Opinions of the Colorado Supreme Court are available to the
public and can be accessed through the Judicial Branch’s
homepage at http://www.courts.state.co.us. Opinions are also
posted on the Colorado Bar Association’s homepage at
http://www.cobar.org.
ADVANCE SHEET HEADNOTE
September 21, 2020
2020 CO 75
No. 18SC607, People v. Jackson—Transferred Intent—Bad-Aim Cases—
Mistaken-Identity Cases—Double Jeopardy.
The defendant was convicted, as a complicitor, of both first degree murder
and attempted first degree murder after his codefendant aimed at, shot, and killed
Y.M. under the mistaken belief that Y.M. was E.O. A division of the court of
appeals ruled that the Double Jeopardy Clauses of the federal and state
constitutions dictate that Jackson cannot stand convicted of both offenses because
the latter is a lesser included offense of the former. But in doing so, the division
relied on the doctrine of transferred intent, a legal fiction that some courts use
largely to ensure that a defendant doesn’t escape liability in what is widely known
as a bad-aim situation (i.e., A aims at and shoots toward B, but misses due to his
bad aim and accidentally hits and kills C, an innocent bystander).
Because Colorado’s broad statutory definition of first degree murder
encompasses unintended victims and renders the transferred intent doctrine
unnecessary, the supreme court disapproves of the doctrine in first degree murder
cases. Further, the supreme court holds that, even if the first degree murder statute
didn’t make the transferred intent doctrine unnecessary, the doctrine would still
be irrelevant here because this is a mistaken-identity case, not a bad-aim case.
Unlike a bad-aim case, where A aims at and shoots toward B but misses and kills
C (an innocent bystander) by accident, in a mistaken-identity case, A aims at, shoots,
and kills C by mistake (A hits his target, mistakenly believing that C is B). Hence,
while a bad-aim case involves two victims (the person the perpetrator aimed at
and shot toward and the unintended victim harmed by the bullet), a mistaken-
identity case like this one involves only one victim (the person the perpetrator
aimed at and shot with the intent to kill, albeit by mistake). It follows that in a
mistaken-identity case, there is no need to transfer the perpetrator’s intent from
one victim to another—the concept of transferred intent is immaterial.
The supreme court determines that the shooter here did not attempt to kill
E.O. when he aimed at and shot Y.M. Rather, in aiming at and shooting Y.M., the
shooter intended and attempted to kill Y.M., the same person he actually killed.
That the shooter wanted to kill E.O. and mistakenly believed Y.M. was E.O. is of
no moment. Therefore, the defendant’s convictions for first degree murder and
attempted first degree murder are based on the same criminal conduct and relate
to the same victim (Y.M.).
Accordingly, although the supreme court agrees that the trial court plainly
erred in entering convictions and imposing sentences for both of the offenses in
question, its rationale differs from the division’s. The division’s judgment is thus
affirmed on other grounds. The matter is remanded with instructions to return
the case to the trial court to vacate the conviction and sentence for the lesser
included offense of attempted first degree murder.
The Supreme Court of the State of Colorado
2 East 14th Avenue • Denver, Colorado 80203
2020 CO 75
Supreme Court Case No. 18SC607
Certiorari to the Colorado Court of Appeals
Court of Appeals Case No. 16CA854
Petitioner:
The People of the State of Colorado,
v.
Respondent:
Brandon Jackson.
Judgment Affirmed
en banc
September 21, 2020
Attorneys for Petitioner:
Philip J. Weiser, Attorney General
Matthew S. Holman, First Assistant Attorney General
Denver, Colorado
Attorneys for Respondent:
Samler & Whitson, P.C.
Eric A. Samler
Hollis A. Whitson
Denver, Colorado
JUSTICE SAMOUR delivered the Opinion of the Court.
¶1 After deliberation and with the intent to kill, A aims at and shoots someone
he mistakenly believes is B but who turns out to be C, and C dies from the gunshot
wound. The question that typically arises from this factual scenario is whether A
may be convicted of murder in the first degree after deliberation and with intent
(“first degree murder”) for killing C. Here, no one disputes that the answer to this
question is “yes.” Where the parties cross swords is on the issue of whether, as
the People argue, A may additionally be convicted of criminal attempt to commit
murder in the first degree after deliberation and with intent (“attempted first
degree murder”) for wanting to kill B. A division of the court of appeals correctly
rejected the People’s position on double jeopardy principles. But in doing so, it
relied on the doctrine of transferred intent, a legal fiction that some courts use
largely to ensure that a defendant doesn’t escape liability in what is widely known
as a bad-aim situation (i.e., A aims at and shoots toward B, but misses due to his
bad aim and accidentally hits and kills C, an innocent bystander).
¶2 Because Colorado’s broad statutory definition of first degree murder
encompasses unintended victims and renders the transferred intent doctrine
unnecessary, we now disapprove of the doctrine in first degree murder cases.
Even if our first degree murder statute didn’t make the transferred intent doctrine
unnecessary, the doctrine would still be irrelevant here because this is a mistaken-
identity case, not a bad-aim case. Unlike a bad-aim case, where A aims at and
2
shoots toward B but misses and kills C (an innocent bystander) by accident, in a
mistaken-identity case, A aims at, shoots, and kills C by mistake (A hits his target,
mistakenly believing that C is B). Thus, while a bad-aim case involves two victims
(the person the perpetrator aimed at and shot toward and the unintended victim
harmed by the bullet), a mistaken-identity case like this one involves only one
victim (the person the perpetrator aimed at and shot with the intent to kill, albeit
by mistake). It follows that in a mistaken-identity case, there is no need to transfer
the perpetrator’s intent from one victim to another—the concept of transferred
intent is immaterial.
¶3 As relevant here, Brandon Jackson was convicted, as a complicitor, of both
first degree murder and attempted first degree murder after his codefendant
aimed at, shot, and killed Y.M. under the mistaken belief that Y.M. was E.O. We
now hold that the Double Jeopardy Clauses of the federal and state constitutions
dictate that Jackson may not stand convicted of both first degree murder and
attempted first degree murder because the latter is a lesser included offense of the
former—the elements of attempted first degree murder are a subset of the
elements of first degree murder, and this particular attempted first degree murder
is not factually distinct from this particular first degree murder. Contrary to the
People’s assertion, the shooter did not attempt to kill E.O. when he aimed at and
shot Y.M. Rather, in aiming at and shooting Y.M., the shooter intended and
3
attempted to kill Y.M., the same person he actually killed. That the shooter wanted
to kill E.O. and mistakenly believed Y.M. was E.O. is of no moment. Therefore,
Jackson’s convictions for first degree murder and attempted first degree murder
are based on the same criminal conduct and relate to the same victim (Y.M.).
¶4 Accordingly, we ultimately agree with the division that the trial court
plainly erred in entering convictions and imposing sentences for both of the
offenses in question. But because our rationale differs from the division’s, we
affirm on other grounds. We remand with instructions to return the case to the
trial court to vacate the conviction and sentence for attempted first degree murder.
I. Facts and Procedural History
¶5 The charges brought against Jackson stem from longstanding animosity
between two rival gangs: “Sicc Made,” which is a subset of the “Crips”; and “Most
Hated,” which is also known as “Most Hated Gangsters.” Jackson is a member
and founder of Sicc Made. E.O. is a member of Most Hated.
¶6 In November 2010, members of Most Hated fired gunshots into an
apartment where Jackson apparently stayed. No one was injured. A little over a
year later, during the late evening of December 23 and early morning of December
24, 2011, E.O. shot Amin El-Howeris, a member of Sicc Made, while at a party.
El-Howeris was injured, but survived. Approximately forty-eight hours later, on
December 25, Jackson and a handful of fellow Sicc Made members met in an
4
apartment to discuss retaliating against E.O. (“the meeting”). During the meeting,
El-Howeris exclaimed, “[L]ook what they did to me,” and one of his associates
responded, “They mess with one of us, they mess with all of us.” As someone
passed around a gun with a laser sight, the group discussed shooting E.O. and
“finish[ing] him off.” The men knew the location of the apartment where E.O.
lived and were aware that he drove a gold SUV.
¶7 Jackson and his compatriots decided to go to E.O.’s apartment complex after
the meeting. They traveled there in two Ford Explorers, one of which was driven
by Jackson. They parked in the parking lot and waited for E.O.’s arrival.
¶8 Y.M., who was not involved with either gang, lived in the same apartment
complex as E.O. He returned home from work at 3 a.m. on December 26. Y.M.
drove a gold SUV similar to E.O.’s and happened to park near E.O.’s apartment.
Believing that Y.M. was E.O., one of Jackson’s cohorts got out of the Explorer
Jackson had driven to E.O.’s apartment, walked over to Y.M.’s SUV, and shot him
twice in the head, killing him instantly. When the shooter realized he had killed
the wrong person, he fired numerous shots into E.O.’s apartment. No one was in
the apartment at the time.
¶9 A grand jury subsequently indicted Jackson and other Sicc Made members.
Jackson was charged with: (1) first degree murder (naming Y.M. as the victim);
(2) attempted first degree murder (naming E.O. as the victim); (3) criminal attempt
5
to commit extreme indifference murder (naming E.O. as the victim, apparently
based on the shots fired into his apartment after Y.M. was killed);1 (4) conspiracy
to commit first degree murder; and (5) accessory to the crime of first degree
murder. Since Jackson was not the shooter, at trial the People relied on a
complicity theory of liability and the court instructed the jury accordingly.2
¶10 The jury found Jackson guilty of all five charges. The trial court then
sentenced him to life imprisonment without the possibility of parole on count 1,
twenty-four years’ imprisonment per count on counts 2, 3, and 4, and six years’
imprisonment on count 5. The sentences were ordered to be served consecutively,
for a total prison term of a life sentence without the possibility of parole plus
seventy-eight years.
1 The charge of attempted extreme indifference murder is not implicated in this
appeal. The references in this opinion to the charge of (and the conviction for)
attempted first degree murder all relate to count 2.
2 Under our complicity jurisprudence, a defendant is legally accountable as a
principal for behavior by another constituting a criminal offense “if he aids, abets,
advises, or encourages the other person in planning or committing that offense”
and does so “with: (1) the intent to aid, abet, advise, or encourage the other person
in his criminal act or conduct, and (2) an awareness of circumstances attending the
act or conduct he seeks to further, including a required mental state, if any, that
are necessary for commission of the offense in question.” People v. Childress,
2015 CO 65M, ¶ 34, 363 P.3d 155, 165. In this appeal, Jackson does not dispute that
he is legally accountable as a principal for any conduct by the shooter that
constitutes a criminal offense.
6
¶11 Jackson appealed on several grounds. People v. Jackson, 2018 COA 79,
__ P.3d __. He argued, among other things, that his separate convictions and
consecutive sentences for first degree murder (count 1) and attempted first degree
murder (count 2) violated his state and federal constitutional rights against double
jeopardy. Id. at ¶ 70. The People countered that the two separate convictions were
justified because count 1 listed Y.M. as the victim while count 2 listed E.O. as the
victim. However, the People agreed that a remand was necessary to direct the trial
court to run the corresponding sentences concurrently. Id.
¶12 In a published opinion, a unanimous division of the court of appeals sided
with Jackson. Id. at ¶ 83. Like the People, the division believed that there were
two victims (Y.M. on count 1 and E.O. on count 2). Id. at ¶¶ 82–83. But, invoking
the transferred intent doctrine, it nevertheless found a double jeopardy violation.
Id. It then vacated Jackson’s conviction and sentence for attempted first degree
murder and remanded the case to the trial court for correction of the mittimus. Id.
at ¶ 91. The division otherwise affirmed the judgment of conviction. Id.
¶13 Both parties timely petitioned our court for certiorari. We denied Jackson’s
petition but granted the People’s cross-petition.3
3 Here are the two issues on which we granted certiorari:
7
II. Analysis
¶14 We begin by examining the transferred intent doctrine and determining that
it has no place in first degree murder cases in Colorado given our legislature’s far-
reaching definition of first degree murder, which encompasses unintended
victims. Next, we conclude that even if our first degree murder statute didn’t
render the transferred intent doctrine unnecessary, the doctrine would still be
irrelevant here because this is a mistaken-identity case, not a bad-aim case. In a
mistaken-identity case like this one, there is only one victim—here, Y.M., the
person the shooter aimed at and shot with the intent to kill, albeit by mistake. As
such, in this case, there is no need to consider transferring the shooter’s intent from
one victim to another.
1. Whether the court of appeals erred in holding that the defendant’s
attempted murder after deliberation conviction must be vacated where
the evidence was sufficient to support it as a separate and distinct
offense.
2. Whether the court of appeals erred in holding that the doctrine of
transferred intent under the first degree murder statute extends to
“mistaken identity” cases where such an extension is contrary to the
plain language of the statute, and in concluding that the attempted
murder after deliberation conviction constituted a lesser included
offense of first degree murder based on its application of the transferred
intent doctrine.
8
¶15 We proceed to hold that, notwithstanding the way the People charged count
2 (listing E.O. as the victim) and the arguments they advanced to the jury without
objection in support of that count, as a legal matter and based on the evidence
presented at trial, the victim of the attempted first degree murder was Y.M., the
person the shooter aimed at and shot with the intent to kill. Because the first
degree murder conviction and the attempted first degree murder conviction
involved the same criminal conduct and the same victim (Y.M.), we further hold
that the trial court violated Jackson’s protection against double jeopardy by
entering both convictions. The elements of attempted first degree murder are a
subset of the elements of first degree murder, and this particular attempted first
degree murder is not factually distinct from this particular first degree murder.
We end by ruling that the trial court’s error was plain.
A. The Transferred Intent Doctrine Has No Place in First
Degree Murder Cases in Colorado
¶16 The doctrine of transferred intent generally provides that when A aims at
and shoots toward B but accidentally misses and hits C (an innocent bystander), A
is just as guilty as if his aim had been precise. Wayne R. LaFave, Substantive
Criminal Law § 6.4(d) (3d ed. 2019). Courts uniformly recognize that if A aims at
and shoots toward B with murderous intent but misses because he has bad aim
and ends up hitting and killing C, A is guilty of some degree of murder of C. Id.
And in the majority of jurisdictions, if A aims at and shoots toward B with the
9
specific state of mind required for first degree murder, but misses due to bad aim
and kills C instead, A commits first degree murder with respect to C. Id.
¶17 Such conclusions regarding criminal liability in bad-aim cases are clearly
proper. Id. However, they are sometimes said to rest on what has come to be
known as the “transferred intent” doctrine: “To be guilty of a crime involving a
harmful result to C, A must intend to do harm to C, but A’s intent to harm B will
be transferred to C; thus, A actually did intend to harm C; so he is guilty of the
crime against C.” Id. Of course, “A never really intended to harm C.” Id. The
disciples of the transferred intent doctrine are nevertheless willing to pretend
otherwise under the purely fictional notion that A’s intent to kill may somehow
magically be transferred from B to C.
¶18 Perhaps unsurprisingly, many legal commentators widely disparage the
transferred intent doctrine as a “legal fiction,” with some going so far as to deride
it using terms as varied as they are numerous, including “theoretically
incoherent,” “arbitrarily abstract,” an “unexplained mystery,” a “historical
aberration,” an “arbitrary exception to normal principles,” “overly harsh,” an
“arrant, bare-faced” theory, a rule that has “no place in criminal law,” and even as
“something of a freak.” Peter K. Westen, The Significance of Transferred Intent, 7
Crim. L. & Phil. 321, 322 (2013). And while courts seem less concerned about the
fictional aspect of the doctrine, they disagree on its scope. Id.
10
¶19 We need not pass judgment today on whether the transferred intent
doctrine may ever be properly invoked as a theory of criminal liability.4 Nor do
we have to decide here whether the doctrine may ever properly serve as an
analytical tool to address a legal question in a criminal case. Suffice it to say that
we do not approve of the division’s reliance on the doctrine to resolve the double
jeopardy claim raised in this first degree murder case. According to the division,
since “the victim killed was not the . . . intended target,” the transferred intent
doctrine was “implicated by the facts of this case and provide[d] a useful
framework for resolving the legal question presented.” 5 Jackson, ¶¶ 84, 88. We
disagree.
4 In Candelaria v. People, 148 P.3d 178 (Colo. 2006), we observed that the jury had
been instructed as to first degree murder “according to a theory of transferred
intent,” id. at 183, but we were quick to point out that neither the adequacy of that
instruction nor the sufficiency of the evidence was before us, id. at 183 & n.3.
5 For support, the division turned chiefly to People v. Hunt, 2016 COA 93, 412 P.3d
838, where a different division read our decision in People v. Marcy, 628 P.2d 69
(Colo. 1981), as establishing “that the doctrine of transferred intent applies to
second degree murder.” Hunt, ¶ 22, 412 P.3d at 843–44. But we did not reference,
let alone discuss, the transferred intent doctrine in Marcy. Instead, we simply
concluded, based on the statutory language that defined extreme indifference murder
and second degree murder at the time, that there was “no requirement that the
knowing conduct essential” to both offenses “be directed against the person
actually killed.” Marcy, 628 P.2d at 79. “[A]s long as the offender knowingly
act[ed] in the [statutorily] proscribed manner and cause[d] the death of another,”
we continued, he was “guilty of the crime even though the person killed [was] not
the person against whom the criminal conduct was directed.” Id.
11
¶20 The transferred intent doctrine is nothing more than a “round-about
method” to ensure that when A acts with the intent to kill B but kills C instead by
accident, he is considered (as he ought to be) “just as guilty as if he had actually
harmed” B. LaFave, supra. Stated differently, in the criminal homicide arena, the
law does not require—nor should it require—“that the defendant cause harm to
the intended victim; an unintended victim will do just as well.” Id.
¶21 In the context of first degree murder cases in Colorado, though, the concept
of transferred intent is as useful as a screen door on a submarine. After all, under
section 18-3-102(1)(a), C.R.S. (2019), a person commits first degree murder if,
“[a]fter deliberation and with the intent to cause the death of a person other than himself,
he causes the death of that person or of another person.”6 (Emphases added.) This
language deems the identity of the person harmed immaterial to the issue of intent
and holds a perpetrator just as liable when he kills an unintended victim as when
he kills his intended victim. Such statutory language renders the transferred intent
6 In Colorado, a person commits attempted first degree murder “if, acting with the
kind of culpability otherwise required for commission of [the] offense [of first
degree murder], he engages in conduct constituting a substantial step toward the
commission of th[at] offense.” See § 18-2-101(1), C.R.S. (2019). “A substantial step
is any conduct . . . , which is strongly corroborative of the firmness of the actor’s
purpose to complete the commission of the offense.” Id.
12
doctrine unnecessary because it accomplishes directly that which the doctrine
purports to accomplish indirectly via a legal fiction.
¶22 In fairness, the division consulted the language our General Assembly used
in defining first degree murder. But it inferred that such language “incorporates
the doctrine of transferred intent” to hold an actor “liable for the death of an
unintended victim.”7 Jackson, ¶ 85 (quoting Hunt, ¶ 21, 412 P.3d at 843). In other
words, the division apparently reasoned that our legislature adopted a legal fiction
sometimes used by courts when the statute defining the offense of first degree
murder would otherwise permit a defendant to escape liability for harming an
unintended victim by accident. We prefer to view the expansive language in
section 18-3-102(1)(a) as simply avoiding the need for the legal fiction altogether.8
Whether by design or not, our legislature’s definition of first degree murder
obviates any need to rely on the doctrine.
7Other divisions of the court of appeals have made similar declarations. See, e.g.,
People v. Candelaria, 107 P.3d 1080, 1091 (Colo. App. 2004), aff’d in part and rev’d in
part, 148 P.3d 178 (Colo. 2006); People v. Versteeg, 165 P.3d 760, 769 (Colo. App.
2006).
8 Even assuming for the sake of argument that, as the division surmised, section
18-3-102(1)(a) incorporates the transferred intent doctrine, that’s all the more
reason to simply apply the plain language of the statute without resorting to the
doctrine. What’s the point of treating the statute as incorporating the doctrine if
analyzing a defendant’s liability for first degree murder still requires reliance on
the legal fiction at the core of the doctrine?
13
B. The Transferred Intent Doctrine Is Inapplicable Here
for an Additional Reason: This Is a Mistaken-Identity Case
¶23 Even if our first degree murder statute didn’t render the transferred intent
doctrine unnecessary, the doctrine would still be irrelevant here because this is a
mistaken-identity case, not a bad-aim case. Traditionally, application of the
transferred intent doctrine has been limited to bad-aim cases. See, e.g., State v.
Fekete, 901 P.2d 708, 714 (N.M. 1995). As LaFave aptly notes, “the mistaken-
identity situation . . . is governed by a quite separate set of legal rules.” LaFave,
supra.
¶24 Bad-aim cases and mistaken-identity cases are alike in that the unintended
victim harmed is a surprise to the actor. Id. But they differ in that the surprise
originates in a different deficit on the actor’s part. Westen, supra, at 333. In the
bad-aim situation, the actor harms another “by accident, that is, by lack of physical
control over the direction [his] threatened harm[] will take” as it leaves his hands.
Id. In the mistaken-identity situation, the actor harms another “by mistake,
namely, by failing fully to realize who [his] . . . target [is].” Id.
¶25 These distinct deficits result in another critical difference between bad-aim
cases and mistaken-identity cases: In a bad-aim case, there are two victims (the
person the actor aims at and shoots toward and the unintended victim harmed by
the bullet), but in a mistaken-identity case like this one, there is only one victim
(the person the actor aims at and shoots with the intent to kill). For that reason,
14
any discussion about transferring the actor’s intent from one victim to another is
irrelevant in the mistaken-identity context.
¶26 Thus, if in the semi-darkness, A shoots with the intent to kill someone he
believes is B but who is actually C, and “his well-aimed bullet kills C,” A is guilty
of murdering C, not because he intended to kill B and that intent is somehow
transferred to C, but because he actually intended to kill C, the person he aimed at
and shot with the intent to kill; in that situation, “there is even less difficulty in
holding [A] guilty than in the bad-aim situation.” LaFave, supra. Any argument
by A that his mistake of fact regarding the victim’s identity “somehow negatives
his guilt of murder would be unavailing: his mistake does not negative his intent
to kill; and on the facts as he supposes them to be A is just as guilty of murder as
he is on the facts which actually exist.” Id.
¶27 In a mistaken-identity first degree murder case, then, the perpetrator kills
the person he aims at and shoots. As such, he kills the person he intends to kill.
Transferred intent has nothing to do with it.
¶28 We are not persuaded otherwise by our century-old decision in Ryan v.
People, 114 P. 306 (Colo. 1911), which the division used to bolster its determination
regarding the applicability of the transferred intent doctrine in mistaken-identity
cases. In Ryan, shortly after a physical encounter with two men that left him
“bruised and wounded,” the defendant approached the front door of his hotel
15
with a revolver in each hand and “fired five or six shots toward [a] crowd”
gathered outside. Id. at 307. Though the two men involved in the earlier brawl
were present in the crowd, they escaped unharmed. Id. But one of the defendant’s
shots hit and killed a third man, an unintended victim. Id.
¶29 As a preliminary matter, unlike the division, we view Ryan as a bad-aim or
extreme indifference murder case, not a mistaken-identity case.9 As such, it is
distinguishable.
¶30 More importantly, in affirming the judgment of conviction there, we relied
primarily on the statutory definition of murder in effect at the time, which cast a
net wide enough to draw in the killing of an unintended victim. Id. at 308. We
observed that “[s]ection 1624 of the Revised Statutes of 1908” stated that “murder”
included the “killing ‘perpetrated from a deliberate and premeditated design,
unlawfully and maliciously, to effect the death of any human being other than him
who is killed.’” Id. (emphasis added). Consistent with that statutory provision, we
explained that “[i]f a shot is fired, without justification, with malice and
deliberation, and a killing results, the homicide is first degree murder, although
9 The prosecution’s theory was that Ryan “was shooting at” his intended victims
and missed. Ryan, 114 P. at 307. But the evidence “show[ed] either this to be true,
or that Ryan shot indiscriminately at and toward the crowd without positive aim.”
Id.
16
the premeditation and malice were directed against one other than the person
actually killed.” Id. As well, we recited the uncontroversial rule that forms the
foundation for liability vis-à-vis extreme indifference murder: When A shoots into
a crowd with the intent “to hurt or kill any one whom he may hit,” and B is killed,
A “may be indicted” for B’s murder. Id. (quoting Francis Wharton, A Treatise on
Criminal Law 489 (Wm. Draper Lewis ed., 10th ed. 1896)).
¶31 Notably, we nowhere mentioned, much less examined, the transferred
intent doctrine. Given the statutory definition of murder, it was unnecessary to
rely on the legal fiction that’s the marrow of that doctrine. Hence, the division’s
transferred intent methodology in this mistaken-identity first degree murder case
finds no purchase in Ryan.10
¶32 The well-reasoned opinion by the Court of Special Appeals of Maryland in
Wieland v. State, 643 A.2d 446 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 1994), superseded by statute on
10 Admittedly, in Ryan, we quoted Wharton’s text on homicide for the “nearly
. . . universal” rule applicable when a perpetrator kills someone by mistake: “[O]ne
who kills another, mistaking him for a third person . . . , is guilty or innocent of the
offense charged the same as if the fatal act had killed the person” he wanted to kill.
114 P. at 308 (quoting Francis Wharton, The Law of Homicide 574 (Frank H. Bowlby
ed., 3d ed. 1907)). But in doing so, we didn’t intend to signal that the facts there
implicated a mistaken-identity situation, much less that we approved of the
transferred intent doctrine. Rather, we meant to simply reinforce the notion that
a perpetrator cannot escape liability for murder on the ground that the person he
killed was an unintended victim.
17
other grounds, Md. Code Crim. Law § 3-201(b) (2002), as stated in Watts v. State,
179 A.3d 929 (Md. 2018), is instructive on the reason the transferred intent doctrine
is irrelevant in mistaken-identity cases. There, the appellant, who was apparently
three sheets to the wind, returned home after a confrontation at a 7-Eleven. Id. at
448–49. He was awakened by noises outside his residence, got up, opened the
front door, and shot and injured someone he believed was attempting to enter; the
would-be intruder turned out to be his brother, an unintended victim. Id. The
evidence at trial established that in one simultaneous action, the appellant opened
his front door and deliberately fired away at the person standing there before
realizing that it was his brother. Id. at 466. Rejecting the transferred intent doctrine
as “totally inappropriate and immaterial” under those facts, id. at 467, the court
spoke as follows:
[W]ho was th[e] intended victim? The intended victim was the person the
appellant was shooting at, not the person he thought he was shooting at. The
intended victim, therefore, was [the appellant’s brother]. That the
appellant mistakenly thought his intended victim was someone other
than [his brother] was of no consequence . . . . The appellant intended
to shoot the person standing outside his front door; his aim was sure; and he
shot the person standing outside his front door. His perception of the
identity of the person he was shooting at was a non-issue. Transferred
intent has nothing to do with it.
Id. at 466 (second, third, and fourth emphases added) (citations omitted).
¶33 The court in Wieland added that “[i]ntending to shoot [the appellant’s
brother]” required “nothing more than intending to shoot some member of the
18
species homo sapiens who coincidentally turn[ed] out to be [the appellant’s
brother].” Id. Because he “hit the very body he intended to hit,” the court found
that the appellant’s intent needed “no transferring.” Id. at 468; see also Martinez v.
State, 844 S.W.2d 279, 282 (Tex. Ct. App. 1992) (explaining that the doctrine of
transferred intent generally applies in situations where the defendant intends to
shoot one person and misses, striking another by accident, but in the mistaken-
identity case before it, “appellant knowingly aimed the gun at [the deceased
victim], fired the gun at [him], and thereby caused [his] death”; the fact that
appellant “may have believed that the victim was [someone else] [was]
immaterial”).
¶34 Here, notwithstanding his mistaken belief that Y.M. was E.O., the shooter is
clearly liable for the first degree murder of Y.M., and the concept of transferred
intent plays no part in the determination of such liability. 11 The shooter aimed at
11The division did not comment on the interrelationship between the complicity
theory of liability and the transferred intent doctrine. It nevertheless referred to
the transfer of Jackson’s intent to kill. Jackson, ¶ 89. But Jackson’s intent to kill was
not necessarily established through proof of his complicity. See Childress, ¶ 33,
363 P.3d at 165 (indicating that “the intent requirement of the complicity statute
does not extend to prohibited results”). We infer that the division meant to refer
to the transfer of the shooter’s intent to kill. Our focus in this opinion on the
shooter’s intent reflects this understanding and is consistent with the parties’
implicit agreement in this appeal that Jackson is liable as a principal for any crimes
committed by the shooter.
19
Y.M. and shot Y.M. As such, he shot and killed the very person he aimed at and
intended to shoot and kill. That the shooter wanted to kill E.O. and mistakenly
believed Y.M. was E.O. is of no consequence.
¶35 Of course, the jury convicted Jackson under a complicity theory of liability
for the first degree murder of Y.M. And the validity of that conviction is not before
us. The question we confront is whether double jeopardy principles preclude
Jackson’s additional conviction for attempted first degree murder for wanting to
kill E.O. We tackle that question next.
C. Double Jeopardy Prohibits Convictions for Both First
Degree Murder and Attempted First Degree Murder
¶36 As we explained earlier, our General Assembly has defined first degree
murder broadly so as to include unintended victims. See § 18-3-102(1)(a). That
extensive definition applies with equal force in the context of attempted first
degree murder. The question that naturally flows from the sweeping legislative
pronouncement in section 18-3-102(1)(a) is why, then, do we care about who the
shooter intended to kill when he aimed at and shot Y.M.? After all, whether it was
Y.M. or E.O., the shooter intended to kill “another person,” as that term is used in
section 18-3-102(1)(a). The reason we must consider the question is that the People
argue that double jeopardy principles do not require the merger of the convictions
under inspection because one of them, first degree murder (count 1), involved
Y.M. as the victim, while the other, attempted first degree murder (count 2),
20
involved E.O. as the victim. Before addressing the People’s position, though, we
pause to set forth the tenets underpinning double jeopardy.
¶37 The U.S. Constitution shields a person from being “twice put in jeopardy of
life or limb” for the same offense. U.S. Const. amend. V. Similarly, the Colorado
Constitution provides that a person shall not “be twice put in jeopardy for the
same offense.” Colo. Const. art. II, § 18. The protective umbrella of these
constitutional provisions prohibits a second trial for the same offense, Whalen v.
United States, 445 U.S. 684, 688 (1980), and “affords shelter ‘against receiving
multiple punishments for the same offense,’” Waddell v. People, 2020 CO 39, ¶ 11,
462 P.3d 1100, 1105 (quoting Allman v. People, 2019 CO 78, ¶ 11, 451 P.3d 826, 829).
We deal here only with the protection against improper multiple punishments.
¶38 Double jeopardy tends to be implicated when multiplicity issues exist.
Woellhaf v. People, 105 P.3d 209, 214 (Colo. 2005). Multiplicity refers to “the
charging of multiple counts and the imposition of multiple punishments for the
same criminal conduct.” Id. We have said that the “vice of multiplicity” is that it
may yield multiple punishments for the same offense, thereby running afoul of
double jeopardy principles. Id. Multiple punishments do not merely encompass
multiple sentences. In the double jeopardy realm, “[e]ven a conviction
unaccompanied by a sentence bears sufficiently adverse collateral consequences
to amount to punishment.” People v. Wood, 2019 CO 7, ¶ 23, 433 P.3d 585, 592.
21
¶39 The mantle of protection afforded by the Double Jeopardy Clauses does not
prevent the legislature from specifying multiple punishments based on the same
criminal conduct. Woellhaf, 105 P.3d at 214. After all, the power to define criminal
offenses and to prescribe the punishments to be imposed upon defendants found
guilty of those offenses lies solely with the legislature. Reyna-Abarca v. People,
2017 CO 15, ¶ 49, 390 P.3d 816, 824. Consequently, to determine whether a
punishment imposed following a conviction infringes on a defendant’s double
jeopardy rights, we must first examine the punishment authorized by the
legislature for that conviction. Id. at ¶ 50, 390 P.3d at 824. If the legislature has not
authorized multiple punishments, then the protection against double jeopardy
prohibits the imposition of multiple punishments. Id. In this regard, the Double
Jeopardy Clauses embody “the constitutional principle of separation of powers by
ensuring that courts do not exceed their own authority by imposing multiple
punishments not authorized by the legislature.” Woellhaf, 105 P.3d at 214.
¶40 Our General Assembly has decreed that when a defendant’s conduct
establishes the commission of more than one offense, he “may be prosecuted for
each such offense.” § 18-1-408(1), C.R.S. (2019) (emphasis added). But if one
offense is a lesser included offense of another, he “may not be convicted” of both.
§ 18-1-408(1)(a) (emphasis added). Simultaneous convictions for an offense and a
lesser included offense would give rise to multiplicity issues. See id.
22
¶41 When we find multiplicitous convictions, the remedy is “to vacate one of
the underlying convictions as well as the . . . sentence based upon it.” Wood, ¶ 28,
433 P.3d at 593 (quoting United States v. Barrett, 496 F.3d 1079, 1095 (10th Cir.
2007)). And we have made clear that in deciding which conviction or convictions
should be vacated to honor the Double Jeopardy Clauses, “a trial court
‘should . . . enter as many convictions and impose as many sentences as are legally
possible to fully effectuate the jury’s verdict.’” Id. (quoting People v. Glover,
893 P.2d 1311, 1315 (Colo. 1995)); see also Halaseh v. People, 2020 CO 35M, ¶ 10,
463 P.3d 249, 252 (observing that when multiple convictions cannot stand “by
reason of either constitutional or statutory prohibitions,” we have “instructed trial
courts to select the combination of offenses that can simultaneously stand that
produce the most convictions and the longest sentences, in order to maximize the
effect of the jury’s verdict”).
¶42 As pertinent here, an offense is a lesser included offense of a greater offense
when “[i]t is established by proof of the same or less than all the facts required to
establish the commission” of the greater offense. § 18-1-408(5)(a). But what test
do we apply to evaluate whether an offense is a lesser included offense of another
offense under section 18-1-408(5)(a)? We answered this question recently in
Reyna-Abarca, where we held that an offense is a lesser included offense of a greater
offense for purposes of section 18-1-408(5)(a) “if the elements of the lesser offense
23
are a subset of the elements of the greater offense, such that the lesser offense
contains only elements that are also included in the elements of the greater
offense.” Reyna-Abarca, ¶ 64, 390 P.3d at 826.
¶43 In this case, the division found, and we agree, that attempted first degree
murder is a lesser included offense of first degree murder pursuant to section
18-1-408(5)(a) because the elements of the former are a subset of the elements of
the latter, such that the former contains only elements that are also included in the
elements of the latter. Put differently, by proving the elements of first degree
murder, a prosecutor necessarily establishes the elements of attempted first degree
murder.
¶44 This does not end our inquiry, though. There is still the question of whether
this particular attempted first degree murder is a lesser included offense of this
particular first degree murder.
¶45 In Reyna-Abarca, we did not mean to suggest that whether an offense is a
lesser included offense of another offense is strictly “a consequence of the statutory
elements of the respective offenses alone.” People v. Rock, 2017 CO 84, ¶ 17,
402 P.3d 472, 478. As we recognized in Rock, convictions for two separate offenses,
the elements of one of which constitute a subset of the elements of the other, “can
clearly stand if the offenses were committed by distinctly different conduct.” Id.
24
¶46 In determining whether two offenses are factually distinct, we generally
consider: (1) whether the acts occurred at different times and were separated by
intervening events; (2) whether there were different volitional acts or new
volitional departures in the defendant’s course of conduct; and (3) other factors
such as temporal proximity, the location of the victim (e.g., whether the victim was
moved), the defendant’s intent (as manifested through his conduct and
utterances), and the number of victims. See Quintano v. People, 105 P.3d 585, 591
(Colo. 2005). As it relates to the last of these considerations, both the court of
appeals and our court have recognized that in some circumstances the presence of
multiple victims alone renders the offenses factually distinct. See, e.g., People v.
Espinoza, 2020 CO 43, ¶ 21, 463 P.3d 855, 860 (holding that “offenses defined in
terms of their victimization of another and committed against different victims are
not capable of being proved by identical evidence within the contemplation of
section 18-1-408(3)”); People v. Borghesi, 66 P.3d 93, 94–95 (Colo. 2003) (upholding
two aggravated robbery convictions based on the same criminal conduct because
there were two victims and aggravated robbery is a crime intended to protect
persons); People v. Harris, 2016 COA 159, ¶ 56, 405 P.3d 361, 372 (concluding that
“the existence of multiple victims created factually distinct offenses” for purposes
of section 18-1-408(1)(e)).
25
¶47 Here, the People posit that this particular first degree murder and this
particular attempted first degree murder were committed by distinctly different
conduct because Y.M. was the victim of the former and E.O. was the victim of the
latter. Embracing the premise of the People’s hypothesis, the division treated the
offenses as involving two different victims. Jackson, ¶¶ 82–83. But the division
nevertheless discerned that this particular first degree murder and this particular
attempted first degree murder were not committed by distinctly different conduct.
Id. at ¶ 83. In so doing, the division viewed the evidence through the prism of the
transferred intent doctrine, concluding that the shooter’s intent was to kill E.O.
and that such intent “transferred to Y.M. and made [the shooter] criminally liable
for Y.M’s death.” Id. at ¶ 89. The division then reasoned that “[b]y proving the
first degree murder of Y.M under this [doctrine], the prosecution necessarily
proved that [the shooter] intended and attempted to kill E.O.” Id. Therefore,
although the division believed that the two offenses involved different victims, it
nonetheless held that this particular attempted first degree murder was a lesser
included offense of this particular first degree murder. Id.
¶48 The division’s approach is out of sync with Colorado case law establishing
that in circumstances like those implicated here, the presence of multiple victims
renders the offenses factually distinct. See, e.g., Espinoza, ¶ 21, 463 P.3d at 860;
Borghesi, 66 P.3d at 94–95; Harris, ¶ 56, 405 P.3d at 372. If, as the division
26
incorrectly believed, this incident involved two separate victims, our case law
would require that the offenses at issue be deemed factually distinct.
¶49 Moreover, as the following hypothetical illustrates, there are critical
shortcomings in the division’s double jeopardy analysis. Suppose that A shot B
after deliberation and with the intent to kill B, the bullet hit and wounded B,
passed through B, and hit and killed C, an innocent bystander behind B.12 Under
the division’s rationale, A may be convicted of first degree murder with respect to
C, but may not also be convicted of attempted first degree murder with respect to
B, even though A shot and wounded B with the intent to kill B. Instead, the
division would presumably rule that, notwithstanding the presence of multiple
victims, the attempted first degree murder of B is a lesser included offense of the
first degree murder of C because A’s intent to kill B transferred to C and, thus, by
proving A guilty of the first degree murder of C, the prosecution necessarily
proved that A intended and attempted to kill B. It hardly bears stating that this
would be an undesirable result.
12 This factual scenario, which includes two victims and is akin to a bad-aim
situation, is not far-fetched. In Poe v. State, 671 A.2d 501, 502 (Md. 1996), the
defendant, intending to kill his estranged wife, shot and wounded her, but the
bullet passed through her and killed a child standing behind her.
27
¶50 The wide-ranging statutory definition of first degree murder in Colorado
averts the need for mental gymnastics, never mind legal fictions, in order to hold
A fully liable. A may be convicted of first degree murder for C’s death because,
“[a]fter deliberation and with the intent to cause the death of a person other than
himself,” (i.e., B), A “cause[d] the death of that person or of another person,” (i.e.,
C). § 18-3-102(1)(a). And A may be convicted of the attempted first degree murder
of B because, acting after deliberation and with the intent to kill B, A aimed at and
shot B, thereby “engag[ing] in conduct constituting a substantial step toward the
commission of the offense” of first degree murder. § 18-2-101(1), C.R.S. (2019).
¶51 Significantly, because there is no need to resort to the much-maligned
transferred intent doctrine, the muddled legal fiction that is its nucleus does not
complicate the double jeopardy analysis. This particular attempted first degree
murder of B is not a lesser included offense of this particular first degree murder
of C because these offenses, which are intended to protect persons and are, in fact,
defined in terms of their victimization of persons, were committed against
different victims. Thus, the two offenses are factually distinct, which means that
A may stand convicted of both without giving rise to double jeopardy concerns.
¶52 This analytical framework is pliable and fits any factual situation, including
the one before us, though it yields the opposite result here on the double jeopardy
front. The shooter may be convicted of first degree murder because, “[a]fter
28
deliberation and with the intent to cause the death of a person other than himself,”
i.e., Y.M., he caused “the death of that person,” although the death “of another
person” would have done just as well. § 18-3-102(1)(a). But the shooter may not
also stand convicted of attempted first degree murder because the attempted first
degree murder relates to the same criminal conduct and the same victim involved
in the first degree murder of Y.M. Contrary to the People’s contention, when the
shooter aimed at and shot Y.M., he intended and attempted to kill Y.M., even if he
mistakenly believed that Y.M. was E.O. That is to say, unlike the hypothetical
where the bullet injures and passes through the intended victim and then strikes
an unintended victim by accident, this mistaken-identity case involves only one
victim: Y.M. The shooter attempted to kill the same person he actually killed. That
the shooter wanted to kill E.O. is inconsequential. Therefore, this particular
attempted first degree murder is a lesser included offense of this particular first
degree murder (albeit for a different reason than that espoused by the division),
and the conviction for the former must merge into the conviction for the latter.
¶53 The People push back, though, asserting that the first degree murder charge
listed Y.M. as the victim while the attempted first degree murder charge listed E.O.
as the victim. And, continue the People, that’s how they argued the case to the
29
jury without objection.13 Be that as it may, we have now concluded that, as a
matter of law, the evidence introduced at trial established that the only person the
shooter could have attempted to kill when he aimed at and shot Y.M. with the
intent to kill was Y.M., not E.O. We reiterate that the fact that the shooter wanted
to kill E.O. and mistakenly believed that Y.M. was E.O. is neither here nor there.
“Wanting, desiring, or hoping to hit [E.O.] . . . is not the same as intending to hit
[E.O.].” Wieland, 643 A.2d at 467. “One’s intent is to hit one’s target,” not “to hit
some other person” one “believes the target to be.” Id.; see also id. at 466 (“If one
shoots at the President, erroneously believing him to be a cleverly disguised
foreign spy, one intends to shoot the President.”). Thus, notwithstanding the way
the People charged count 2 and the arguments they advanced in front of the jury
without objection, as a legal matter and based on the evidence introduced at trial,
the attempted first degree murder conviction cannot relate to E.O.; it can only
relate to Y.M.
13 We note that none of the jury’s elemental instructions and verdict forms on
counts 1 and 2 identified a victim. Rather, they used the same generic language
the legislature used to define the crime of first degree murder and, by extension,
the crime of attempted first degree murder. As a result, the jury’s finding on count
2 simply reflects that “another person” was the victim of the attempted first degree
murder.
30
¶54 We are just as unmoved by the People’s assertion that when the shooter
arrived at E.O.’s apartment complex, he completed the crime of attempted first
degree murder with respect to E.O., and that, thereafter, when he approached,
aimed at, and shot Y.M., he committed the factually distinct crime of first degree
murder with respect to Y.M. Even assuming, without deciding, that driving to
E.O.’s apartment complex after the meeting was sufficient to constitute a
substantial step toward the commission of first degree murder, this argument fails,
though we concede it has intuitive appeal.
¶55 First, there is no factual basis for the bifurcated methodology proposed by
the People. This was a single, uninterrupted criminal episode in which the
shooter, after deliberation and with the intent to kill, killed Y.M. The plan
formulated and set in motion during the meeting continued as the shooter went to
E.O.’s apartment complex, waited for the arrival of the gold SUV, and then
approached, aimed at, and shot the driver with the intent to kill him. Nothing
changed during that chain of events to warrant viewing the shooter’s arrival at
E.O.’s apartment complex as the end of one crime and some subsequent moment
as the beginning of a factually distinct crime. From its inception, the plan was
never to commit attempted first degree murder; the plan all along was to commit
first degree murder. To slice the incident into two separate transactions and deem,
on the one hand, the arrival at E.O.’s apartment complex as the completion of the
31
crime of attempted first degree murder, and on the other, walking up to the gold
SUV, aiming at the driver, and shooting him with the intent to kill him as the
factually distinct crime of first degree murder, would be to engage in incomplete,
inaccurate, and misleading analysis.
¶56 True, during the meeting, it was clear that the shooter wanted to kill E.O.,
not Y.M. But the person the shooter actually intended to kill was Y.M.—the person
the shooter approached, aimed at, and shot.
¶57 Second, the People do not provide any legal basis to buttress their invitation
to analyze the events in question piecemeal. And we are aware of none.
¶58 Finally, if, as planned, the shooter had actually shot and killed E.O. instead
of Y.M., the People would not be entitled to the segmented analysis they request.
And in that case, even they admit that the shooter—and, correspondingly,
Jackson—could not have been convicted of both first degree murder (for the
murder of E.O.) and attempted first degree murder (for the attempted murder of
E.O.). Why should it be any different simply because, by mistake, the person the
shooter approached, aimed at, and shot ended up being Y.M., not E.O.?
¶59 In sum, because a mistaken-identity case like this one has only one victim—
here, Y.M.—we reject the People’s position and conclude that this particular
attempted first degree murder is not factually distinct from this particular first
degree murder. Hence, the former is a lesser included offense of the latter and the
32
Double Jeopardy Clauses dictate that Jackson may not stand convicted of both
offenses.
D. The Trial Court Plainly Erred
¶60 We have determined that the trial court erred in entering convictions and
imposing sentences for both first degree murder (count 1) and attempted first
degree murder (count 2). Because Jackson did not preserve his double jeopardy
claim, though, we may only reverse if this was plain error. Reyna-Abarca, ¶ 47,
390 P.3d at 823. Jackson maintains that the trial court’s error was obvious and
substantial and, therefore, plain. People v. Miller, 113 P.3d 743, 750 (Colo. 2005)
(“Plain error addresses error that is both ‘obvious and substantial.’”). The People
do not argue otherwise. We take such silence to be the People’s implicit concession
of the issue. Cf. Hoang v. People, 2014 CO 27, ¶ 52, 323 P.3d 780, 790 (noting the
People’s failure to contest the defendant’s timely filing of his notice of appeal,
which he discussed in his opening brief with the court of appeals, and “accept[ing]
this implicit concession”).
¶61 Regardless, we independently rule that the trial court plainly erred. Double
jeopardy principles and section 18-1-408(1)(b) clearly prohibit convictions for both
of the offenses at issue. As such, the trial court’s error was obvious. And we have
little difficulty finding that the error was also substantial because “[i]n both our
own jurisprudence and in case law nationally, courts have invariably concluded
33
that when a defendant’s double jeopardy rights are violated . . . , such a violation
requires a remedy.” Reyna-Abarca, ¶ 81, 390 P.3d at 828.
¶62 The appropriate remedy in this case is to vacate the conviction and sentence
on count 2 and to leave undisturbed the conviction and sentence on count 1. See
Halaseh, ¶ 10, 463 P.3d at 252; Wood, ¶ 28, 433 P.3d at 593. Thus, we remand with
instructions to return the case to the trial court to amend the mittimus accordingly.
III. Conclusion
¶63 We conclude that the Double Jeopardy Clauses dictate that Jackson may not
stand convicted of both first degree murder and attempted first degree murder
under the facts of this case. Though the division reached the same result, it did so
by erroneously relying on the transferred intent doctrine. Accordingly, we affirm
on other grounds. We remand with instructions to return the case to the trial court
to amend the mittimus by vacating the conviction and sentence for attempted first
degree murder.
34