Barr v. American Assn. of Political Consultants, Inc.

(Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2019 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus BARR, ATTORNEY GENERAL, ET AL. v. AMERICAN ASSOCIATION OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC., ET AL. CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT No. 19–631. Argued May 6, 2020—Decided July 6, 2020 In response to consumer complaints, Congress passed the Telephone Consumer Protection Act of 1991 (TCPA) to prohibit, inter alia, almost all robocalls to cell phones. 47 U. S. C. §227(b)(1)(A)(iii). In 2015, Con- gress amended the robocall restriction, carving out a new government- debt exception that allows robocalls made solely to collect a debt owed to or guaranteed by the United States. 129 Stat. 588. The American Association of Political Consultants and three other organizations that participate in the political system filed a declaratory judgment action, claiming that §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) violated the First Amendment. The District Court determined that the robocall restriction with the gov- ernment-debt exception was content-based but that it survived strict scrutiny because of the Government’s compelling interest in collecting debt. The Fourth Circuit vacated the judgment, agreeing that the robo- call restriction with the government-debt exception was a content- based speech restriction, but holding that the law could not withstand strict scrutiny. The court invalidated the government-debt exception and applied traditional severability principles to sever it from the ro- bocall restriction. Held: The judgment is affirmed. 923 F. 3d 159, affirmed. JUSTICE KAVANAUGH, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE, JUSTICE THOMAS, and JUSTICE ALITO, concluded in Part II that the 2015 gov- ernment-debt exception violates the First Amendment. Pp. 6–9. (a) The Free Speech Clause provides that government generally “has no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its 2 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Syllabus subject matter, or its content.” Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92, 95. Under this Court’s precedents, content-based laws are subject to strict scrutiny. See Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 576 U. S. 155, 165. Section 227(b)(1)(A)(iii)’s robocall restriction, with the govern- ment-debt exception, is content based because it favors speech made for the purpose of collecting government debt over political and other speech. Pp. 6–7. (b) The Government’s arguments for deeming the statute content- neutral are unpersuasive. First, §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) does not draw dis- tinctions based on speakers, and even if it did, that would not “auto- matically render the distinction content neutral.” Reed, 576 U. S., at 170. Second, the law here focuses on whether the caller is speaking about a particular topic and not, as the Government contends, simply on whether the caller is engaged in a particular economic activity. See Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc., 564 U. S. 552, 563–564. Third, while “the First Amendment does not prevent restrictions directed at commerce or conduct from imposing incidental burdens on speech,” this law “does not simply have an effect on speech, but is directed at certain content and is aimed at particular speakers.” Id., at 567. (c) As the Government concedes, the robocall restriction with the government-debt exception cannot satisfy strict scrutiny. The Govern- ment has not sufficiently justified the differentiation between govern- ment-debt collection speech and other important categories of robocall speech, such as political speech, issue advocacy, and the like. Pp. 7–9. JUSTICE KAVANAUGH, joined by THE CHIEF JUSTICE and JUSTICE ALITO, concluded in Part III that the 2015 government-debt exception is severable from the underlying 1991 robocall restriction. The TCPA is part of the Communications Act, which has contained an express severability clause since 1934. Even if that clause did not apply to the exception, the presumption of severability would still apply. See, e.g., Free Enterprise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight Bd., 561 U. S. 477. The remainder of the law is capable of functioning in- dependently and would be fully operative as a law. Severing this rel- atively narrow exception to the broad robocall restriction fully cures the First Amendment unequal treatment problem and does not raise any other constitutional problems. Pp. 9–24. JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR concluded that the government-debt exception fails under intermediate scrutiny and is severable from the rest of the Act. Pp. 1–2. JUSTICE BREYER, joined by JUSTICE GINSBURG and JUSTICE KAGAN, would have upheld the government-debt exception, but given the con- trary majority view, agreed that the provision is severable from the rest of the statute. Pp. 11–12. JUSTICE GORSUCH concluded that content-based restrictions on Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 3 Syllabus speech are subject to strict scrutiny, that the Telephone Consumer Protection Act’s rule against cellphone robocalls is a content-based re- striction, and that this rule fails strict scrutiny and therefore cannot be constitutionally enforced. Pp. 1–4. KAVANAUGH, J., announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an opinion, in which ROBERTS, C. J., and ALITO, J., joined, and in which THOMAS, J., joined as to Parts I and II. SOTOMAYOR, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment. BREYER, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment with respect to severability and dissenting in part, in which GINSBURG and KAGAN, JJ., joined. GORSUCH, J., filed an opinion concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part, in which THOMAS, J., joined as to Part II. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 1 Opinion Opinion ofAVANAUGH of K the Court, J. NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal resvision before publication in the preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Wash- ington, D. C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to press. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 19–631 _________________ WILLIAM P. BARR, ATTORNEY GENERAL, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. AMERICAN ASSOCIATION OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC., ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT [July 6, 2020] JUSTICE KAVANAUGH announced the judgment of the Court and delivered an opinion, in which THE CHIEF JUSTICE and JUSTICE ALITO join, and in which JUSTICE THOMAS joins as to Parts I and II. Americans passionately disagree about many things. But they are largely united in their disdain for robocalls. The Federal Government receives a staggering number of com- plaints about robocalls—3.7 million complaints in 2019 alone. The States likewise field a constant barrage of com- plaints. For nearly 30 years, the people’s representatives in Con- gress have been fighting back. As relevant here, the Tele- phone Consumer Protection Act of 1991, known as the TCPA, generally prohibits robocalls to cell phones and home phones. But a 2015 amendment to the TCPA allows robocalls that are made to collect debts owed to or guaran- teed by the Federal Government, including robocalls made to collect many student loan and mortgage debts. This case concerns robocalls to cell phones. Plaintiffs in this case are political and nonprofit organizations that want 2 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. to make political robocalls to cell phones. Invoking the First Amendment, they argue that the 2015 government-debt ex- ception unconstitutionally favors debt-collection speech over political and other speech. As relief from that uncon- stitutional law, they urge us to invalidate the entire 1991 robocall restriction, rather than simply invalidating the 2015 government-debt exception. Six Members of the Court today conclude that Congress has impermissibly favored debt-collection speech over polit- ical and other speech, in violation of the First Amendment. See infra, at 6–9; post, at 1–2 (SOTOMAYOR, J., concurring in judgment); post, at 1, 3 (GORSUCH, J., concurring in judg- ment in part and dissenting in part). Applying traditional severability principles, seven Members of the Court con- clude that the entire 1991 robocall restriction should not be invalidated, but rather that the 2015 government-debt ex- ception must be invalidated and severed from the remain- der of the statute. See infra, at 10–25; post, at 2 (SOTOMAYOR, J., concurring in judgment); post, at 11–12 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment with respect to sever- ability and dissenting in part). As a result, plaintiffs still may not make political robocalls to cell phones, but their speech is now treated equally with debt-collection speech. The judgment of the U. S. Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit is affirmed. I A In 1991, Congress passed and President George H. W. Bush signed the Telephone Consumer Protection Act. The Act responded to a torrent of vociferous consumer com- plaints about intrusive robocalls. A growing number of tel- emarketers were using equipment that could automatically dial a telephone number and deliver an artificial or prere- corded voice message. At the time, more than 300,000 so- licitors called more than 18 million Americans every day. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 3 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. TCPA, §2, ¶¶3, 6, 105 Stat. 2394, note following 47 U. S. C. §227. Consumers were “outraged” and considered robocalls an invasion of privacy “regardless of the content or the ini- tiator of the message.” ¶¶6, 10. A leading Senate sponsor of the TCPA captured the zeit- geist in 1991, describing robocalls as “the scourge of modern civilization. They wake us up in the morning; they inter- rupt our dinner at night; they force the sick and elderly out of bed; they hound us until we want to rip the telephone right out of the wall.” 137 Cong. Rec. 30821 (1991). In enacting the TCPA, Congress found that banning ro- bocalls was “the only effective means of protecting tele- phone consumers from this nuisance and privacy invasion.” TCPA §2, ¶12. To that end, the TCPA imposed various re- strictions on the use of automated telephone equipment. §3(a), 105 Stat. 2395. As relevant here, one restriction pro- hibited “any call (other than a call made for emergency pur- poses or made with the prior express consent of the called party) using any automatic telephone dialing system or an artificial or prerecorded voice” to “any telephone number assigned to a paging service, cellular telephone service, spe- cialized mobile radio service, or other radio common carrier service, or any service for which the called party is charged for the call.” Id., at 2395–2396 (emphasis added). That pro- vision is codified in §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) of Title 47 of the U. S. Code. In plain English, the TCPA prohibited almost all ro- bocalls to cell phones.1 —————— 1 The robocall restriction, as implemented by the Federal Communica- tions Commission, bars both automated voice calls and automated text messages. See In re Rules and Regulations Implementing the Telephone Consumer Protection Act of 1991, 18 FCC Rcd. 14014, 14115 (2003). The robocall restriction applies to “persons,” which does not include the Gov- ernment itself. See 47 U. S. C. §153(39). Congress has also authorized the FCC to promulgate regulatory exceptions to the robocall restriction. See §227(b)(2)(C). The FCC has authorized various exceptions over the years, such as exceptions for package-delivery notifications and certain 4 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. Twenty-four years later, in 2015, Congress passed and President Obama signed the Bipartisan Budget Act. In ad- dition to making other unrelated changes to the U. S. Code, that Act amended the TCPA’s restriction on robocalls to cell phones. It stated: “(a) IN GENERAL.—Section 227(b) of the Communica- tions Act of 1934 (47 U. S. C. 227(b)) is amended— (1) in paragraph (1)— (A) in subparagraph (A)(iii), by inserting ‘, unless such call is made solely to collect a debt owed to or guar- anteed by the United States’ after ‘charged for the call.’ ” 129 Stat. 588.2 In other words, Congress carved out a new government- debt exception to the general robocall restriction. The TCPA imposes tough penalties for violating the ro- bocall restriction. Private parties can sue to recover up to $1,500 per violation or three times their actual monetary losses, which can add up quickly in a class action. §227(b)(3). States may bring civil actions against ro- bocallers on behalf of their citizens. §227(g)(1). And the —————— healthcare-related calls. In this case, plaintiffs do not separately chal- lenge the validity of the FCC’s regulatory exceptions. 2 After the 2015 amendment, §227(b)(1) now provides: “It shall be unlawful for any person within the United States, or any person outside the United States if the recipient is within the United States— (A) to make any call (other than a call made for emergency purposes or made with the prior express consent of the called party) using any automatic telephone dialing system or an artificial or prerecorded voice— . . . . . (iii) to any telephone number assigned to a paging service, cellular tel- ephone service, specialized mobile radio service, or other radio common carrier service, or any service for which the called party is charged for the call, unless such call is made solely to collect a debt owed to or guar- anteed by the United States.” (Emphasis added.) Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 5 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. Federal Communications Commission can seek forfeiture penalties for willful or repeated violations of the statute. §503(b). B Plaintiffs in this case are the American Association of Po- litical Consultants and three other organizations that par- ticipate in the political system. Plaintiffs and their mem- bers make calls to citizens to discuss candidates and issues, solicit donations, conduct polls, and get out the vote. Plain- tiffs believe that their political outreach would be more ef- fective and efficient if they could make robocalls to cell phones.3 But because plaintiffs are not in the business of collecting government debt, §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) prohibits them from making those robocalls. Plaintiffs filed a declaratory judgment action against the U. S. Attorney General and the FCC, claiming that §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) violated the First Amendment. The U. S. District Court for the Eastern District of North Carolina de- termined that the robocall restriction with the government- debt exception was a content-based speech regulation, thereby triggering strict scrutiny. But the court concluded that the law survived strict scrutiny, even with the content- based exception, because of the Government’s compelling interest in collecting debt. The U. S. Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit vacated the judgment. American Assn. of Political Consultants, Inc. v. FCC, 923 F. 3d 159 (2019). The Court of Appeals agreed with the District Court that the robocall restriction with the government-debt exception was a content-based speech re- striction. But the court held that the law could not with- stand strict scrutiny and was therefore unconstitutional. The Court of Appeals then applied traditional severability —————— 3 Plaintiffs have not challenged the TCPA’s separate restriction on ro- bocalls to home phones. See 47 U. S. C. §227(b)(1)(B). 6 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. principles and concluded that the government-debt excep- tion was severable from the underlying robocall restriction. The Court of Appeals therefore invalidated the govern- ment-debt exception and severed it from the robocall re- striction. The Government petitioned for a writ of certiorari be- cause the Court of Appeals invalidated part of a federal statute—namely, the government-debt exception. Plain- tiffs supported the petition, arguing from the other direc- tion that the Court of Appeals did not go far enough in providing relief and should have invalidated the entire 1991 robocall restriction rather than simply invalidating the 2015 government-debt exception. We granted certiorari. 589 U. S. ___ (2020). II Ratified in 1791, the First Amendment provides that Congress shall make no law “abridging the freedom of speech.” Above “all else, the First Amendment means that government” generally “has no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.” Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92, 95 (1972). The Court’s precedents allow the government to “consti- tutionally impose reasonable time, place, and manner reg- ulations” on speech, but the precedents restrict the govern- ment from discriminating “in the regulation of expression on the basis of the content of that expression.” Hudgens v. NLRB, 424 U. S. 507, 520 (1976). Content-based laws are subject to strict scrutiny. See Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 576 U. S. 155, 163–164 (2015). By contrast, content-neutral laws are subject to a lower level of scrutiny. Id., at 166. Section 227(b)(1)(A)(iii) generally bars robocalls to cell phones. Since the 2015 amendment, the law has exempted robocalls to collect government debt. The initial First Amendment question is whether the robocall restriction, Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 7 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. with the government-debt exception, is content-based. The answer is yes. As relevant here, a law is content-based if “a regulation of speech ‘on its face’ draws distinctions based on the mes- sage a speaker conveys.” Reed, 576 U. S., at 163. That de- scription applies to a law that “singles out specific subject matter for differential treatment.” Id., at 169. For exam- ple, “a law banning the use of sound trucks for political speech—and only political speech—would be a content- based regulation, even if it imposed no limits on the politi- cal viewpoints that could be expressed.” Ibid.; see, e.g., Si- mon & Schuster, Inc. v. Members of N. Y. State Crime Vic- tims Bd., 502 U. S. 105, 116 (1991); Arkansas Writers’ Project, Inc. v. Ragland, 481 U. S. 221, 229–230 (1987); Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U. S. 263, 265, 276–277 (1981); Carey v. Brown, 447 U. S. 455, 459–463 (1980); Erznoznik v. Jacksonville, 422 U. S. 205, 211–212 (1975); Mosley, 408 U. S., at 95–96. Under §227(b)(1)(A)(iii), the legality of a robocall turns on whether it is “made solely to collect a debt owed to or guar- anteed by the United States.” A robocall that says, “Please pay your government debt” is legal. A robocall that says, “Please donate to our political campaign” is illegal. That is about as content-based as it gets. Because the law favors speech made for collecting government debt over political and other speech, the law is a content-based restriction on speech. The Government advances three main arguments for deeming the statute content-neutral, but none is persua- sive. First, the Government suggests that §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) draws distinctions based on speakers (authorized debt col- lectors), not based on content. But that is not the law in front of us. This statute singles out calls “made solely to collect a debt owed to or guaranteed by the United States,” not all calls from authorized debt collectors. 8 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. In any event, “the fact that a distinction is speaker based” does not “automatically render the distinction content neu- tral.” Reed, 576 U. S., at 170; Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc., 564 U. S. 552, 563–564 (2011). Indeed, the Court has held that “ ‘ laws favoring some speakers over others demand strict scrutiny when the legislature’s speaker preference re- flects a content preference.’ ” Reed, 576 U. S., at 170 (quot- ing Turner Broadcasting System, Inc. v. FCC, 512 U. S. 622, 658 (1994)). Second, the Government argues that the legality of a ro- bocall under the statute depends simply on whether the caller is engaged in a particular economic activity, not on the content of speech. We disagree. The law here focuses on whether the caller is speaking about a particular topic. In Sorrell, this Court held that a law singling out pharma- ceutical marketing for unfavorable treatment was content- based. 564 U. S., at 563–564. So too here. Third, according to the Government, if this statute is con- tent-based because it singles out debt-collection speech, then so are statutes that regulate debt collection, like the Fair Debt Collection Practices Act. See 15 U. S. C. §1692 et seq.4 That slippery-slope argument is unpersuasive in this case. As we explained in Sorrell, “the First Amendment does not prevent restrictions directed at commerce or con- duct from imposing incidental burdens on speech.” 564 U. S., at 567. The law here, like the Vermont law in Sorrell, “does not simply have an effect on speech, but is directed at certain content and is aimed at particular speakers.” Ibid. The Government’s concern is understandable, but the courts have generally been able to distinguish impermissi- ble content-based speech restrictions from traditional or or- —————— 4 This opinion uses the term “debt-collection speech” and “debt-collec- tion robocalls” as shorthand for government-debt collection speech and robocalls. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 9 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. dinary economic regulation of commercial activity that im- poses incidental burdens on speech. The issue before us concerns only robocalls to cell phones. Our decision today on that issue fits comfortably within existing First Amend- ment precedent. Our decision is not intended to expand ex- isting First Amendment doctrine or to otherwise affect tra- ditional or ordinary economic regulation of commercial activity. In short, the robocall restriction with the government- debt exception is content-based. Under the Court’s prece- dents, a “law that is content based” is “subject to strict scru- tiny.” Reed, 576 U. S., at 165. The Government concedes that it cannot satisfy strict scrutiny to justify the govern- ment-debt exception. We agree. The Government’s stated justification for the government-debt exception is collecting government debt. Although collecting government debt is no doubt a worthy goal, the Government concedes that it has not sufficiently justified the differentiation between government-debt collection speech and other important cat- egories of robocall speech, such as political speech, charita- ble fundraising, issue advocacy, commercial advertising, and the like.5 —————— 5 In his scholarly separate opinion, JUSTICE BREYER explains how he would apply freedom of speech principles. But the Court’s longstanding precedents, which we carefully follow here, have not adopted that ap- proach. In essence, therefore, JUSTICE BREYER argues for overruling sev- eral of the Court’s First Amendment cases, including the recent 2015 de- cision in Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 576 U. S. 155 (2015). Before overruling precedent, the Court usually requires that a party ask for overruling, or at least obtains briefing on the overruling question, and then the Court carefully evaluates the traditional stare decisis factors. Here, no party has asked for overruling, and JUSTICE BREYER’s opinion does not analyze the usual stare decisis factors. JUSTICE BREYER’s opinion therefore dis- counts both the Court’s precedent and the Court’s precedent on prece- dent. 10 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. III Having concluded that the 2015 government-debt excep- tion created an unconstitutional exception to the 1991 ro- bocall restriction, we must decide whether to invalidate the entire 1991 robocall restriction, or instead to invalidate and sever the 2015 government-debt exception. Before we apply ordinary severability principles, we must address plaintiffs’ broader initial argument for why the entire 1991 robocall restriction is unconstitutional. A Plaintiffs correctly point out that the Government’s as- serted interest for the 1991 robocall restriction is consumer privacy. But according to plaintiffs, Congress’s willingness to enact the government-debt exception in 2015 betrays a newfound lack of genuine congressional concern for con- sumer privacy. As plaintiffs phrase it, the 2015 exception “undermines the credibility” of the Government’s interest in consumer privacy. Tr. of Oral Arg. 38. Plaintiffs further contend that if Congress no longer has a genuine interest in consumer privacy, then the underlying 1991 robocall re- striction is no longer justified (presumably under any level of heightened scrutiny) and is therefore now unconstitu- tional. Plaintiffs’ argument is not without force, but we ulti- mately disagree with it. It is true that the Court has recog- nized that exceptions to a speech restriction “may diminish the credibility of the government’s rationale for restricting speech in the first place.” City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43, 52 (1994). But here, Congress’s addition of the govern- ment-debt exception in 2015 does not cause us to doubt the credibility of Congress’s continuing interest in protecting consumer privacy. After all, the government-debt exception is only a slice of the overall robocall landscape. This is not a case where a Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 11 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. restriction on speech is littered with exceptions that sub- stantially negate the restriction. On the contrary, even af- ter 2015, Congress has retained a very broad restriction on robocalls. The pre-1991 statistics on robocalls show that a variety of organizations collectively made a huge number of robocalls. And there is no reason to think that the incen- tives for those organizations—and many others—to make robocalls has diminished in any way since 1991. The con- tinuing robocall restriction proscribes tens of millions of would-be robocalls that would otherwise occur every day. Congress’s continuing broad prohibition of robocalls amply demonstrates Congress’s continuing interest in consumer privacy. The simple reality, as we assess the legislative develop- ments, is that Congress has competing interests. Con- gress’s growing interest (as reflected in the 2015 amend- ment) in collecting government debt does not mean that Congress suddenly lacks a genuine interest in restricting robocalls. Plaintiffs seem to argue that Congress must be interested either in debt collection or in consumer privacy. But that is a false dichotomy, as we see it. As is not infre- quently the case with either/or questions, the answer to this either/or question is “both.” Congress is interested both in collecting government debt and in protecting consumer pri- vacy. Therefore, we disagree with plaintiffs’ broader initial ar- gument for holding the entire 1991 robocall restriction un- constitutional. B Plaintiffs next focus on ordinary severability principles. Applying those principles, the question before the Court is whether (i) to invalidate the entire 1991 robocall re- striction, as plaintiffs want, or (ii) to invalidate just the 2015 government-debt exception and sever it from the re- mainder of the statute, as the Government wants. 12 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. We agree with the Government that we must invalidate the 2015 government-debt exception and sever that excep- tion from the remainder of the statute. To explain why, we begin with general severability principles and then apply those principles to this case. 1 When enacting a law, Congress sometimes expressly ad- dresses severability. For example, Congress may include a severability clause in the law, making clear that the uncon- stitutionality of one provision does not affect the rest of the law. See, e.g., 12 U. S. C. §5302; 15 U. S. C. §78gg; 47 U. S. C. §608. Alternatively, Congress may include a non- severability clause, making clear that the unconstitutional- ity of one provision means the invalidity of some or all of the remainder of the law, to the extent specified in the text of the nonseverability clause. See, e.g., 4 U. S. C. §125; note following 42 U. S. C. §300aa–1; 94 Stat. 1797. When Congress includes an express severability or non- severability clause in the relevant statute, the judicial in- quiry is straightforward. At least absent extraordinary cir- cumstances, the Court should adhere to the text of the severability or nonseverability clause. That is because a severability or nonseverability clause leaves no doubt about what the enacting Congress wanted if one provision of the law were later declared unconstitutional. A severability clause indicates “that Congress did not intend the validity of the statute in question to depend on the validity of the constitutionally offensive provision.” Alaska Airlines, Inc. v. Brock, 480 U. S. 678, 686 (1987). And a nonseverability clause does the opposite. On occasion, a party will nonetheless ask the Court to override the text of a severability or nonseverability clause on the ground that the text does not reflect Congress’s “ac- tual intent” as to severability. That kind of argument may Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 13 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. have carried some force back when courts paid less atten- tion to statutory text as the definitive expression of Con- gress’s will. But courts today zero in on the precise statu- tory text and, as a result, courts hew closely to the text of severability or nonseverability clauses. See Seila Law LLC v. Consumer Financial Protection Bureau, ante, at 33 (plu- rality opinion); cf. Milner v. Department of Navy, 562 U. S. 562, 569–573 (2011).6 Of course, when enacting a law, Congress often does not include either a severability clause or a nonseverability clause. In those cases, it is sometimes said that courts applying severability doctrine should search for other indicia of con- gressional intent. For example, some of the Court’s cases declare that courts should sever the offending provision un- less “the statute created in its absence is legislation that Congress would not have enacted.” Alaska Airlines, 480 U. S., at 685. But experience shows that this formulation often leads to an analytical dead end. That is because courts are not well equipped to imaginatively reconstruct a prior Congress’s hypothetical intent. In other words, ab- sent a severability or nonseverability clause, a court often cannot really know what the two Houses of Congress and the President from the time of original enactment of a law would have wanted if one provision of a law were later de- clared unconstitutional. The Court’s cases have instead developed a strong pre- —————— 6 When Congress enacts a law with a severability clause and later adds new provisions to that statute, the severability clause applies to those new provisions to the extent dictated by the text of the severability clause. Likewise, when Congress has not included a severability clause in initial legislation, Congress can subsequently enact a severability clause that applies to the existing statute to the extent dictated by the text of the later-added severability clause. In both scenarios, the text of the severability clause remains central to the severability inquiry. 14 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. sumption of severability. The Court presumes that an un- constitutional provision in a law is severable from the re- mainder of the law or statute. For example, in Free Enter- prise Fund v. Public Company Accounting Oversight Bd., the Court set forth the “normal rule”: “Generally speaking, when confronting a constitutional flaw in a statute, we try to limit the solution to the problem, severing any problem- atic portions while leaving the remainder intact.” 561 U. S. 477, 508 (2010) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Seila Law, ante, at 32 (same). In Regan v. Time, Inc., the plurality opinion likewise described a “presumption” in “fa- vor of severability” and stated that the Court should “re- frain from invalidating more of the statute than is neces- sary.” 468 U. S. 641, 652–653 (1984). The Court’s power and preference to partially invalidate a statute in that fashion has been firmly established since Marbury v. Madison. There, the Court invalidated part of §13 of the Judiciary Act of 1789. 1 Cranch 137, 179–180 (1803). The Judiciary Act did not contain a severability clause. But the Court did not proceed to invalidate the en- tire Judiciary Act. As Chief Justice Marshall later ex- plained, if any part of an Act is “unconstitutional, the pro- visions of that part may be disregarded while full effect will be given to such as are not repugnant to the constitution of the United States.” Bank of Hamilton v. Lessee of Dudley, 2 Pet. 492, 526 (1829); see also Dorchy v. Kansas, 264 U. S. 286, 289–290 (1924) (“A statute bad in part is not neces- sarily void in its entirety. Provisions within the legislative power may stand if separable from the bad”); Loeb v. Co- lumbia Township Trustees, 179 U. S. 472, 490 (1900) (“one section of a statute may be repugnant to the Constitution without rendering the whole act void”). From Marbury v. Madison to the present, apart from some isolated detours mostly in the late 1800s and early 1900s, the Court’s remedial preference after finding a pro- vision of a federal law unconstitutional has been to salvage Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 15 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. rather than destroy the rest of the law passed by Congress and signed by the President. The Court’s precedents reflect a decisive preference for surgical severance rather than wholesale destruction, even in the absence of a severability clause. The Court’s presumption of severability supplies a work- able solution—one that allows courts to avoid judicial poli- cymaking or de facto judicial legislation in determining just how much of the remainder of a statute should be invali- dated.7 The presumption also reflects the confined role of the Judiciary in our system of separated powers—stated otherwise, the presumption manifests the Judiciary’s re- spect for Congress’s legislative role by keeping courts from unnecessarily disturbing a law apart from invalidating the provision that is unconstitutional. Furthermore, the pre- sumption recognizes that plaintiffs who successfully chal- lenge one provision of a law may lack standing to challenge other provisions of that law. See Murphy v. National Colle- giate Athletic Assn., 584 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2018) (THOMAS, J., concurring) (slip op., at 5–6). Those and other considerations, taken together, have steered the Court to a presumption of severability. Apply- ing the presumption, the Court invalidates and severs un- constitutional provisions from the remainder of the law ra- ther than razing whole statutes or Acts of Congress. Put in common parlance, the tail (one unconstitutional provision) —————— 7 If courts had broad license to invalidate more than just the offending provision, a reviewing court would have to consider what other provi- sions to invalidate: the whole section, the chapter, the statute, the public law, or something else altogether. Courts would be largely at sea in mak- ing that determination, and usually could not do it in a principled way. Here, for example, would a court invalidate all or part of the Bipartisan Budget Act of 2015 rather than all or part of the 1991 TCPA? After all, that 2015 Bipartisan Budget Act, not the 1991 TCPA, added the consti- tutionally problematic government-debt exception. That is the kind of free-wheeling policy question that the Court’s presumption of severabil- ity avoids. 16 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. does not wag the dog (the rest of the codified statute or the Act as passed by Congress). Constitutional litigation is not a game of gotcha against Congress, where litigants can ride a discrete constitutional flaw in a statute to take down the whole, otherwise constitutional statute. If the rule were otherwise, the entire Judiciary Act of 1789 would be invalid as a consequence of Marbury v. Madison.8 Before severing a provision and leaving the remainder of a law intact, the Court must determine that the remainder of the statute is “capable of functioning independently” and —————— 8 The term “invalidate” is a common judicial shorthand when the Court holds that a particular provision is unlawful and therefore may not be enforced against a plaintiff. To be clear, however, when it “invalidates” a law as unconstitutional, the Court of course does not formally repeal the law from the U. S. Code or the Statutes at Large. Instead, in Chief Justice Marshall’s words, the Court recognizes that the Constitution is a “superior, paramount law,” and that “a legislative act contrary to the constitution is not law” at all. Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137, 177 (1803). The Court’s authority on this front “amounts to little more than the negative power to disregard an unconstitutional enactment.” Mas- sachusetts v. Mellon, 262 U. S. 447, 488 (1923). JUSTICE THOMAS’s thoughtful approach to severability as outlined in Murphy v. National Collegiate Athletic Assn., 584 U. S. ___, ___–___ (2018) (slip op., at 2–6), and Seila Law LLC v. Consumer Financial Pro- tection Bureau, ante, at 14–24, (joined by JUSTICE GORSUCH in the latter) would simply enjoin enforcement of a law as applied to the particular plaintiffs in a case. Under either the Court’s approach or JUSTICE THOMAS’s approach, an offending provision formally remains on the stat- ute books (at least unless Congress also formally repeals it). Under ei- ther approach, the formal remedy afforded to the plaintiff is an injunc- tion, declaration, or damages. One difference between the two approaches is this: Under the Court’s approach, a provision is declared invalid and cannot be lawfully enforced against others. Under JUSTICE THOMAS’s approach, the Court’s ruling that a provision cannot be en- forced against the plaintiff, plus executive respect in its enforcement pol- icies for controlling decisional law, plus vertical and horizontal stare de- cisis in the courts, will mean that the provision will not and cannot be lawfully enforced against others. The Court and JUSTICE THOMAS take different analytical paths, but in many cases, the different paths lead to the same place. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 17 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. thus would be “fully operative” as a law. Seila Law, ante, at 33; see Murphy, 584 U. S., at ___–___ (slip op., at 25–30). But it is fairly unusual for the remainder of a law not to be operative.9 2 We next apply those general severability principles to this case. Recall how this statute came together. Passed by Con- gress and signed by President Franklin Roosevelt in 1934, the Communications Act is codified in Title 47 of the U. S. Code. The TCPA of 1991 amended the Communications Act by adding the robocall restriction, which is codified at §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) of Title 47. The Bipartisan Budget Act of 2015 then amended the Communications Act by adding the government-debt exception, which is codified along with the robocall restriction at §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) of Title 47. Since 1934, the Communications Act has contained an ex- press severability clause: “If any provision of this chapter or the application thereof to any person or circumstance is held invalid, the remainder of the chapter and the applica- tion of such provision to other persons or circumstances shall not be affected thereby.” 47 U. S. C. §608 (emphasis added). The “chapter” referred to in the severability clause is Chapter 5 of Title 47. And Chapter 5 in turn encom- passes §151 to §700 of Title 47, and therefore covers §227 of Title 47, the provision with the robocall restriction and the government-debt exception.10 —————— 9 On occasion, of course, it may be that a particular surrounding or con- nected provision is not operative in the absence of the unconstitutional provision, even though the rest of the law would be operative. That sce- nario may require severance of somewhat more than just the offending provision, albeit not of the entire law. Courts address that scenario as it arises. 10 A codifier’s note explains a change in wording from the original Pub- lic Law: “This chapter, referred to in text, was in the original ‘this Act’, 18 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. Enacted in 2015, the government-debt exception added an unconstitutional discriminatory exception to the ro- bocall restriction. The text of the severability clause squarely covers the unconstitutional government-debt ex- ception and requires that we sever it. To get around the text of the severability clause, plaintiffs point out that the Communications Act’s severability clause was enacted in 1934, long before the TCPA’s 1991 robocall restriction and the 2015 government-debt exception. But a severability clause must be interpreted according to its terms, regardless of when Congress enacted it. See n. 6, supra. Even if the severability clause did not apply to the gov- ernment-debt provision at issue in this case (or even if there were no severability clause in the Communications Act), we would apply the presumption of severability as described and applied in cases such as Free Enterprise Fund. And under that presumption, we likewise would sever the 2015 government-debt exception, the constitutionally offending provision. With the government-debt exception severed, the re- mainder of the law is capable of functioning independently and thus would be fully operative as a law. Indeed, the re- mainder of the robocall restriction did function inde- pendently and fully operate as a law for 20-plus years be- fore the government-debt exception was added in 2015. The Court’s precedents further support severing the 2015 government-debt exception. The Court has long applied severability principles in cases like this one, where Con- gress added an unconstitutional amendment to a prior law. In those cases, the Court has treated the original, pre- —————— meaning act June 19, 1934, ch. 652, 48 Stat. 1064, known as the Com- munications Act of 1934, which is classified principally to this chapter.” Note following 47 U. S. C. §608. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 19 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. amendment statute as the “valid expression of the legisla- tive intent.” Frost v. Corporation Comm’n of Okla., 278 U. S. 515, 526–527 (1929). The Court has severed the “ex- ception introduced by amendment,” so that “the original law stands without the amendatory exception.” Truax v. Corrigan, 257 U. S. 312, 342 (1921). For example, in Eberle v. Michigan, the Court held that “discriminatory wine-and-cider amendments” added in 1899 and 1903 were severable from the underlying 1889 state law generally prohibiting the manufacture of alcohol. 232 U. S. 700, 704–705 (1914). In Truax, the Court ruled that a 1913 amendment prohibiting Arizona courts from is- suing injunctions in labor disputes was invalid and severa- ble from the underlying 1901 law authorizing Arizona courts to issue injunctions generally. 257 U. S., at 341–342. In Frost, the Court concluded that a 1925 amendment ex- empting certain corporations from making a showing of “public necessity” in order to obtain a cotton gin license was invalid and severable from the 1915 law that required that showing. 278 U. S., at 525–528. Echoing Marbury, the Court in Frost explained that an unconstitutional statutory amendment “is a nullity” and “void” when enacted, and for that reason has no effect on the original statute. 278 U. S., at 526–527 (internal quotation marks omitted).11 Similarly, in 1932, Congress enacted the Federal Kidnap- ing Act, and then in 1934, added a death penalty provision to the Act. The death penalty provision was later declared unconstitutional by this Court. In considering severability, —————— 11 The cases cited in the text above are pre-Erie decisions involving the constitutionality of state laws. See Erie R. Co. v. Tompkins, 304 U. S. 64 (1938). In that era, the Court often treated severability of state laws and federal laws in the same general way. In the post-Erie era, severability of state laws can potentially pose different questions than severability of federal laws. We need not address post-Erie severability of state laws. See, e.g., Ayotte v. Planned Parenthood of Northern New Eng., 546 U. S. 320, 328–331 (2006); Leavitt v. Jane L., 518 U. S. 137, 139 (1996) (per curiam) (“Severability is of course a matter of state law”). 20 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. the Court stated that the “law as originally enacted in 1932 contained no capital punishment provision.” United States v. Jackson, 390 U. S. 570, 586 (1968). And when Congress amended the Act in 1934 to add the death penalty, “the stat- ute was left substantially unchanged in every other re- spect.” Id., at 587–588. The Court found it “difficult to im- agine a more compelling case for severability.” Id., at 589. So too here. In sum, the text of the Communications Act’s severability clause requires that the Court sever the 2015 government- debt exception from the remainder of the statute. And even if the text of the severability clause did not apply here, the presumption of severability would require that the Court sever the 2015 government-debt exception from the remain- der of the statute. 3 One final severability wrinkle remains. This is an equal- treatment case, and equal-treatment cases can sometimes pose complicated severability questions. The “First Amendment is a kind of Equal Protection Clause for ideas.” Williams-Yulee v. Florida Bar, 575 U. S. 433, 470 (2015) (Scalia, J., dissenting). And Congress vio- lated that First Amendment equal-treatment principle in this case by favoring debt-collection robocalls and discrimi- nating against political and other robocalls. When the constitutional violation is unequal treatment, as it is here, a court theoretically can cure that unequal treatment either by extending the benefits or burdens to the exempted class, or by nullifying the benefits or burdens for all. See, e.g., Heckler v. Mathews, 465 U. S. 728, 740 (1984). Here, for example, the Government would prefer to cure the unequal treatment by extending the robocall re- striction and thereby proscribing nearly all robocalls to cell phones. By contrast, plaintiffs want to cure the unequal treatment by nullifying the robocall restriction and thereby Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 21 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. allowing all robocalls to cell phones. When, as here, the Court confronts an equal-treatment constitutional violation, the Court generally applies the same commonsense severability principles described above. If the statute contains a severability clause, the Court typ- ically severs the discriminatory exception or classification, and thereby extends the relevant statutory benefits or bur- dens to those previously exempted, rather than nullifying the benefits or burdens for all. In light of the presumption of severability, the Court generally does the same even in the absence of a severability clause. The Court’s precedents reflect that preference for extension rather than nullifica- tion. See, e.g., Sessions v. Morales-Santana, 582 U. S. ___, ___ (2017) (slip op., at 25); Califano v. Westcott, 443 U. S. 76, 89–91 (1979); Califano v. Goldfarb, 430 U. S. 199, 202– 204, 213–217 (1977) (plurality opinion); Jimenez v. Wein- berger, 417 U. S. 628, 637–638 (1974); Department of Agri- culture v. Moreno, 413 U. S. 528, 529, 537–538 (1973); Fron- tiero v. Richardson, 411 U. S. 677, 678–679, 690–691 (1973) (plurality opinion); Welsh v. United States, 398 U. S. 333, 361–367 (1970) (Harlan, J., concurring in result). To be sure, some equal-treatment cases can raise complex questions about whether it is appropriate to extend benefits or burdens, rather than nullifying the benefits or burdens. See, e.g., Morales-Santana, 582 U. S. ___. For example, there can be due process, fair notice, or other independent constitutional barriers to extension of benefits or burdens. Cf. Miller v. Albright, 523 U. S. 420, 458–459 (1998) (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment); see generally Ginsburg, Some Thoughts on Judicial Authority to Repair Unconstitutional Legislation, 28 Clev. St. L. Rev. 301 (1979). There also can be knotty questions about what is the exception and what is the rule. But here, we need not tackle all of the possible hypothetical applications of severability doctrine in equal- treatment cases. The government-debt exception is a rela- tively narrow exception to the broad robocall restriction, 22 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. and severing the government-debt exception does not raise any other constitutional problems. Plaintiffs insist, however, that a First Amendment equal- treatment case is different. According to plaintiffs, a court should not cure “a First Amendment violation by outlawing more speech.” Brief for Respondents 34. The implicit prem- ise of that argument is that extending the robocall re- striction to debt-collection robocalls would be unconstitu- tional. But that is wrong. A generally applicable robocall restriction would be permissible under the First Amend- ment. Extending the robocall restriction to those robocalls raises no First Amendment problem. So the First Amend- ment does not tell us which way to cure the unequal treat- ment in this case. Therefore, we apply traditional severa- bility principles. And as we have explained, severing the 2015 government-debt exception cures the unequal treat- ment and constitutes the proper result under the Court’s traditional severability principles. In short, the correct re- sult in this case is to sever the 2015 government-debt ex- ception and leave in place the longstanding robocall re- striction.12 4 JUSTICE GORSUCH’s well-stated separate opinion makes a number of important points that warrant this respectful response. JUSTICE GORSUCH suggests that our decision provides “no relief” to plaintiffs. Post, at 6. We disagree. Plaintiffs want to be able to make political robocalls to cell phones, —————— 12 As the Government acknowledges, although our decision means the end of the government-debt exception, no one should be penalized or held liable for making robocalls to collect government debt after the effective date of the 2015 government-debt exception and before the entry of final judgment by the District Court on remand in this case, or such date that the lower courts determine is appropriate. See Reply Brief 24. On the other side of the ledger, our decision today does not negate the liability of parties who made robocalls covered by the robocall restriction. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 23 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. and they have not received that relief. But the First Amendment complaint at the heart of their suit was une- qual treatment. Invalidating and severing the government- debt exception fully addresses that First Amendment in- jury.13 JUSTICE GORSUCH further suggests that plaintiffs may lack standing to challenge the government-debt excep- tion, because that exception merely favors others. See ibid. But the Court has squarely held that a plaintiff who suffers unequal treatment has standing to challenge a discrimina- tory exception that favors others. See Heckler v. Mathews, 465 U. S., at 737–740 (a plaintiff who suffers unequal treat- ment has standing to seek “withdrawal of benefits from the favored class”); see also Northeastern Fla. Chapter, Associ- ated Gen. Contractors of America v. Jacksonville, 508 U. S. 656, 666 (1993) (“The ‘injury in fact’ in an equal protection case of this variety is the denial of equal treatment result- ing from the imposition of the barrier, not the ultimate in- ability to obtain the benefit”). JUSTICE GORSUCH also objects that our decision today “harms strangers to this suit” by eliminating favorable treatment for debt collectors. Post, at 6. But that is neces- sarily true in many cases where a court cures unequal treat- ment by, for example, extending a burden or nullifying a benefit. See, e.g., Morales-Santana, 582 U. S., at ___ (slip op., at 28) (curing unequal treatment of children born to un- wed U. S.-citizen fathers by extending a burden to children of unwed U. S.-citizen mothers); Orr v. Orr, 374 So. 2d 895, 896–897 (Ala. Civ. App. 1979) (extending alimony obliga- tions to women after a male plaintiff successfully chal- lenged Alabama’s discriminatory alimony statute in this —————— 13 Plaintiffs suggest that parties will not have incentive to sue if the cure for challenging an unconstitutional exception to a speech restriction is to eliminate the exception and extend the restriction. But many indi- viduals and organizations often have incentive to challenge unequal treatment of speech, especially when a competitor is regulated less heav- ily. 24 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. Court). Moreover, JUSTICE GORSUCH’s approach to this case would not solve the problem of harming strangers to this suit; it would just create a different and much bigger prob- lem. His proposed remedy of injunctive relief, plus stare decisis, would in effect allow all robocalls to cell phones— notwithstanding Congress’s decisive choice to prohibit most robocalls to cell phones. That is not a judicially modest ap- proach but is more of a wolf in sheep’s clothing. That ap- proach would disrespect the democratic process, through which the people’s representatives have made crystal clear that robocalls must be restricted. JUSTICE GORSUCH’s rem- edy would end up harming a different and far larger set of strangers to this suit—the tens of millions of consumers who would be bombarded every day with nonstop robocalls notwithstanding Congress’s clear prohibition of those ro- bocalls. JUSTICE GORSUCH suggests more broadly that severabil- ity doctrine may need to be reconsidered. But when and how? As the saying goes, John Marshall is not walking through that door. And this Court, in this and other recent decisions, has clarified and refined severability doctrine by emphasizing firm adherence to the text of severability clauses, and underscoring the strong presumption of sever- ability. The doctrine as so refined is constitutionally well- rooted, see, e.g., Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137 (Mar- shall, C. J.), and can be predictably applied. True, there is no magic solution to severability that solves every conun- drum, especially in equal-treatment cases, but the Court’s current approach as reflected in recent cases such as Free Enterprise Fund and Seila Law is constitutional, stable, predictable, and commonsensical. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 25 Opinion of KAVANAUGH, J. * * * In 1991, Congress enacted a general restriction on ro- bocalls to cell phones. In 2015, Congress carved out an ex- ception that allowed robocalls made to collect government debt. In doing so, Congress favored debt-collection speech over plaintiffs’ political speech. We hold that the 2015 gov- ernment-debt exception added an unconstitutional excep- tion to the law. We cure that constitutional violation by invalidating the 2015 government-debt exception and sev- ering it from the remainder of the statute. The judgment of the U. S. Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit is af- firmed. It is so ordered. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 1 SOTOMAYOR, J., concurring in judgment SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 19–631 _________________ WILLIAM P. BARR, ATTORNEY GENERAL, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. AMERICAN ASSOCIATION OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC., ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT [July 6, 2020] JUSTICE SOTOMAYOR, concurring in the judgment. I agree with much of the partial dissent’s explanation that strict scrutiny should not apply to all content-based distinctions. Cf. post, at 5–9 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment with respect to severability and dissenting in part). In my view, however, the government-debt exception in 47 U. S. C. §227(b) still fails intermediate scrutiny be- cause it is not “narrowly tailored to serve a significant gov- ernmental interest.” Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781, 791 (1989) (internal quotation marks omitted). Even under intermediate scrutiny, the Government has not explained how a debt-collection robocall about a govern- ment-backed debt is any less intrusive or could be any less harassing than a debt-collection robocall about a privately backed debt. As the Fourth Circuit noted, the government- debt exception is seriously underinclusive because it per- mits “many of the intrusive calls that the automated call ban was enacted to prohibit.” American Assn. of Political Consultants, Inc. v. FCC, 923 F. 3d 159, 168 (2019) (case below). The Government could have employed far less re- strictive means to further its interest in collecting debt, such as “secur[ing] consent from the debtors to make debt- collection calls” or “plac[ing] the calls itself.” Id., at 169, 2 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. SOTOMAYOR, J., concurring in judgment n. 10; see also §227(b)(1)(A). Nor has the Government “suf- ficiently justified the differentiation between government- debt collection speech and other important categories of ro- bocall speech, such as political speech, charitable fundrais- ing, issue advocacy, commercial advertising, and the like.” Ante, at 9. Nevertheless, I agree that the offending provision is sev- erable. See ante, at 2; post, at 11–12 (opinion of BREYER, J.); see also City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43, 51–53 (1994) (explaining that an appropriate “solution” to a law that covers “too little speech because its exemptions dis- criminate on the basis of [the speaker’s] messages” could be to “remove” the discrimination). With those understandings, I concur in the judgment. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 1 BREYER, J., concurring Opinioninofpart and, dissenting BREYER J. in part SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 19–631 _________________ WILLIAM P. BARR, ATTORNEY GENERAL, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. AMERICAN ASSOCIATION OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC., ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT [July 6, 2020] JUSTICE BREYER, with whom JUSTICE GINSBURG and JUSTICE KAGAN join, concurring in the judgment with re- spect to severability and dissenting in part. A federal statute forbids, with some exceptions, making automatically dialed or prerecorded telephone calls (called robocalls) to cell phones. This case concerns one of these exceptions, which applies to calls “made solely to collect a debt owed to or guaranteed by the United States.” 47 U. S. C. §227(b)(1)(A)(iii). A majority of the Court holds that the exception violates the Constitution’s First Amend- ment. In my view, it does not. I This case concerns the Telephone Consumer Protection Act of 1991. That Act was designed to “protec[t ] telephone consumers from th[e] nuisance and privacy invasion” caused by automated and prerecorded phone calls. §2(12), 105 Stat. 2395. The Act, among other things, bans almost all robocalls made to cell phones. In particular, it forbids “any call (other than a call made for emergency purposes or made with the prior express consent of the called party) us- ing any automatic telephone dialing system or an artificial or prerecorded voice . . . to any telephone number assigned to a . . . cellular telephone service.” §3(a) (codified at 47 2 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of BREYER, J. U. S. C. §227(b)(1)(A)(iii)). The Act delegates authority to the Federal Communications Commission to make certain additional exceptions from that general cell phone robocall restriction. §227(b)(2)(C). More than 20 years later, Congress enacted another stat- ute, which created the government-debt exception. The Of- fice of Management and Budget had reported to Congress that in “this time of fiscal constraint . . . the Federal Gov- ernment should ensure that all debt owed to the United States is collected as quickly and efficiently as possible.” Office of Management and Budget, Analytical Perspectives, Budget of the U. S. Government, Fiscal Year 2016, p. 128 (2015), https://www.govinfo.gov/content/pkg/BUDGET- 2016-PER/pdf/BUDGET-2016-PER.pdf. It recommended that Congress permit “the use of automatic dialing systems and prerecorded voice messages” to contact “wireless phones in the collection of debt owed to or granted [sic] by the United States.” Ibid. Congress adopted that recommendation. It enacted a provision that excepts from the general cell phone robocall restriction any call “made solely to collect a debt owed to or guaranteed by the United States.” 129 Stat. 588; see also ibid. (categorizing the exception as a “debt collection im- provemen[t]” measure). The question here is whether the First Amendment prohibits the Federal Government from enacting that government-debt collection measure. II The plurality finds the government-debt exception un- constitutional primarily by applying a logical syllogism: (1) “Content-based laws are subject to strict scrutiny.” Ante, at 6 (citing Reed v. Town of Gilbert, 576 U. S. 155, 163–164 (2015)). (2) The exception is based on “content.” Ante, at 7. (3) Hence, the exception is subject to “strict scrutiny.” Ante, at 9. (4) And the Government concedes that the exception cannot survive “strict scrutiny” examination. Ibid. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 3 Opinion of BREYER, J. The problem with that approach, which reflexively ap- plies strict scrutiny to all content-based speech distinctions, is that it is divorced from First Amendment values. This case primarily involves commercial regulation—namely, debt collection. And, in my view, there is no basis here to apply “strict scrutiny” based on “content-discrimination.” To appreciate why, it is important to understand at least one set of values that underlie the First Amendment and the related reasons why courts scrutinize some speech re- strictions strictly. The concept is abstract but simple: “We the People of the United States” have created a government of laws enacted by elected representatives. For our govern- ment to remain a democratic republic, the people must be free to generate, debate, and discuss both general and spe- cific ideas, hopes, and experiences. The people must then be able to transmit their resulting views and conclusions to their elected representatives, which they may do directly, or indirectly through the shaping of public opinion. The ob- ject of that transmission is to influence the public policy en- acted by elected representatives. As this Court has ex- plained, “[t]he First Amendment was fashioned to assure unfettered interchange of ideas for the bringing about of po- litical and social changes desired by the people.” Meyer v. Grant, 486 U. S. 414, 421 (1988) (internal quotation marks omitted). See generally R. Post, Democracy, Expertise, and Academic Freedom: A First Amendment Jurisprudence for the Modern State 1–25 (2012). In other words, the free marketplace of ideas is not simply a debating society for expressing thought in a vacuum. It is in significant part an instrument for “bringing about . . . political and social chang[e ].” Meyer, 486 U. S., at 421. The representative democracy that “We the People” have cre- ated insists that this be so. See Sorrell v. IMS Health Inc., 564 U. S. 552, 583 (2011) (BREYER, J., dissenting). See gen- erally, e.g., B. Neuborne, Madison’s Music: On Reading the First Amendment (2015). 4 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of BREYER, J. It is thus no surprise that our First Amendment jurispru- dence has long reflected these core values. This Court’s cases have provided heightened judicial protection for polit- ical speech, public forums, and the expression of all view- points on any given issue. See, e.g., Buckley v. American Constitutional Law Foundation, Inc., 525 U. S. 182, 186– 187 (1999) (heightened protection for “core political speech”); Rosenberger v. Rector and Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U. S. 819, 829–830 (1995) (government discrimination on basis of “particular views taken by speakers on a subject” presumptively unconstitutional); Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312, 321 (1988) (“content-based restriction[s] on political speech in a public forum” subject to “most exacting scru- tiny” (emphasis deleted)); Perry Ed. Assn. v. Perry Local Ed- ucators’ Assn., 460 U. S. 37, 45–46 (1983) (content-based ex- clusions in public forums subject to strict scrutiny). These cases reflect the straightforward principle that “govern- ments must not be allowed to choose which issues are worth discussing or debating.” Reed, 576 U. S., at 182 (KAGAN, J., concurring in judgment) (internal quotation marks omit- ted). From a democratic perspective, however, it is equally im- portant that courts not use the First Amendment in a way that would threaten the workings of ordinary regulatory programs posing little threat to the free marketplace of ideas enacted as result of that public discourse. As a gen- eral matter, the strictest scrutiny should not apply indis- criminately to the very “political and social changes desired by the people”—that is, to those government programs which the “unfettered interchange of ideas” has sought to achieve. Meyer, 486 U. S., at 421 (internal quotation marks omitted). Otherwise, our democratic system would fail, not through the inability of the people to speak or to transmit their views to government, but because of an elected gov- ernment’s inability to translate those views into action. Thus, once again, it is not surprising that this Court has Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 5 Opinion of BREYER, J. applied less strict standards when reviewing speech re- strictions embodied in government regulatory programs. This Court, for example, has applied a “rational basis” standard for reviewing those restrictions when they have only indirect impacts on speech. See Glickman v. Wileman Brothers & Elliott, Inc., 521 U. S. 457, 469–470, 477 (1997). And it has applied a mid-level standard of review—often termed “intermediate scrutiny”—when the government di- rectly restricts protected commercial speech. See Central Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Public Serv. Comm’n of N. Y., 447 U. S. 557, 561–564 (1980). This account of well-established principles at the core of the First Amendment demonstrates the problem with the plurality’s approach. To reflexively treat all content-based distinctions as subject to strict scrutiny regardless of con- text or practical effect is to engage in an analysis unteth- ered from the First Amendment’s objectives. And in this case, strict scrutiny is inappropriate. Recall that the excep- tion at issue here concerns debt collection—specifically a method for collecting government-owned or -backed debt. Regulation of debt collection does not fall on the first side of the democratic equation. It has next to nothing to do with the free marketplace of ideas or the transmission of the peo- ple’s thoughts and will to the government. It has every- thing to do with the second side of the equation, that is, with government response to the public will through ordinary commercial regulation. To apply the strictest level of scru- tiny to the economically based exemption here is thus re- markable. I recognize that the underlying cell phone robocall re- striction primarily concerns a means of communication. And that fact, as I discuss below, triggers some heightened scrutiny, reflected in an intermediate scrutiny standard. Strict scrutiny and its strong presumption of unconstitu- tionality, however, have no place here. 6 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of BREYER, J. The plurality claims that its approach, which categori- cally applies strict scrutiny to content-based distinctions, will not “affect traditional or ordinary economic regulation of commercial activity.” Ante, at 9. But how is that so? Much of human life involves activity that takes place through speech. And much regulatory activity turns upon speech content. See, e.g., Reed, 576 U. S., at 177–178 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment) (giving examples). Consider, for example, the regulation of securities sales, drug labeling, food labeling, false advertising, workplace safety warnings, automobile airbag instructions, consumer electronic labels, tax forms, debt collection, and so on. All of those regulations necessarily involve content-based speech distinctions. What are the differences between reg- ulatory programs themselves other than differences based on content? After all, the regulatory spheres in which the Securities and Exchange Commission or the Federal Trade Commission operate are defined by content. Put simply, treating all content-based distinctions on speech as pre- sumptively unconstitutional is unworkable and would ob- struct the ordinary workings of democratic governance. That conclusion is true here notwithstanding the plural- ity’s effort to bring political speech into the First Amend- ment analysis. See ante, at 7, 25 (characterizing Congress as having “favored debt-collection speech over plaintiffs’ po- litical speech”). It is true that the underlying cell phone robocall restriction generally prohibits political speakers from making robocalls. But that has little to do with the government-debt exception or its practical effect. Nor does it justify the application of strict scrutiny. Consider prescription drug labels, securities forms, and tax statements. A government agency might reasonably specify just what information the form or label must contain and further provide that the form or label may not contain other information (thereby excluding political statements). No one would think that the exclusion of political speech, Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 7 Opinion of BREYER, J. say, from a drug label, means that courts must examine all other regulatory exceptions with strict scrutiny. Put differ- ently, it is hard to imagine that such exceptions threaten political speech in the marketplace of ideas, or have any sig- nificant impact on the free exchange of ideas. To treat those exceptions as presumptively unconstitutional would work a significant transfer of authority from legislatures and agen- cies to courts, potentially inhibiting the creation of the very government programs for which the people (after debate) have voiced their support, despite those programs’ minimal speech-related harms. See Sorrell, 564 U. S., at 584–585 (BREYER, J., dissenting). Given the values at the heart of the First Amendment, see supra, at 3–5, that interpretation threatens to stand that Amendment on its head. It could also lead the Court to water down the strict scrutiny stand- ard, which would limit speech protections in situations where strict scrutiny’s strong protections should properly apply. Reed, 576 U. S., at 178 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment). If, as I have argued, the First Amendment does not sup- port the mechanical conclusion that content discrimination automatically triggers strict scrutiny, what role might con- tent discrimination play? The plurality is correct when it quotes this Court as having said that the government may not discriminate “ ‘in the regulation of expression on the ba- sis of the content of that expression.’ ” Ante, at 6 (quoting Hudgens v. NLRB, 424 U. S. 507, 520 (1976)). If, however, this Court is to apply the First Amendment consistently with the democratic values embodied within that Amend- ment, that kind of statement must reflect a rule of thumb applicable only in certain circumstances. See Reed, 576 U. S., at 176 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment); id., at 183 (KAGAN, J., concurring in judgment) (“We can adminis- ter our content-regulation doctrine with a dose of common sense, so as to leave standing laws that in no way implicate its intended function”). 8 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of BREYER, J. Indeed, that must be so given that this Court’s First Amendment jurisprudence itself ties the constitutional pro- tection speech receives to the content or purpose of that speech. The Court has held that entire categories of speech—for example, obscenity, fraud, and speech integral to criminal conduct—are generally unprotected by the First Amendment entirely because of their content. See Miller v. California, 413 U. S. 15, 23 (1973) (obscenity); Virginia Bd. of Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U. S. 748, 771 (1976) (fraud); Giboney v. Empire Stor- age & Ice Co., 336 U. S. 490, 498 (1949) (speech integral to criminal conduct). As Justice Stevens pointed out, “our en- tire First Amendment jurisprudence creates a regime based on the content of speech.” R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. 377, 420 (1992) (opinion concurring in judgment); see id., at 420–422 (providing examples). Given that this Court looks to the nature and content of speech to determine whether, or to what extent, the First Amendment protects it, it makes little sense to treat every content-based distinction Congress has made as presumptively unconstitutional. Moreover, it is no answer to claim that this Court’s prec- edents categorically require such an analysis. See ante, at 9, n. 5 (plurality opinion). Our First Amendment jurispru- dence has always been contextual and has defied straight- forward reduction to unyielding categorical rules. The idea that broad language in any one case (even Reed) has cate- gorically determined how content discrimination should be applied in every single context is both wrong and reflects an oversimplification and over-reading of our precedent. The diversity of approaches in this very case underscores the point that the law here is far from settled. Indeed, the plu- rality itself disclaims the idea that its rule would apply to unsettle “traditional or ordinary economic regulation of commercial activity,” indicating that the plurality presum- ably thinks there are some outer bounds to its broad lan- guage. Ante, at 9. The question here is whether the Court’s Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 9 Opinion of BREYER, J. general statements about content discrimination triggering strict scrutiny, including in Reed, make sense as applied in this context. As I have explained, they do not. That said, I am not arguing for the abolition of the con- cept of “content discrimination.” There are times when us- ing content discrimination to trigger scrutiny is eminently reasonable. Specifically, when content-based distinctions are used as a method for suppressing particular viewpoints or threatening the neutrality of a traditional public forum, content discrimination triggering strict scrutiny is gener- ally appropriate. See Reed, 576 U. S., at 176 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment); id., at 182–183 (KAGAN, J., con- curring in judgment). Neither of those situations is present here. Outside of these circumstances, content discrimination can at times help determine the strength of a government justification or identify a potential interference with the free market- place of ideas. See id., at 176–177 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment). But, as I have explained, this case is not about protecting the marketplace of ideas. It is not about the formation of public opinion or the transmission of the people’s will to elected representatives. It is fundamentally about a method of regulating debt collection. III I would examine the validity of the regulation at issue here using a First Amendment standard that (unlike strict scrutiny) does not strongly presume that a regulation that affects speech is unconstitutional. However, given that the government-debt exception does directly impact a means of communication, the appropriate standard requires a closer look at the restriction than does a traditional “rational ba- sis” test. A proper inquiry should examine the seriousness of the speech-related harm, the importance of countervail- ing objectives, the likelihood that the restriction will achieve those objectives, and whether there are other, less 10 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of BREYER, J. restrictive ways of doing so. Narrow tailoring in this con- text, however, does not necessarily require the use of the least-restrictive means of furthering those objectives. Cf. Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781, 797–799, and n. 6 (1989) (explaining that outside of strict scrutiny review, narrow tailoring does not require the use of least-restric- tive-means analysis). That inquiry ultimately evaluates a restriction’s speech-related harms in light of its justifica- tions. We have typically called this approach “intermediate scrutiny,” though we have sometimes referred to it as an assessment of “fit,” sometimes called it “proportionality,” and sometimes just applied it without using a label. See United States v. Alvarez, 567 U. S. 709, 730–731 (2012) (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment); Reed, 576 U. S., at 179 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment). Applying this Court’s intermediate scrutiny analysis, I would begin by asking just what the First Amendment harm is here. As JUSTICE KAVANAUGH notes, the govern- ment-debt exception provides no basis for undermining the general cell phone robocall restriction. Ante, at 10–11. In- deed, looking at the government-debt exception in context, we can see that the practical effect of the exception, taken together with the rest of the statute, is to put non-govern- ment debt collectors at a disadvantage. Their speech oper- ates in the same sphere as government-debt collection speech, communicates comparable messages, and yet does not have the benefit of a particular instrument of commu- nication (robocalls). While this is a speech-related harm, debt-collection speech is both commercial and highly regu- lated. See Brief for Petitioners 20–21 (describing multiple restrictions imposed by the Fair Debt Collection Practices Act on communications by debt collectors in the course of debt collection). The speech-related harm at issue here— and any related effect on the marketplace of ideas—is mod- est. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 11 Opinion of BREYER, J. What, then, is the justification for this harm? The pur- pose of the exception is to further the protection of the pub- lic fisc. See supra, at 2. That protection is an important governmental interest. Private debt typically involves pri- vate funds; public debt typically involves funds that, in principle, belong to all of us, and help to implement numer- ous governmental policies that the people support. Finally, is the exception narrowly tailored? Its limited scope shows that it is. Congress has minimized any speech- related harm by tying the exception directly to the Govern- ment’s interest in preserving the public fisc. The statutory text makes clear that calls will only fall within the bounds of that exception if they are “made solely to collect” Govern- ment debt. 47 U. S. C. §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) (emphasis added). Thus, the exception cannot be used to permit communica- tions unrelated or less directly related to that public fiscal interest. The upshot is that the government-debt exception, taken in context, inflicts some speech-related harm. But the harm, as I have explained, is related not to public efforts to develop ideas or transmit them to the Government, but to the Government’s response to those efforts, which here takes the form of highly regulated commercial communica- tions. Moreover, there is an important justification for that harm, and the exception is narrowly tailored to further that goal. Given those facts, the government-debt exception should survive intermediate First Amendment scrutiny. IV For the reasons described above, I would find that the government-debt exception does not violate the First Amendment. A majority of the Court, however, has con- cluded the contrary. It must thus decide whether that pro- vision is severable from the rest of the statute. As to that question, I agree with JUSTICE KAVANAUGH’s conclusion that the provision is severable. Accordingly, I respectfully 12 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of BREYER, J. concur in the judgment with respect to severability and dis- sent in part. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 1 GORSUCH, J., concurring inGpart Opinion of and,dissenting ORSUCH J. in part SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES _________________ No. 19–631 _________________ WILLIAM P. BARR, ATTORNEY GENERAL, ET AL., PETITIONERS v. AMERICAN ASSOCIATION OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC., ET AL. ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT [July 6, 2020] JUSTICE GORSUCH, with whom JUSTICE THOMAS joins as to Part II, concurring in the judgment in part and dissent- ing in part. I agree with JUSTICE KAVANAUGH that the provision of the Telephone Consumer Protection Act before us violates the First Amendment. Respectfully, however, I disagree about why that is so and what remedial consequences should follow. I The TCPA is full of regulations on robocalls. The statute limits robocalls to residential landlines, hospitals, emer- gency numbers, and business lines. The only provision be- fore us today, however, concerns robocalls to cell phones, mobile devices, or “any service for which the called party is charged for the call.” 47 U. S. C. §227(b)(1)(A)(iii). Before the law’s enactment, many cell phone users had to pay for each call, so they suffered not only the pleasure of robocalls, but also the privilege of paying for them. In 1991, Congress sought to address the problem by banning nearly all unso- licited robocalls to cell phones. But much has changed since then. Now, cell phone users often pay a flat monthly fee for unlimited minutes, reducing the cost (if not the annoyance) of hearing from robocallers. 2 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of GORSUCH, J. New weapons in the fight against robocallers have emerged, too—including tools that allow consumers to more easily screen and block unwanted calls. Perhaps in recog- nition of these changes, Congress relaxed the ban on cell- phone robocallers in 2015. Today, unsolicited calls are per- mitted if they are “made solely to collect a debt owed to or guaranteed by the United States.” That leaves robocallers no shortage of material. The gov- ernment backs millions upon millions of loans—student loans, home mortgages, veterans’ loans, farm loans, busi- ness loans. When it comes to student loans alone, the gov- ernment guarantees more than $150 billion in private loans involving over 7 million individuals. And, to be clear, it’s not just the government that’s allowed to call about these loans. Private lenders and debt collectors are free to send in the robots too, so long as the debt at issue is ultimately guaranteed by the government. Today’s plaintiffs wish to use robocalls for something dif- ferent: to campaign and solicit donations for political causes. The plaintiffs allege that the law’s continuing ban on calls like theirs violates the First Amendment, and on the main points of their argument the parties agree. First, no one doubts the TCPA regulates speech. Second, every- one accepts that restrictions on speech—no matter how ev- enhanded—must be justified by at least a “ ‘significant gov- ernmental interest.’ ” Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781, 791 (1989). And, third, the parties agree that laws that go further by regulating speech on the basis of content invite still greater scrutiny. When the government seeks to censor speech based on its content, favoring certain voices and punishing others, its restrictions must satisfy “strict scrutiny”—meaning they must be justified by inter- ests that are “compelling,” not just significant. After all, a constitutional right would hardly be needed to protect pop- ular speakers; the First Amendment does its real work in Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 3 Opinion of GORSUCH, J. giving voice to those a majority would silence. See McCul- len v. Coakley, 573 U. S. 464, 477–478 (2014); but see ante, at 5–6 (BREYER, J., concurring in judgment with respect to severability and dissenting in part) (seeking to overturn precedent and allow the government sometimes to impose content-based restrictions to “respon[d] to the public will”). In my view, the TCPA’s rule against cellphone robocalls is a content-based restriction that fails strict scrutiny. The statute is content-based because it allows speech on a sub- ject the government favors (collecting its debts) while ban- ning speech on other disfavored subjects (including political matters). Cf. ante, at 9–11 (opinion of BREYER, J.) (mistak- enly characterizing the content discrimination as “not about” political activities). The statute fails strict scrutiny because the government offers no compelling justification for its prohibition against the plaintiffs’ political speech. In fact, the government does not dispute that, if strict scrutiny applies, its law must fall. It’s easy enough to see why the government makes no ef- fort to satisfy strict scrutiny. Now that most cell phone plans do not charge by the call, the only justification the government cites for its robocall ban is its interest in pro- tecting consumer privacy. No one questions that protecting consumer privacy qualifies as a legitimate and “genuine” interest for the government to pursue. Ante, at 2–3, 10. But before the government may censor the plaintiffs’ speech based on its content, it must point to a compelling interest. And if the government thinks consumer privacy interests are insufficient to overcome its interest in collecting debts, it’s hard to see how the government might invoke consumer privacy interests to justify banning private political speech. Especially when consumers seem to find debt collection ef- forts particularly intrusive: Year after year, the Federal Trade Commission receives more complaints about the debt collection industry than any other. The nature and breadth of the law’s exception calls into question the necessity of its 4 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of GORSUCH, J. rule. Much precedent supports this course. As this Court has long explained, a law’s failure to address a wide swath of conduct implicating its supposed concern “diminish[es] the credibility of the government’s [stated] rationale for [its] re- strict[ion].” City of Ladue v. Gilleo, 512 U. S. 43, 52 (1994). Or, as the Court has elsewhere put it, the compellingness of the government’s putative interest is undermined when its law “leaves appreciable damage to [the] supposedly vital interest unprohibited.” Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye, Inc. v. Hialeah, 508 U. S. 520, 547 (1993) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Gonzales v. O Centro Espírita Be- neficente União do Vegetal, 546 U. S. 418, 433 (2006). The insight is simple: A law’s failure to cover “significant tracts of conduct implicating [its] putatively compelling interes[t] can raise . . . the inference that the . . . claimed interest isn’t . . . so compelling after all.” Yellowbear v. Lampert, 741 F. 3d 48, 60 (CA10 2014). That’s not to say the inference is irrebuttable. The gov- ernment might, for example, show that the apparent incon- sistency in its law is justified by some qualitative or quan- titative difference between the speech it favors and the speech it disfavors. See id., at 61. So if debt collection ro- bocalls were less invasive of consumer privacy than other kinds of robocalls, or if they were inherently rare, an excep- tion permitting debt collection calls might not undermine the government’s claimed interest in banning other calls. But the government, a party with every incentive and am- ple resources, has not even tried to suggest conditions like those are present here, and understandably so: The government-debt exception allows a seemingly infinite number of robocalls of the type consumers appear to find most invasive. II With a First Amendment violation proven, the question Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 5 Opinion of GORSUCH, J. turns to remedy. Because the challenged robocall ban un- constitutionally infringes on their speech, I would hold that the plaintiffs are entitled to an injunction preventing its en- forcement against them. This is the traditional remedy for proven violations of legal rights likely to work irreparable injury in the future. Preventing the law’s enforcement against the plaintiffs would fully address their injury. And going this far, but no further, would avoid “short circuit[ing] the democratic process” by interfering with the work of Con- gress any more than necessary. Washington State Grange v. Washington State Republican Party, 552 U. S. 442, 451 (2008). JUSTICE KAVANAUGH’s opinion pursues a different course. Invoking “severability doctrine,” it declares the government-debt exception void and severs it from the stat- ute. As revised by today’s decision, the law prohibits nearly all robocalls to cell phones, just as it did back in 1991. In support of this remedy, we are asked to consider cases in- volving equal protection violations, where courts have sometimes solved the problem of unequal treatment by lev- eling others “down” to the plaintiff ’s status rather than by leveling the plaintiff “up” to the status others enjoy. I am doubtful of our authority to rewrite the law in this way. Many have questioned the propriety of modern sever- ability doctrine,* and today’s case illustrates some of the reasons why. To start, it’s hard to see how today’s use of severability doctrine qualifies as a remedy at all: The plain- tiffs have not challenged the government-debt exception, they have not sought to have it severed and stricken, and far from placing “unequal treatment” at the “heart of their —————— *See, e.g., Seila Law LLC v. Consumer Financial Protection Bureau, ante, at 14–24 (THOMAS, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part); Harrison, Severability, Remedies, and Constitutional Adjudication, 83 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 56 (2014); see also Movsesian, Severability in Stat- utes and Contracts, 30 Ga. L. Rev. 41, 41–42 (1995) (collecting academic criticism of severability doctrine). 6 BARR v. AMERICAN ASSN. OF POLITICAL CONSULTANTS, INC. Opinion of GORSUCH, J. suit,” they have never complained of unequal treatment as such. Ante, at 23. The plaintiffs point to the government- debt exception only to show that the government lacks a compelling interest in restricting their speech. It isn’t even clear the plaintiffs would have standing to challenge the government-debt exception. They came to court asserting a right to speak, not a right to be free from other speakers. Severing and voiding the government-debt exception does nothing to address the injury they claim; after today’s rul- ing, federal law bars the plaintiffs from using robocalls to promote political causes just as stoutly as it did before. What is the point of fighting this long battle, through many years and all the way to the Supreme Court, if the prize for winning is no relief at all? A severance remedy not only fails to help the plaintiffs, it harms strangers to this suit. Just five years ago, Congress expressly authorized robocalls to cell phones to collect gov- ernment-backed debts. Yet, today, the Court reverses that decision and outlaws the entire industry. It is highly unu- sual for judges to render unlawful conduct that Congress has explicitly made lawful—let alone to take such an ex- traordinary step without warning to those who have or- dered their lives and livelihoods in reliance on the law, and without affording those individuals any opportunity to be heard. This assertion of power strikes me as raising serious separation of powers questions, and it marks no small de- parture from our usual reliance on the adversarial process. Nor does the analogy to equal protection doctrine solve the problem. That doctrine promises equality of treatment, whatever that treatment may be. The First Amendment isn’t so neutral. It pushes, always, in one direction: against governmental restrictions on speech. Yet, somehow, in the name of vindicating the First Amendment, our remedial course today leads to the unlikely result that not a single person will be allowed to speak more freely and, instead, more speech will be banned. Cite as: 591 U. S. ____ (2020) 7 Opinion of GORSUCH, J. In an effort to mitigate at least some of these problems, JUSTICE KAVANAUGH suggests that the ban on government- debt collection calls announced today might be applied only prospectively. See ante, at 22, n. 13. But prospective deci- sionmaking has never been easy to square with the judicial power. See, e.g., James B. Beam Distilling Co. v. Georgia, 501 U. S. 529, 548–549 (Scalia, J., concurring in judgment) (judicial power is limited to “discerning what the law is, ra- ther than decreeing . . . what it will tomorrow be”). And a holding that shields only government-debt collection callers from past liability under an admittedly unconstitutional law would wind up endorsing the very same kind of content discrimination we say we are seeking to eliminate. Unable to solve the problems associated with its pre- ferred severance remedy, today’s decision seeks at least to identify “harm[s]” associated with mine. Cf. ante, at 24 (opinion of KAVANAUGH, J.). In particular, we are reminded that granting an injunction in this case would allow the plaintiffs’ (unpopular) speech, and that could induce others to seek injunctions of their own, resulting in still more (un- popular) speech. But this “harm” is hardly comparable to the problems associated with using severability doctrine: Having to tolerate unwanted speech imposes no cognizable constitutional injury on anyone; it is life under the First Amendment, which is almost always invoked to protect speech some would rather not hear. * In the end, I agree that 47 U. S. C. §227(b)(1)(A)(iii) vio- lates the First Amendment, though not for the reasons JUSTICE KAVANAUGH offers. Nor am I able to support the remedy the Court endorses today. Respectfully, if this is what modern “severability doctrine” has become, it seems to me all the more reason to reconsider our course.