, in the exercise of
our independent judgment, that the enterprise of identifying which
juvenile offenders are irretrievable at the time of trial is simply too
speculative and likely impossible given what we now know about the
timeline of brain development and related prospects for self-regulation
and rehabilitation. We agree with the observation in Graham that the
sentencing task is undertaken by trial judges “who seek with diligence
and professionalism to take into account the human existence of the
offender and the just demands of a wronged society.” Graham, 560 U.S.
at 77, 130 S. Ct. at 2031, 176 L. Ed. 2d at 847. But a district court at
the time of trial cannot apply the Miller factors in any principled way to
identify with assurance those very few adolescent offenders that might
later be proven to be irretrievably depraved. In short, we are asking the
sentencer to do the impossible, namely, to determine whether the
offender is “irretrievably corrupt” at a time when even trained
professionals with years of clinical experience would not attempt to make
such a determination.
No structural or procedural approach, including a provision of a
death-penalty-type legal defense, will cure this fundamental problem. As
can be seen in the caselaw, the United States Supreme Court has
struggled between categorical and case-by-case approaches involving the
death-penalty and life-without-the-possibility-of-parole sentences.
Generally, a case-by-case approach is only permitted in death-penalty
cases when the sentencer has adequate information and the risk of an
arbitrary application is minimized by substantive and procedural
standards. But here, in imposing a sanction akin to the death penalty in
51
some respects, the trial court simply will not have adequate information
and the risk of error is unacceptably high, even if we were to require an
intensive, highly structured inquiry similar to that required by the ABA
guidelines for the defense of death-penalty cases.
The Court’s reasoning in Roper, foreshadowed the fallacy of the
predictive enterprise later narrowly reserved in Miller. In Roper, the
Court concluded the death penalty is cruel and unusual for juvenile
offenders under the Eighth Amendment—without regard to the
heinousness of their crimes—because an emerging consensus in
neuroscience has revealed the human brain is not fully developed until
the early to mid-twenties. Roper, 543 U.S. at 568–74, 125 S. Ct. at
1194–98, 161 L. Ed. 2d at 21–25; see also Laurence Steinberg, Age of
Opportunity: Lessons from the New Science of Adolescence 71 (2014)
[hereinafter Steinberg] (suggesting the brain’s prefrontal cortex and the
limbic system become more interconnected during the third and final
phase of brain development). In the third and final phase of brain
development extending into the early twenties, humans “get better at
controlling their impulses, thinking about the long-term consequences of
their decisions, and resisting peer pressure.” Steinberg at 71. This
phenomenon of brain development explains why adolescents can
demonstrate intellectual promise 7 and utilize a robust vocabulary while
lacking sound judgment and exhibiting poor self-regulation. Put another
7The sentencing court observed that Sweet recited his rights during an
interrogation and showed signs of average to above average intelligence. The ability to
recite one’s rights, however, does not necessarily establish one’s mature understanding
of them or demonstrate maturity of judgment. Steinberg provides a reminder of this
distinction by rhetorically asking, “If adolescents are so smart, why do they do such
stupid things?” Steinberg at 69. The answer, Steinberg tells us, “has to do with how
their brains develop.” Id.
52
way, the timeline of brain development explains why smart adolescents
sometimes do really stupid things. Id. at 69.
While not without some value, we think the fact that an offender is
approaching the age of eighteen is not a very helpful factor in
determining who fits the narrow group of irretrievably depraved
defenders. We have noted that “the fact . . . a defendant is nearing the
age of eighteen does not undermine the teachings of Miller.” Seats, 865
N.W.2d at 557. The features of youth identified in Roper and Graham
simply do not magically disappear at age seventeen—or eighteen for that
matter. See Elizabeth S. Scott & Laurence Steinberg, Rethinking Juvenile
Justice 60 (2008) (“[S]ubstantial psychological maturation takes place in
middle and late adolescence and even into early adulthood.”); see also
Null, 836 N.W.2d at 55 (“[T]he human brain continues to mature into the
early twenties.”). While older teenagers may show greater intellectual
development, that is not the same as the maturity of judgment necessary
for imposing adult culpability. As Steinberg asks rhetorically, “If
adolescents are so smart, why do they do such stupid things?” Steinberg
at 69. We thus do not find chronological age is a reliable factor that can
be applied by the district court to identify those uncommon juveniles
that may merit life without the possibility of parole.
Another factor suggested in Miller—the offender’s family and home
environment—is also fraught with risks. For example, what significance
should a sentencing court attach to a juvenile offender’s stable home
environment? Would the fact that the adolescent offender failed to
benefit from a comparatively positive home environment suggest he or
she is irreparable and an unlikely candidate for rehabilitation? Or
conversely, would the offender’s experience with a stable home
environment suggest that his or her character and personality have not
53
been irreparably damaged and prospects for rehabilitation are therefore
greater? See Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 561–62 (Hecht, J., concurring
specially) (suggesting a sentencing court cannot predict the answers to
these extremely challenging questions with reasonable certainty).
A similar quandary faces courts sentencing juvenile offenders who
have experienced horrendous abuse and neglect or otherwise have been
deprived of a stable home environment. Should the offenders’ resulting
profound character deficits and deep-seated wounds count against the
prospects for rehabilitation and in favor of life-without-the-possibility-of-
parole sentences under the Miller framework? Or should sentencing
courts view the deprivation of a stable home environment as a
contraindication for life without the possibility of parole because only
time will tell whether maturation will come with age and treatment in a
structured environment? See Louisell, 865 N.W.2d at 592–95 (describing
an inmate with a difficult and chaotic childhood who committed first-
degree murder at age seventeen but made remarkable progress toward
maturity and rehabilitation during twenty-six years in prison).
Social science suggests reliable answers to these questions come
only with the benefit of time and completion of brain development. Why,
then, should we empower sentencing courts to make final decisions on
opportunities for parole before the juvenile offenders’ prospects for
rehabilitation are reliably known? There is, after all, plenty of time to
make such determinations later for juvenile offenders like Sweet who are
sentenced to life in prison for first-degree murder.
Because of the difficulty of applying the individual Miller factors,
the likelihood that the multifactor test can be consistently applied by our
district courts is doubtful at best. The APA in Miller in an amicus brief
emphasized that professional psychologists could not predict who was
54
irretrievable. APA Brief at *21. We should not ask our district court
judges to predict future prospects for maturation and rehabilitation when
highly trained professionals say such predictions are impossible.
In sum, we conclude that sentencing courts should not be required
to make speculative up-front decisions on juvenile offenders’ prospects
for rehabilitation because they lack adequate predictive information
supporting such a decision. The parole board will be better able to
discern whether the offender is irreparably corrupt after time has passed,
after opportunities for maturation and rehabilitation have been provided,
and after a record of success or failure in the rehabilitative process is
available. See Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 557 (“Even if the judge sentences
the juvenile to life in prison with parole, it does not mean the parole
board will release the juvenile from prison.”); see also State v. Andrews,
329 S.W.3d 369, 379 (Mo. 2010) (Wolff, J., dissenting) (noting an
offender sentenced to life with parole may nonetheless “spend the rest of
his life in prison if the parole board does not determine that he is
suitable for parole release”). Steinberg has poignantly made this very
point:
It’s not only adolescents’ immature judgment that
demands that we treat them differently when they break the
law. If the plasticity of the adolescent brain makes juveniles
more amenable to rehabilitation, this argues against
mandatory life sentences that don’t allow courts to consider
whether an impulsive or impressionable teenager might grow
into a law-abiding adult who can control his impulses and
stand up to peer pressure. Of course, a teenager who kills
another person deliberately should be punished—no one is
arguing otherwise. But should he be incarcerated for the
rest of his life, with no chance to prove that he has matured?
Steinberg at 188. Thus, juvenile offenders’ prospects for rehabilitation
augur forcefully against speculative, up-front determinations of
opportunities for parole and leads inexorably to the categorical
55
elimination of life-without-the-possibility-of-parole sentences for juvenile
offenders.
For the above reasons, we adopt a categorical rule that juvenile
offenders may not be sentenced to life without the possibility of parole
under article I, section 17 of the Iowa Constitution. As a result, the
sentence of the district court in this case is vacated and the matter
remanded to the district court for resentencing.
Nothing in this opinion, of course, suggests that a juvenile offender
is entitled to parole. The State is not required to make such a guarantee,
and those who over time show irredeemable corruption will no doubt
spend their lives in prison. The determination of irredeemable
corruption, however, must be made when the information is available to
make that determination and not at a time when the juvenile character is
a work in progress.
IV. Conclusion.
For the above reasons, we conclude a sentence of life without the
possibility of parole for a juvenile offender violates article I, section 17 of
the Iowa Constitution. The sentence imposed by the district court is
reversed, and the case is remanded for resentencing consistent with this
opinion.
DISTRICT COURT SENTENCE REVERSED AND CASE
REMANDED WITH INSTRUCTIONS.
Cady, C.J., and Wiggins and Hecht, JJ., join this opinion. Cady,
C.J., and Wiggins, J., file separate concurring opinions. Mansfield, J.,
files a dissenting opinion in which Waterman and Zager, JJ., join. Zager,
J., files a separate dissenting opinion in which Waterman and Mansfield,
JJ., join.
56
#14–0455, State v. Sweet
CADY, Chief Justice (concurring specially).
I concur in the opinion of the court. I agree the new statutory
scheme adopted by our legislature for sentencing juvenile offenders
convicted of first-degree murder to life without the possibility of parole
violates the cruel and unusual punishment clause. See Iowa Const. art.
I, § 17. However, I write separately to express my opinion that the
statutory scheme is unconstitutional only because it does not permit the
sentencing court to retain jurisdiction to reconsider a sentencing
decision that denies eligibility for parole once full brain development had
occurred.
The constitutional deficiencies in mandatory life-without-parole
sentences for juvenile offenders first observed in Miller v. Alabama, 567
U.S. ___, ___, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 2471, 183 L. Ed. 2d 407, 426 (2012), are
not removed when the hearing provided to overcome those deficiencies
occurs long before one of the most critical characteristics of youth has
unfolded to enable courts to fully assess and consider that characteristic.
A constitutionally mandated hearing must be meaningful. A hearing to
determine whether a juvenile offender should spend his or her entire life
in prison is not meaningful as a final decision when it occurs before
brain development is completed and before the court is able to best
understand and assess the possibility of rehabilitation.
The problem we identify today with the current sentencing scheme
was not observed when the constitutional necessity for a hearing first
surfaced in Miller. Instead, we initially addressed the excessive nature of
lengthy mandatory sentences in the context of diminished juvenile
capacity. See State v. Ragland, 836 N.W.2d 107, 121–22 (Iowa 2013)
(finding a sixty-year mandatory minimum as part of a life sentence to be
57
the functional equivalent of life without parole); see also State v. Pearson,
836 N.W.2d 88, 96 (Iowa 2013) (holding a thirty-five-year minimum
ignored the diminished culpability of juveniles); State v. Null, 836 N.W.2d
41, 70–71 (Iowa 2013) (finding a mandatory fifty-two and a half year
minimum on a term of years sentence to violate the Miller principles). In
the process, we established the requirements for a resentencing hearing
using the Supreme Court guidance from Miller. See Ragland, 836
N.W.2d at 115 & n.6. The legislature promptly responded by amending
the statute to provide for a hearing and a detailed list of circumstances
for the court to consider. See 2015 Iowa Acts ch. 65, §§ 1–2 (codified at
Iowa Code § 902.1(2)–(3)). The amendment addressed the constitutional
deficiency identified in Miller and in our cases that followed.
Yet, we now observe an inherent deficiency in the information
available when sentencing juvenile offenders in the first instance. In
particular, a juvenile offender who is resentenced based on evidence of
rehabilitation acquired after full brain development has occurred may
present a far better case for parole than an offender who has not
completed brain development. Compare State v. Louisell, 865 N.W.2d
590, 594–95 (Iowa 2015) (describing numerous achievements
accomplished over twenty-six years in prison to show she was
rehabilitated at age forty six), with Null, 836 N.W.2d at 45–46, 76–77
(resentencing occurring at age twenty, three years into his sentence).
Judicial review tends to develop the law incrementally, and in
taking this next step now, our obligation is to again apply the
constitutional standard of cruel and unusual punishment to the
circumstances we face. These circumstances disclose that it is cruel to
sentence a youthful offender to life without the possibility of parole at a
time when the juvenile has not even had the time to finish maturing.
58
While we strive to uphold the constitutionality of a statute when possible,
we do not follow this approach by lowering our expectations for justice or
accepting the imperfections we discover as an inevitable part of justice.
We must embrace each discovery in each step as an opportunity to bring
our law closer to our constitutional values, not find ways to avoid doing
so.
It is also important to keep in mind that speculation is inevitably
injected into judicial decision-making when judges are asked to make
decisions before all the necessary information has accumulated. In turn,
speculation only enhances the likelihood of inconsistent sentencing
decisions for those who have committed the same crime. This can lead
over time to patterns and outcomes that are often inconsistent with the
most basic notions of justice. These outcomes need to be curtailed to
better ensure fairness in our system of justice. Certainly, this fairness
could not be more important when dealing with the imposition of the
most severe punishment allowed by society on a child. Close enough can
never be good enough.
The decision by the court today is consistent with our
constitutional values and a positive step forward. It advances Iowa in an
important area of the law. Yet, the parole board does not need to be the
only entity standing between a juvenile offender and a lifetime of
imprisonment. The entire sentencing process will best consider the
interests of all in society when the final decision as to the eligibility of
parole is considered by a court after all relevant information is available.
Accordingly, if a juvenile offender is to be sentenced to life without
the possibility of parole the sentencing court must be given continuing
jurisdiction to consider a single subsequent request by the juvenile
offender for rehearing once brain development is completed. This
59
approach allows the juvenile offender a full and fair opportunity to show
rehabilitation potential and provides the court with a more complete
picture in weighing all the interests involved and determining whether
the offender is “incorrigible.” See Null, 836 N.W.2d at 63.
This approach mirrors the approach taken under the current
statute that allows courts to reconsider a sentence. See Iowa Code
§ 902.4 (2015) (allowing the court to reconsider a felony sentence within
the first year of conviction, excluding mandatory minimum sentences
and class “A” felonies). It would give the courts the information they
need for a fair evaluation and juvenile offenders the constitutional
protection they deserve. Of course, it should not be overlooked that the
decision of the court today also provides meaningful protection for the
youth of our state.
60
#14–0455, State v. Sweet
WIGGINS, Justice (concurring specially).
I firmly agree with and join the majority opinion. I write separately
to address points made in Justice Mansfield’s dissent.
The dissent contends our decision today means the parole board
will release every juvenile from prison at some point in the future. That
contention is nothing more than fearmongering. The Iowa Code sets
forth the standard the parole board must use in determining whether to
grant a parole. Iowa Code § 906.4(1) (2015). It provides,
A parole or work release shall be ordered only for the best
interest of society and the offender, not as an award of
clemency. The board shall release on parole or work release
any person whom it has the power to so release, when in its
opinion there is reasonable probability that the person can
be released without detriment to the community or to the
person. A person’s release is not a detriment to the
community or the person if the person is able and willing to
fulfill the obligations of a law-abiding citizen, in the board’s
determination.
Id. Not all juveniles, if any, will meet this standard. As we have
previously stated,
Even if the judge sentences the juvenile to life in prison with
parole, it does not mean the parole board will release the
juvenile from prison. Once the court sentences a juvenile to
life in prison with the possibility of parole, the decision to
release the juvenile is up to the parole board. If the parole
board does not find the juvenile is a candidate for release,
the juvenile may well end up serving his or her entire life in
prison.
State v. Seats, 865 N.W.2d 545, 557 (Iowa 2015) (citation omitted).
61
#14–0455, State v. Sweet
MANSFIELD, Justice (dissenting).
Recognizing that our legislature and our trial courts have the
primary role in determining criminal sentences, I would affirm the life-
without-parole (LWOP) sentence for this seventeen year old who
murdered his grandparents who had raised him.
Today, the court breaks new ground in finding that the Iowa
Constitution categorically forbids such sentences. As I will explain
below, I believe the justification offered by the majority for its ruling is
insufficient. More is needed before we strike down a legislatively
authorized sentence—especially one the general assembly reauthorized
by large majorities in both houses just last year.
The facts of this case, accompanied by the district court’s careful
exercise of its sentencing discretion, allow the LWOP sentence in this
particular case to be upheld. Regardless of my personal views on how
this defendant should be sentenced, I do not believe the sentence here is
unconstitutional because it violates the cruel and unusual punishment
clause of the United States or Iowa Constitutions.
I. No Categorical Bar Exists to LWOP Sentences.
To save time and pages, I will not repeat what I previously said in
my dissent in State v. Seats, 865 N.W.2d 545, 574–84 (Iowa 2015)
(Mansfield, J., dissenting). In that case, I discussed why I do not believe
either the United States Constitution or the Iowa Constitution
categorically prohibits the legislature from authorizing LWOP sentences
for juveniles who commit murder. Contrary to the court’s views today, I
do not believe this is a “marginal issue.” It matters to offenders, victims,
and communities. And it goes directly to the relationship between this
court and the elected branches of government. So without restating
62
what I said in Seats, let me explain my disagreement with the majority’s
analysis.
A. The United States Constitution. In Miller v. Alabama, the
United States Supreme Court decided that the Eighth Amendment to the
United States Constitution prohibits mandatory LWOP sentences for
juveniles who commit murder. 567 U.S. ___, ___, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 2469,
183 L. Ed. 2d 407, 424 (2012). However, it said that its decision “does
not categorically bar a penalty . . . . [I]t mandates only that a sentence
follow a certain process—considering an offender’s youth and attendant
characteristics—before imposing a particular penalty.” Id. at ___, 132
S. Ct. at 2471, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 426.
A few months ago, in Montgomery v. Louisiana, the United States
Supreme Court reiterated that LWOP sentences for juveniles were still
available in “rare” cases under the United States Constitution. 577 U.S.
___, ___, 136 S. Ct. 718, 733–34, 193 L. Ed. 2d 599, 619 (2016). To my
knowledge, no reported decision in this nation since Miller has held that
LWOP sentences for juvenile homicide offenders categorically violate the
United States Constitution. See Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 574 n.10
(gathering cases). In State v. Ragland, we concluded unanimously that
Miller “would seemingly permit life-without-parole sentences that are not
mandated by statute if the sentencing court has the power to consider
the attributes of youth in the mitigation of punishment.” 836 N.W.2d
107, 115 (Iowa 2013).
Nonetheless, today the court claims that Miller was “ambiguous[]”
as to whether it enacts a categorical bar on LWOP sentences for juvenile
murderers. This is based on the court’s novel reading of the following
clause in Miller: “[W]e think appropriate occasions for sentencing
juveniles to this harshest possible penalty will be uncommon.” See 567
63
U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 424. According to my
colleagues, Miller’s reference to “appropriate occasions” may actually be a
reference to “parole hearings or posttrial proceedings.” I must confess I
do not follow what the majority is saying here. It seems quite clear that
LWOP sentences for juvenile homicide offenders are permissible under
the United States Constitution so long the standards set forth in Miller
are complied with.
That was exactly the point of last year’s legislation enacted by a
vote of forty-seven to three in the Iowa Senate and eighty to eighteen in
the Iowa House. See 2015 Iowa Acts ch. 65 (to be codified at Iowa Code
§ 902.1(2)–(3)). Under that law, LWOP has ceased to be mandatory for
juveniles who commit first-degree murder. Id. However, it remains a
discretionary sentencing option following a consideration of relevant
factors. Id.
B. The Iowa Constitution. This leads me to the cruel and
unusual punishment clause in the Iowa Constitution, which has the
same wording as the Cruel and Unusual Punishment Clause in the
United States Constitution. Several sources of state constitutional
interpretation are relevant. For the most part, the majority either
disregards or gives short shrift to them.
As I pointed out in Seats, Iowa constitutional history does not
support the conclusion that an LWOP sentence for a juvenile murderer is
unconstitutional regardless of the circumstances. See Seats, 865 N.W.2d
at 575–77. Despite the length of its opinion, the court today does not
discuss the Iowa historical record at all.
This silence is significant because this court has invoked our
state’s constitutional history in other recent state constitutional
decisions. See, e.g., State v. Young, 863 N.W.2d 249, 277–79 (Iowa
64
2015); State v. Short, 851 N.W.2d 474, 482–85 (Iowa 2014). As was
stated in Chiodo v. Section 43.24 Panel, “We seek to interpret our
constitution consistent with the object sought to be obtained at the time
of adoption as disclosed by the circumstances.” 846 N.W.2d 845, 851
(Iowa 2014) (plurality opinion).
Another relevant consideration is how other states have interpreted
their own constitutions. See Young, 863 N.W.2d at 272 (“[I]n interpreting
our state constitution, the precedents of other states can be
instructive.”); City of Sioux City v. Jacobsma, 862 N.W.2d 335, 350–51
(Iowa 2015). Thus, post-Miller appellate decisions from other states
should be viewed as a helpful frame of reference.
Here the trend is one-sided: All but one out-of-state appellate
decisions have rejected the categorical challenge. See Seats, 865 N.W.2d
at 577–79. Notably, appellate courts from California, Georgia, Louisiana,
Indiana, Michigan, Minnesota, Pennsylvania, and Utah have all held
their states’ constitutions do not forbid LWOP sentences for juveniles
who commit murder. Id. An Illinois court and a New Jersey court
recently joined this list of state appellate courts that have rejected the
state constitutional challenge. See People v. Walker, ___ N.E.3d ___, ___,
2016 WL 1670178, at *5 (Ill. App. Ct. Apr. 25, 2016) (concluding that the
defendant “was sentenced at the discretion of the trial court” and his
LWOP sentence “does not violate the proportionate penalties clause [in
the Illinois Constitution]”); State v. Usry, Nos. 00–01–0166, 93–03–1078,
2016 WL 1092654, at *5 (N.J. Super. Ct. App. Div. Mar. 22, 2016)
(“[D]efendants’ argument that the New Jersey Constitution requires a
categorical ban on life-without-parole sentences for juvenile homicide
offenders is rejected.”). Only Massachusetts has reached a different
65
result. See Diatchenko v. Dist. Att’y, 1 N.E.3d 270, 276, 282–85 (Mass.
2013).
I discussed this caselaw in Seats. See 865 N.W.2d at 577–80. In
fairness, the court does give out-of-state caselaw one paragraph of
discussion today, although the court does not mention seven of the ten
jurisdictions that have rejected the categorical challenge.
Yet another relevant consideration, the majority acknowledges, is
whether there is a statewide or national consensus against LWOP
sentences for juveniles who commit murder. Significantly, the court
concedes there is no consensus against this punishment. However, the
court understates the matter. The reality is that there remains a
consensus in favor of continuing to make LWOP sentences available for
juvenile murderers. This is exemplified by the actions of our elected
representatives last year and by the similar actions of twenty-two other
states that have enacted post-Miller legislation continuing LWOP as a
sentencing option for juvenile homicide offenders. See Seats, 865
N.W.2d at 572 n.8. By contrast, only nine legislatures have made the
choice since Miller to eliminate LWOP. See id. n.6; 2016 S.D. Sess. Laws
ch. 121, § 2 (to be codified at S.D. Codified Laws § 22–6–1); 2016 Utah
Laws ch. 277, § 6 (to be codified at Utah Code § 76–3–209). So
consensus does not support the majority’s position.
What then are the court’s reasons for deciding that article I,
section 17 forbids LWOP sentences for juveniles who commit murder?
There is really just one reason. At the end of its opinion, the court says
that district courts “cannot apply the Miller factors in any principled way
to identify with assurance those very few adolescent offenders that might
later be proven to be irretrievably depraved.” With part of this statement,
I agree. In truth, one cannot predict with full assurance which juvenile
66
offenders can and cannot be rehabilitated. The Massachusetts Supreme
Judicial Court said the same thing in Diatchenko. See 1 N.E.3d at 283–
84. However, for several reasons, I do not believe this rather self-evident
point is enough for us to overturn the legislature’s own judgment in 2015
that LWOP should remain one sentencing option in the exercise of a trial
court’s discretion.
First, if LWOP sentences cannot be constitutionally imposed
whenever there is a possibility of rehabilitation, why is this principle
limited to juveniles? Why aren’t LWOP sentences categorically
unconstitutional for everyone? The court acknowledges, “The features of
youth . . . simply do not magically disappear at age . . . eighteen.”
Second, if the Miller factors are “not . . . very helpful,” “fraught with
risks,” or cannot be “consistently applied” by district courts, as the court
says today, why has this court previously expanded their use to other
contexts besides LWOP? Before today, we had embraced the Miller–
Ragland 8 factors for sentencing juvenile offenders whenever the law
provided for any mandatory minimum period of incarceration. See State
v. Lyle, 854 N.W.2d 378, 403 (Iowa 2014) (“The youth of this state will be
8We distilled five factors from Miller in Ragland, where we said the following:
In Miller, the Court described the factors that the sentencing
court must consider at the hearing, including: (1) the “chronological age”
of the youth and the features of youth, including “immaturity,
impetuosity, and failure to appreciate risks and consequences”; (2) the
“family and home environment” that surrounded the youth; (3) “the
circumstances of the homicide offense, including the extent of [the
youth’s] participation in the conduct and the way familial and peer
pressures may have affected [the youth]”; (4) the “incompetencies
associated with youth—for example, [the youth’s] inability to deal with
police officers or prosecutors (including on a plea agreement) or [the
youth’s] incapacity to assist [the youth’s] own attorneys”; and (5) “the
possibility of rehabilitation.”
836 N.W.2d at 115 n.6 (quoting Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2468, 183 L. Ed.
2d at 423).
67
better served when judges have been permitted to carefully consider all
the circumstances of each case to craft an appropriate sentence and give
each juvenile the individual sentencing attention they deserve . . . .”).
Now, however, the recently mandated factors are deemed to be of
“doubtful” value. Under the majority’s reasoning, we should abandon
any minimum periods of imprisonment and require instant parole
eligibility for every juvenile who commits a serious felony.
Third, and most important, I think the inherent uncertainty
regarding future prospects for rehabilitation is simply an insufficient
basis for supplanting the judgment of our elected representatives and
declaring our existing legislative scheme unconstitutional. I respect the
view that the Iowa Constitution has zero tolerance for error, but justice is
never perfect. Errors can be made—both in incarcerating individuals
who should not be incarcerated and in releasing individuals who should
not be released. And rehabilitation is not the only goal in criminal
sentencing. If it were, all sentences would have no mandatory periods of
incarceration.
As I noted in Seats, both Miller and our cases indicate that factors
other than rehabilitation can be taken into account in sentencing
juveniles. See Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2475, 183 L. Ed. 2d
at 430 (stating that the sentencer may consider “the nature of the[]
crimes,” not just “age and age-related characteristics”); Lyle, 854 N.W.2d
at 398 (stating that the sentencing may consider “the harm the offender
caused”). In Ragland, we said “the possibility of rehabilitation” was one
of five sentencing factors—not the only one. 836 N.W.2d at 115 n.6
(quoting Miller, 567 U.S. ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2468, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 423).
In Miller, the Supreme Court appeared to indicate that LWOP should be
reserved for juvenile murderers “whose crime reflects irreparable
68
corruption.” See Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2469, 183 L. Ed.
2d at 424 (quoting Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 573, 125 S. Ct.
1183, 1197, 161 L. Ed. 2d 1, 24 (2005)). It used this same formulation
several times in Montgomery, stating that LWOP can be imposed on
juvenile murderers “whose crimes reflect irreparable corruption” as
opposed to “transient immaturity.” 577 U.S. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 734,
193 L. Ed. 2d at 620–21. This standard was reiterated at the very end of
the case: “[P]risoners like Montgomery must be given the opportunity to
show their crime did not reflect irreparable corruption . . . .” Id. at ___,
136 S. Ct. at 736, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 623. But saying that a crime reflects
irreparable corruption is not the same thing as saying that the offender
can never be rehabilitated. It is a broader concept that gives weight to all
the Miller–Ragland factors. 9
Society may want to punish a horrendous murder beyond the time
necessary to rehabilitate the murderer. Parole, however, means the
release of the offender occurs as soon as he or she is able and willing to
be a law-abiding citizen. Cf. Iowa Code § 906.4(1) (2015) (“The board [of
parole] shall release on parole or work release any person whom it has
the power to so release, when in its opinion there is reasonable
probability that the person can be released without detriment to the
community or to the person. A person’s release is not a detriment to the
9I acknowledge that one sentence in Montgomery focuses more narrowly on
rehabilitability of the offender: “The [Miller] Court recognized that a sentencer might
encounter the rare juvenile offender who exhibits such irretrievable depravity that
rehabilitation is impossible and life without parole is justified.” 577 U.S. at ___, 136
S. Ct. at 733, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 619. I think this sentence needs to be read in the
context of other, more prevalent language that is crime-based. See id. at ___, 136 S. Ct.
at 734–36, 193 L. Ed. 2d at 619–22.
69
community or the person if the person is able and willing to fulfill the
obligations of a law-abiding citizen, in the board’s determination.”).
When it enacted Senate File 448 last year, our legislature surely
understood this court’s basic observation about the difficulty of
predicting a juvenile’s prospects for rehabilitation. See 2015 Iowa Acts
ch. 65. One doesn’t have to read law review articles to grasp this point.
Yet the legislature decided to leave LWOP on the table for some first-
degree murders committed by juveniles. I do not see a constitutionally
adequate basis for setting aside that legislative judgment.
II. The Sentence in This Case Satisfies the Constitutional
Standards Set Forth in Miller and Ragland.
I now turn to how I would actually decide this case. In addition to
a categorical challenge, Sweet has raised an as-applied challenge to his
sentence. As I previously explained in Seats, when confronted with such
a challenge, I believe we are required to perform a substantive, not
merely a procedural, review of the juvenile LWOP sentence. See 865
N.W.2d at 588–89. Thus, it is not enough for me that the five Miller–
Ragland factors were covered in the sentencing hearing and in the
district court’s sentencing order. We also need to make an independent
determination whether the case is sufficiently uncommon that a district
court, if it so chose, could impose an LWOP sentence. 10 In making this
determination, I would conduct an independent de novo review of the
overall application of the Miller–Ragland factors, while accepting specific
underlying fact findings if they are supported by substantial evidence.
10Montgomery confirms this point. It concluded that Miller imposes both
substantive and procedural limits on when a juvenile homicide offender can be
sentenced to LWOP. See Montgomery, 577 U.S. at ___, 136 S. Ct. at 734–35, 193 L. Ed.
2d at 620.
70
Id. at 588. In this review, no single Miller–Ragland factor is
determinative. Instead, we should consider “whether there are sufficient
indicia the case is out of the mainstream of juvenile homicide cases that
an LWOP sentences is a constitutional option.” Id. at 589.
Under this approach, district courts are not deprived of sentencing
discretion. To put it another way, this approach does not turn appellate
courts into sentencing courts. Yet it provides some check on the kinds of
cases where LWOP sentences are imposed, a check which I believe is
required by Miller and our precedents. What I have described resembles
what several other state appellate courts have done post-Miller. See id.
at 587–88 (discussing cases from California, Louisiana, and North
Carolina).
Here is what the district court found after quoting all the Miller–
Ragland factors. See Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at 115 n.6.
The Court has analyzed this case based on the above
factors. Defendant’s chronological age in and of itself is not
a significant mitigating factor. Defendant was 17 years and
three months old at the time of the murders. Had he been
nine months older, the law would have required him to serve
life in prison without the possibility of parole.
While Defendant’s maturity level at the time of the
crimes is debatable, these were not crimes of impetuosity,
nor were they crimes that Defendant committed because he
failed to appreciate the risks and consequences of his
actions. Defendant planned these murders. He researched
various methods of killing and consulted with others. When
the time came, he took the measured step of wearing ear
muffs so as not to damage his own hearing when he fired the
assault rifle he used to kill the Sweets.
Defendant’s early home environment left something to
be desired. He reported being sexually abused by a neighbor
and apparently never received treatment for any issues that
abuse may have caused. Defendant’s mother was unable to
care for him and left him with the Sweets. The Sweets raised
Defendant as most parents would—including him in family
events and holidays, marking milestones with pictures and
keepsakes, etc. It is undisputed that Defendant behaved
71
badly and was often angry with the Sweets, but the Court
heard nothing that leads it to believe that Defendant’s
behavior and anger was caused by anything the Sweets did
or the quality of home life they provided. By most accounts,
the Sweet household was a stable home; the fact that
Defendant rebelled against the authority they tried to
exercise, sometimes violently, does not change that fact.
The circumstances of the offenses do not militate in
favor of mitigation. As noted above, these were not crimes of
passion, nor did they occur in the heat of the moment.
Defendant did not murder Richard and Janet Sweet because
of familial or peer pressures.
Defendant had no incompetencies that made him
unable to deal with police officers, prosecutors or assist in
his own defense. He understood his rights when he was
apprehended and was able to recite those rights before they
were recited to him. Defendant was, at all relevant times, of
average to above-average intelligence, and there is nothing in
the record that leads the Court to believe that he was unable
to assist his attorneys in his own defense.
The last factor the Court must assess is the possibility
of rehabilitation. The Court considered the testimony and
report of Dr. Stephen Hart [the psychologist called by Sweet
as a witness]. In Dr. Hart’s view, Defendant’s prospects for
rehabilitation are “mixed.” He did not know whether
Defendant was treatable, let alone what treatment might be
appropriate. Dr. Hart offered the statistic that 75% of people
who engage in “serious delinquency” as adolescents
spontaneously desist offending by age 25. The Court was
not provided with the actual study, thus leaving it with
questions regarding the reliability or even applicability of the
data. The Court certainly did not take this data as an
indication that a 17-year-old who murdered his
grandparents in the fashion Defendant did has a 75%
chance of “spontaneously” changing his behavior by age 25.
Considering the manner in which Defendant murdered his
victims and his demeanor following the murders, the Court
believes that “mixed” is an overly-optimistic characterization
of the possibility of rehabilitation.
It should be an uncommon, if not rare, case where a
juvenile offender is committed to life in prison without the
possibility of parole, but if this is not such a case, it is
frightening to imagine what might classify as such. After
giving due weight to the constitutional considerations, the
Court deems this to be a rare case in which such a
punishment is warranted.
72
In the eyes of the law, Defendant was almost an adult
when he murdered his grandparents. He planned the crimes
and acted with cool deliberation and an utter lack of
humanity. The crimes were horrific—two helpless and
unsuspecting victims shot as they sat in their living room,
left to be discovered by other family members. Why? Simply
because Defendant did not like the parental authority they
tried to exercise over him. If Defendant’s cold-bloodedness
wasn’t evident from the crimes themselves, it certainly
became so immediately thereafter, when he began to sell his
victims’ belongings, going so far as to bring a friend into the
house to show him a flat screen t.v. just a few feet from the
Sweets’ bodies.
Defendant may be young, but that has not stopped
him from showing the world who he is. He is extremely
dangerous. He is now and will continue to be a threat to
society. In this case, the interests of justice and community
safety outweigh any mitigating factors under Miller. For
these reasons, the Court imposes the maximum sentence of
life imprisonment without the possibility of parole.
The record fully supports this fact-finding. Unfortunately, the
court today determines its own facts, drawing largely on unverified
statements made by Sweet or his natural mother to the probation officer.
The probation officer appropriately distanced herself from those
unverified statements when she prepared the presentence investigation
report (PSI). 11 Thus, the probation officer said those matters were
“reported” to her without vouching for their accuracy. Regrettably, the
majority treats them as conclusively proven, noting that the PSI was
“admitted into evidence without objection and without correction or
elaboration by either party.” I disagree with this approach, which I
believe gives insufficient deference to the sentencing judge’s first-hand
factual determinations.
Starting from this questionable premise, the majority concludes
Sweet had an “unstable family life.” But the district court found, and the
11It should be noted the natural mother was not an unbiased observer in that
her parental rights were terminated when Sweet was four.
73
record supports, that although Sweet’s early home environment was
poor, Sweet did not suffer from a lack of family stability once he moved in
with his grandparents at the age of four. One can fairly say that Sweet
murdered the two people who rescued him.
Furthermore, Sweet’s juvenile court officer testified that both
grandparents were very involved in Sweet’s supervision and repeatedly
tried to get help for him. Sweet’s psychologist was careful to say that
although Sweet had complained about his grandfather being abusive, “I
just want to make clear I’m not saying that’s a fact.”
In addition to giving considerable weight to unverified statements
made to the PSI preparer, the majority downplays the testimony of
Sweet’s psychologist, much of what was quite unfavorable to Sweet.
Here are excerpts from the psychologist’s cross-examination testimony:
Q. You’ve said that the Defendant is quick to anger;
correct? A. Yes.
Q. That he is deceitful, defiant? A. Yes.
Q. Aggressive? A. Yes.
Q. And he has a lack of attachment to people. A. Yes.
Q. That he lacks trust in people. A. Yes.
Q. That he is emotionally disconnected. A. Yes.
Q. That he has no strong feelings of empathy or
remorse. A. Correct, yes.
Q. He has an attitude of superiority. A. Yes.
Q. And even today you don’t think he begins to
appreciate what he’s done; correct? A. Correct.
Q. Someone with those types of behavior traits that
we just went through, what do you call that when they’re an
adult? A. If those things persisted past the age of 25, if I
had an adult who’d shown those things consistently, then
that’s the kind of thing we often would call psychopathic or
antisocial personality disorder.
74
Q. And I’m correct in saying that you can’t say if he is
going to be a psychopath; correct? A. That’s exactly right. I
can’t tell you that he will or he won’t.
Q. And you have said in your report that he has not
responded to treatment, to any type of treatment, to this
point; correct? A. Correct. There’s some cognitive aspects
of his behaviors. Some of his simple attention has
responded to medications but this doesn’t—hasn’t had a big
impact on the other parts of his behavior.
Q. And so it could be just in-born personality traits;
correct? A. It could be.
Q. And you also cannot recommend any type of
treatment that’s likely to improve him. A. That’s correct.
The ADHD, I would imagine, will continue to be treated by
medications, but that’s actually only one part of his
problems as I’ve outlined them. I think the attachment
issues and the personality issues require other forms of
treatment, but we don’t have any reliably effective treatment
for those things.
Let me now detail what in my view makes this case unusual and
authorized the district court, in its discretion, to impose an LWOP
sentence. In doing so, I will review the Miller–Ragland factors while
accepting specific factual findings of the district court if supported by
substantial evidence.
First, as noted by the district court, Sweet was over seventeen
years old when he killed his grandparents, just nine months short of the
age when Miller–Ragland would no longer even apply. While there is
certainly evidence the defendant often acted impetuously, he did not
commit these murders impetuously. Noteworthy is the district court’s
observation that the defendant “took the measured step of wearing ear
muffs so as not to damage his own hearing when he fired the assault rifle
he used to kill the Sweets.”
Second, as found by the district court, Sweet had the benefit of a
stable home once he moved in with his grandparents at the age of four.
The district court is right: We should not confuse Sweet’s violent
75
rebellion against his grandparents, which culminated in his decision to
murder them, with a poor home environment.
Third, the crime was accurately summarized by the district court
as “horrific.” The defendant not only murdered his grandfather in cold
blood, with whom he did not get along, but his grandmother, with whom
he did get along. Sweet had no accomplices. No one encouraged him to
do what he did.
Fourth, the defendant’s youth did not impair his defense. As the
district court found, he was of average to above average intelligence.
Some of the vocabulary he used in his allocution supports this finding
(e.g., “emotionally,” “sociologically,” “comprehend,” “condolences”). Sweet
knew his rights before the police recited them to him. He knew the exact
penalty provided by the law for his crimes.
Finally, while no one can say for sure whether this defendant can
be rehabilitated, it bodes ill for him that he has traits of an antisocial
personality disorder, for which no treatment is available. In fairness,
Sweet’s psychologist testified that Sweet’s prospects for rehabilitation are
“mixed” because seventy-five percent of delinquents with antisocial
personality characteristics do not develop “life-course-persistent
antisocial behavior”; only twenty-five percent do. However, as the district
court pointed out, these were overall numbers, not numbers specific to
persons who commit a crime like a premeditated double murder of one’s
grandparents.
To my mind, sharp differences exist between this case and three
cases we have recently reviewed—Ragland, State v. Louisell, 865 N.W.2d
76
590 (Iowa 2015), and State v. Querrey, 871 N.W.2d 126 (Iowa 2015). 12
For all these reasons, I believe an LWOP sentence was a constitutional
sentencing option here, and the district court’s sentence should be
affirmed.
For the reasons stated, I respectfully dissent.
Waterman and Zager, JJ., join this dissent.
12A quick review of the court of appeals’ docket indicates that other juveniles
who committed first-degree murder have received non-LWOP sentences post-Miller. See
State v. Harris, No. 14–0394, 2015 WL 576020, at *1 (Iowa Ct. App. Feb. 11, 2015) (life
with immediate parole eligibility); State v. Winfrey, No. 13–1837, 2014 WL 3940136, at
*6 (Iowa Ct. App. Aug. 13, 2014) (life with immediate parole eligibility).
77
#14–0455, State v. Sweet
ZAGER, Justice (dissenting).
I join in the well-written dissent authored by Justice Mansfield. I
would affirm the district court sentence of life without the possibility of
parole (LWOP) for Sweet. I write separately to voice my ongoing objection
to this court’s lack of confidence in our district court judges’ ability to
make difficult sentencing decisions in the area of juvenile sentencing
involving life without parole.
We have now had several opportunities to review the sentencing
decisions of our district court judges regarding juvenile homicide
offenders and LWOP. See, e.g., State v. Louisell, 865 N.W.2d 590, 598–
603 (Iowa 2015); State v. Seats, 865 N.W.2d 545, 555–57 (Iowa 2015). In
each case, our court has refused to uphold the decision of the district
court that the juvenile homicide offender was the rare and uncommon
case warranting the imposition of LWOP. See, e.g., Seats, 865 N.W.2d at
557.
This court has repeatedly demonstrated that, in practice, it is
unwilling to uphold any sentence of life without parole for juvenile
offenders—indeed, we are not even willing to uphold sentences that are
merely the functional equivalent of life without parole. See, e.g., Seats,
865 N.W.2d at 555–57 (expanding on the factors that district court
judges must weigh in a juvenile homicide offender’s sentencing hearing,
vacating the sentence of LWOP imposed by the district court, and
remanding for resentencing); State v. Ragland, 836 N.W.2d 107, 122
(Iowa 2013) (requiring individualized sentencing proceedings per Miller v.
Alabama, 567 U.S. ___, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 183 L. Ed. 2d 407 (2012), not
only for juveniles serving LWOP sentences but also for those serving the
“functional equivalent” of LWOP sentences). After establishing in
78
Ragland and State v. Null that Miller would apply retroactively and
require individualized sentencing hearings, and later expanding on the
factors the district court must consider in Seats, this court is still in this
case unwilling to uphold an LWOP sentence that resulted from a
thorough individualized sentencing hearing. See Seats, 865 N.W.2d at
555–57 (outlining the factors the district court must weigh in
determining which juveniles should be subject to the “rare and
uncommon” sentence of life without parole); Ragland, 836 N.W.2d at
117; State v. Null, 836 N.W.2d 41, 74 (Iowa 2013) (“[W]e conclude article
I, section 17 requires that a district court recognize and apply the core
teachings of Roper [v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 125 S. Ct. 1183, 161
L. Ed. 2d 1 (2005)], Graham [v. Florida, 560 U.S. 48, 130 S. Ct. 2011,
176 L. Ed. 2d 825 (2010)], and Miller in making sentencing decisions for
long prison terms involving juveniles.”).
Unfortunately, as highlighted by the dissent in this case, even after
a thorough sentencing hearing, and after a thorough and well-reasoned
decision by the district court, this court will not support the conclusion
that this may be that rare and uncommon circumstance warranting a
sentence of LWOP. We have certainly provided sufficient guidance as to
what would warrant a sentence of LWOP for juvenile offenders. 13 Of
13We have instructed our judges to weigh certain factors:
First, the court must start with the Supreme Court’s
pronouncement that sentencing a juvenile to life in prison without the
possibility of parole should be rare and uncommon. Thus, the
presumption for any sentencing judge is that the judge should sentence
juveniles to life in prison with the possibility of parole for murder unless
the other factors require a different sentence.
Second, the sentencing judge must recognize that “children are
constitutionally different from adults.” We have explained, “The
constitutional difference arises from a juvenile’s lack of maturity,
underdeveloped sense of responsibility, vulnerability to peer pressure,
and the less fixed nature of the juvenile’s character.”
79
course, the procedural safeguards of an individualized sentencing
hearing have been utilized in all cases. However, in our substantive
analysis, it now appears that the factors we previously established are so
vague, subjective, and uncertain that this court cannot expect the
district court to do the impossible—make a judgement as to whether the
offender is “irretrievably corrupt” or to find a true “rare and uncommon”
case sufficient to justify the imposition of a sentence of life without
parole. The answer, of course, is to take away all sentencing discretion
from the district court and adopt a categorical rule that juvenile
offenders may never be sentenced to life without the possibility of parole
under article I, section 17 of the Iowa Constitution. I find the basis for
this conclusion troubling on many levels.
In sentencing the juvenile offender, the court must take into
account any information in the record regarding “the family and home
environment that surrounds him—and from which he cannot usually
extricate himself—no matter how brutal or dysfunctional.” . . . The
sentencing judge should consider these family and home environment
vulnerabilities together with the juvenile’s lack of maturity,
underdeveloped sense of responsibility, and vulnerability to peer
pressure as mitigating, not aggravating, factors.
Third, the sentencing judge must consider “the circumstances of
the homicide offense, including the extent of [the juvenile’s] participation
in the conduct and the way familial and peer pressures may have
affected him.” . . .
Finally, the sentencing judge must take into consideration that
“[j]uveniles are more capable of change than are adults” and that as a
result, “their actions are less likely to be evidence of ‘irretrievably
depraved character.’ ” . . . The sentencing judge should only sentence
those juveniles to life in prison without the possibility of parole whose
crime reflects irreparable corruption.
Seats, 865 N.W.2d at 555–56 (citations omitted) (first quoting Miller, 567 U.S. at ___,
132 S. Ct. at 2464, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 418; then quoting Null, 836 N.W.2d at 74; then
quoting Miller, 567 U.S. at ___, 132 S. Ct. at 2468, 183 L. Ed. 2d at 423; then quoting
id.; and then quoting Graham, 560 U.S. at 68, 130 S. Ct. at 2026, 176 L. Ed. 2d at
841).
80
First, we are not asking our district court judges to do the
impossible. These are the difficult decisions we expect of our judges and
are the type of decisions that they make with distinction on a daily basis.
I also agree that it is not enough that the Miller–Ragland–Null factors
were considered in Sweet’s sentencing hearing and that the district court
sentencing order discussed and analyzed these factors. We also need to
make an independent judgment as to whether the case is sufficiently
uncommon that the district court judge, in the exercise of his or her own
judgment, could impose an LWOP sentence. This is the function of
appellate review. The adoption of this categorical rule not only
eliminates the role of the district court in its sentencing obligation, but
eliminates any effective appellate review. This sea change in sentencing
requires greater analysis than simply relieving district court judges of
this “impossible” duty. Mere expediency in sentencing juvenile offenders
should not be the standard.
I also do not find persuasive the argument that, since highly
trained psychologists cannot predict when a juvenile offender is
irreparably corrupt, the decisions of our sentencing courts are
speculative because they lack adequate predictive information. It is not
for these trained professionals to offer an ultimate opinion on this. And
frankly, the district court is free to accept it or reject it in any case. It is
just one of the multiple factors that we expect our judges to evaluate
when determining an appropriate sentence for a juvenile offender.
Last, with all due respect, I question whether the board of parole is
better able to discern whether the juvenile offender is irreparably corrupt
after time has passed, and after opportunities for maturation and
rehabilitation have been provided. I am not an expert in the parole
system, nor do I claim to be. But what I have discerned is that the board
81
of parole has an extremely busy schedule handling literally hundreds of
cases a month. Also, parole decisions may be made for a variety of
reasons. Some parole decisions may be the result of a change in the
rules or overcrowding. The point is, many parole decisions may be made
based on factors unrelated to a consideration of maturity and
rehabilitation. Likewise, I am not confident that the department of
corrections has or will have the resources available to hire highly trained
professionals to provide all of the psychological testing and treatment
necessary to offer an informed opinion on whether the offender is now
irreparably corrupt. And of course, even if those opinions were offered,
the board of parole has the ability to reject the opinions as well.
Ultimately, I think the adoption of a categorical rule is an improper
delegation of the sentencing duties and responsibilities vested in the
judicial branch.
The district court provided Sweet with an appropriate Miller-type
hearing. After the sentencing hearing, the district court applied the
unique facts of this case to the multiple factors we have set out in our
caselaw. In a thorough, well-reasoned decision, the district court
concluded this was the rare case where an LWOP sentence was
appropriate. Having done exactly what we expect of our district court
judges, and looking at the entire record independently as we are required
to do, I would affirm the sentence of the district court.
Waterman and Mansfield, JJ., join this dissent.