19-1169
Collins v. Putt
1 UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS
2 FOR THE SECOND CIRCUIT
3
4 August Term, 2019
5
6 (Argued: March 9, 2020 Decided: October 29, 2020)
7
8 Docket No. 19-1169-cv
9
10 _____________________________________
11
12 JEREMY COLLINS,
13
14 Plaintiff-Appellant,
15
16 v.
17
18 REBECCA PUTT, IN HER INDIVIDUAL AND OFFICIAL CAPACITY,
19 ED KLONOSKI, IN HIS OFFICIAL CAPACITY AS PRESIDENT OF
20 CHARTER OAK STATE COLLEGE,
21
22 Defendants-Appellees,
23
24 CHARTER OAK STATE COLLEGE,
25
26 Defendant. *
27 _____________________________________
28
29 Before:
30
31 RAGGI, LOHIER, and MENASHI, Circuit Judges.
32
33 Jeremy Collins, a student at Charter Oak State College, brought suit
34 against his college instructor Rebecca Putt, alleging that Putt violated his First
35 Amendment rights by removing an online blog post that he made in response
36 to a class assignment. Collins further alleged that Putt and Charter Oak’s
37 President, Ed Klonoski, violated his due process rights under the Fourteenth
* The Clerk of Court is directed to amend the caption as set forth above.
1 Amendment in connection with disciplining him for the blog post. The
2 United States District Court for the District of Connecticut (Covello, J.)
3 dismissed Collins’s suit under Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 12(b)(6). For
4 the reasons that follow, we AFFIRM the District Court’s judgment dismissing
5 Collins’s claims.
6
7 Judge Menashi concurs in the judgment in a separate opinion.
8
9 JEREMY COLLINS, pro se, Stamford, CT.
10
11 MARY K. LENEHAN, Assistant Attorney General, for
12 William Tong, Attorney General of the State of
13 Connecticut, Hartford, CT, for Defendants-Appellees
14 Rebecca Putt and Ed Klonoski.
15
16 LOHIER, Circuit Judge:
17 Jeremy Collins, a student at Charter Oak State College, filed this lawsuit
18 under 42 U.S.C. § 1983, alleging that his instructor at the college,
19 Defendant-Appellee Rebecca Putt, violated his First Amendment rights when
20 she removed from a college message board the online blog post that Collins
21 submitted in response to a class assignment. Collins further alleged that Putt
22 and Charter Oak’s President, Ed Klonoski, violated his right to due process
23 under the Fourteenth Amendment by failing to follow the college’s internal
24 disciplinary policies before disciplining him for the post. The United States
25 District Court for the District of Connecticut (Covello, J.) dismissed Collins’s
26 suit for failure to state a claim upon which relief could be granted. See Fed. R.
2
1 Civ. P. 12(b)(6). On appeal, Collins contends that the District Court’s
2 dismissal was error. He principally argues that the District Court applied the
3 wrong legal standard when evaluating his First Amendment claim and
4 misread the college’s disciplinary policies when considering his Fourteenth
5 Amendment claim. For the reasons that follow, we AFFIRM the District
6 Court’s judgment dismissing Collins’s claims.
7 BACKGROUND
8 I
9 The following facts are taken from Collins’s operative, second amended
10 complaint and from documents integral to it. See WC Cap. Mgmt., LLC v.
11 UBS Sec., LLC, 711 F.3d 322, 325 (2d Cir. 2013).
12 In 2017 Collins enrolled in an online class entitled “Communications
13 101” at Charter Oak State College. The class was taught using software that
14 “provides a virtual classroom environment,” which allows for the submission
15 of assignments and for communication via a message board available only to
16 students enrolled in the class, the class instructor, and college administrators.
17 App’x 9–10. Two weeks into the term, Putt, the instructor, asked the class to
18 watch a video that depicted a young man conversing with and assisting an
3
1 elderly disabled person. Putt then provided the class with a list of questions
2 about the video and instructed the students to post their answers to those
3 questions on the virtual classroom’s online message board. The questions
4 required the students to evaluate the conversation between and the
5 perceptions of the individuals depicted in the video.
6 Collins responded with a blog post that his complaint describes as
7 “intentionally humorous, ironic and provocative” and as “includ[ing] what
8 might be reasonably called a critique of the assignment and materials
9 themselves.” App’x 26. Collins’s blog post, which is attached to his
10 complaint, states that the assigned video was “excruciatingly awkward,”
11 “ridiculous,” and depicted “two complete idiots hav[ing] a conversation that
12 could only take place in an alternate reality on a planet far, far away.” App’x
13 41. The post describes the older character as “cranky,” “self pitying,”
14 “offended,” “angry,” and engaged in “miserable griping.” App’x 41.
15 In response to the post, Putt told Collins that while she did not “mind a
16 bit of humor here and there, ranting about the classroom materials in a
17 manner that some might find offensive will not be tolerated.” App’x 29. Putt
18 soon removed Collins’s post, as well as all the comments on the post that had
4
1 been made by Collins and other classmates. Collins accused Putt of censoring
2 his work, and he promised to demand that Putt “be educated on the civil
3 rights of . . . students.” App’x 30.
4 II
5 Collins eventually sued Putt, claiming in his operative complaint that
6 Putt’s deletion of his blog post violated his First Amendment right to freedom
7 of expression. The District Court, relying on Hazelwood School District v.
8 Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. 260, 271–73 (1988), concluded that Putt’s deletion did not
9 violate Collins’s First Amendment rights because it was “reasonably related
10 to legitimate pedagogical concerns.” The District Court therefore dismissed
11 the claim and ultimately dismissed Collins’s complaint in its entirety.
12 This appeal followed.
13 DISCUSSION
14 In this opinion we address four issues. First, we consider whether it
15 was error for the District Court to rely on the Hazelwood standard rather than
16 the standard announced by the Supreme Court in Tinker v. Des Moines
17 Independent Community School District, 393 U.S. 503 (1969). This requires
18 that we address Collins’s argument that his blog post was not sponsored by
5
1 the college. Second, we consider whether the District Court properly applied
2 the Hazelwood standard to the alleged facts in this case. Third, we determine
3 whether Putt’s alleged actions were plausibly viewpoint discriminatory so as
4 to state a First Amendment claim. 1 Finally, we resolve Collins’s due process
5 argument under the Fourteenth Amendment. We address each of these issues
6 in turn, mindful that “[w]e review de novo a district court’s dismissal of a
7 complaint pursuant to Rule 12(b)(6), construing the complaint liberally,
8 accepting all factual allegations in the complaint as true, and drawing all
9 reasonable inferences in the plaintiff’s favor.” Dolan v. Connolly, 794 F.3d
10 290, 293 (2d Cir. 2015) (quotation marks omitted).
1Although Collins argues that Putt deleted his post because she found it offensive,
see Pet’r Br. at 4, 7, 8, 10, 11, 12, he does not specify what viewpoint was allegedly
subjected to discrimination. In the Putt statement attached to Collins’s complaint,
she describes the “manner” of Collins’s expression—not the viewpoint expressed—
as “offensive.” App’x 29. “It is a settled appellate rule that issues adverted to in a
perfunctory manner, unaccompanied by some effort at developed argumentation,
are deemed waived.” Tolbert v. Queens Coll., 242 F.3d 58, 75 (2d Cir. 2001)
(quotation marks omitted). While we might conclude that Collins failed to
sufficiently develop a viewpoint discrimination argument here, we do not deem that
point waived because “pleadings and briefs submitted by pro se litigants” like
Collins are properly read “to raise the strongest arguments they suggest.” McLeod
v. Jewish Guild for the Blind, 864 F.3d 154, 156 (2d Cir. 2017) (quotation marks
omitted). Following that principle here, we address viewpoint discrimination on the
merits in Part III of this opinion.
6
1 I
2 We first consider whether the District Court erred by analyzing
3 Collins’s First Amendment claim under Hazelwood. We conclude that it did
4 not.
5 The Supreme Court has announced various tests or “standards for
6 assessing whether a school’s censorship of student speech is constitutionally
7 permissible.” Guiles ex rel. Guiles v. Marineau, 461 F.3d 320, 324 (2d Cir.
8 2006). Only two of these standards, under Hazelwood and Tinker, are
9 relevant to this appeal. We have referred to Hazelwood and Tinker as
10 identifying “two categories of student expression in the school environment,
11 each of which merits a different degree of judicial scrutiny in connection with
12 school-imposed speech restrictions,” Peck ex rel. Peck v. Baldwinsville Cent.
13 Sch. Dist., 426 F.3d 617, 627 (2d Cir. 2005), with Tinker being more protective
14 of student speech than Hazelwood, see DeFabio v. E. Hampton Union Free
15 Sch. Dist., 623 F.3d 71, 79 (2d Cir. 2010).
16 If Collins’s blog post constituted a “school-sponsored expressive
17 activit[y],” then the deferential standard announced in Hazelwood applies.
18 Hazelwood, 484 U.S. at 273; see Marineau, 461 F.3d at 327. We evaluate
7
1 whether a student’s speech is “school[] sponsored” based on whether
2 “students, parents, and members of the public might reasonably perceive” the
3 speech “to bear the imprimatur of the school.” Hazelwood, 484 U.S. at 271.
4 Under the Hazelwood standard, educators may regulate student speech “so
5 long as their actions are reasonably related to legitimate pedagogical
6 concerns.” Id. at 273. This is because “[t]he determination of what manner of
7 speech in the classroom or in school assembly is inappropriate properly rests
8 with the school . . . rather than with the federal courts.” Id. at 267 (quotation
9 marks omitted).
10 If, on the other hand, Collins’s post constituted “a student’s personal
11 expression that happens to occur on the school premises,” id. at 271, then the
12 standard is supplied by Tinker. Under the Tinker standard, school officials
13 may regulate student speech that the school does not sponsor if that speech
14 would “materially and substantially disrupt classwork and discipline in the
15 school.” Marineau, 461 F.3d at 325 (citing Tinker, 393 U.S. at 513). 2
2Beyond Hazelwood and Tinker are two additional standards related to the
regulation of school speech, neither of which is relevant here. First, “schools have
wide discretion to prohibit speech that is less than obscene—to wit, vulgar, lewd,
indecent or plainly offensive speech.” Marineau, 461 F.3d at 325 (citing Bethel Sch.
8
1 Regardless of the standard, we keep in mind that the First Amendment
2 rights of students “must be applied in light of the special characteristics of the
3 school environment.” Morse v. Frederick, 551 U.S. 393, 397 (2007) (quotation
4 marks omitted).
5 Collins insists that Tinker, not Hazelwood, governs this case. We
6 disagree. As we have explained, Hazelwood “comes into play . . . when the
7 student speech is school-sponsored or when a reasonable observer would
8 believe it to be so sponsored.” Marineau, 461 F.3d at 327 (quotation marks
9 omitted). Hazelwood applies to student speech that “may fairly be
10 characterized as part of the school curriculum, whether or not [it] occur[s] in a
11 traditional classroom setting, so long as [it is] supervised by faculty members
Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U.S. 675, 683–85 (1986)). Second, “schools may restrict
student speech that they “reasonably [] regard[] as encouraging illegal drug use.”
R.O. ex rel. Ochshorn v. Ithaca City Sch. Dist., 645 F.3d 533, 541 (2d Cir. 2011) (citing
Morse v. Frederick, 551 U.S. 393, 397 (2007)). The Supreme Court has suggested in
passing that there may be additional standards beyond Hazelwood, Tinker, Fraser,
and Morse. See Doninger v. Niehoff, 642 F.3d 334, 354 (2d Cir. 2011) (citing Morse,
551 U.S. at 405). But it has yet to identify them. “[W]e neither recognize any such
[additional standards], nor express a view as to their desirability,” but “this
qualification does not rule out the possibility that some such hitherto unrecognized
[standard] may exist.” Id.
9
1 and designed to impart particular knowledge or skills to student participants
2 and audiences.” Peck, 426 F.3d at 628 (quotation marks omitted).
3 Here, Collins’s blog post bears the hallmarks of school sponsorship. It
4 was made specifically in response to a class assignment, under the
5 supervision of a college faculty member, and on a message board that was
6 provided by the college offering the class. The message board in turn was
7 designed as a pedagogical tool to convey information to class participants and
8 to receive communications from them, particularly, their completed class
9 assignments. The message board bore the college’s initials and was accessible
10 only to the class’s students, instructor, and the college’s administrators. We
11 have pointed to the same or similar characteristics to conclude that student
12 speech was “school-sponsored, or at least . . . constituted an expressive
13 activit[y] that students . . . and members of the public might reasonably
14 perceive to bear the imprimatur of the school, which is sufficient to trigger the
15 application of Hazelwood.” R.O. ex rel. Ochshorn v. Ithaca City Sch. Dist.,
16 645 F.3d 533, 541 (2d Cir. 2011) (quotation marks omitted). 3 Under these
3We recognize that “Hazelwood explicitly reserved the question of whether the
substantial deference shown to high school administrators was appropriate with
10
1 circumstances, the District Court did not err in determining that the
2 Hazelwood standard rather than the Tinker standard applies.
3 II
4 Nor did the District Court err in determining that Putt’s deletion of
5 Collins’s post was “reasonably related to legitimate pedagogical concerns,” in
6 satisfaction of the Hazelwood standard. Peck, 426 F.3d at 633. Indeed, we
7 have no doubt that Putt’s response to Collins’s post was reasonably related to
8 legitimate pedagogical concerns. As Collins himself alleged, his post
9 “critique[d] . . . the assignment and materials themselves,” App’x 26, which
10 was not the assignment. Putt’s assignment required students to identify the
11 perceptions of the video’s two characters and to discuss how those
12 perceptions affected their dialogue. Collins’s initial post did neither. It
13 focused instead on his perception of the video’s speciousness, not the
14 characters’ perceptions of their situation or the effect of those perceptions on
respect to school-sponsored expressive activities at,” as here, “the college or
university level . . . where the relation between students and their schools is
different and at least arguably distinguishable.” Amidon v. Student Ass’n of State
Univ. of N.Y. at Albany, 508 F.3d 94, 105 (2d Cir. 2007) (quotation marks omitted).
Because neither party argues that Hazelwood applies with less force in the
university context, particularly with respect to the posting of completed class
assignments, we apply Hazelwood without qualification in this case.
11
1 their dialogue. Absent some other basis in fact not alleged in the complaint,
2 Putt’s removal of Collins’s blog post is thus most reasonably understood to
3 ensure that the message board was used for its school-sponsored, pedagogical
4 purpose, i.e., for students to post completed class assignments and for online
5 discussion of those postings to further the communications lessons the
6 assignment was intended to impart, without diverting attention to the non-
7 responsive subject of the quality of classroom materials. See, e.g., Ashcroft v.
8 Iqbal, 556 U.S. 662, 682 (2009) (“As between that obvious alternative
9 explanation for the arrests, and the purposeful, invidious discrimination
10 respondent asks us to infer, discrimination is not a plausible conclusion.”
11 (quotation marks omitted)). Such action was constitutionally permissible
12 under Hazelwood. See Peck, 426 F.3d at 629 n.8 (“Unquestionably, whether a
13 student’s work is responsive to an assignment . . . [is] part and parcel of a
14 school’s responsibility to ensure that participants learn whatever lessons the
15 activity is designed to teach . . . .” (quotation marks omitted)). Collins’s
16 conclusory assertion that it was “not off-topic” for him “to voice his own
17 perceptions and viewpoints,” App’x 26, cannot by itself state a plausible claim
18 for discrimination. See Iqbal, 556 U.S. at 678 (stating that “mere conclusory
12
1 statements” cannot plead plausible claim); Krys v. Pigott, 749 F.3d 117, 128
2 (2d Cir. 2014) (holding that court is not “required to accept as true allegations
3 that are wholly conclusory”). 4
4 III
5 Our Circuit has held that school-sponsored speech may not be
6 regulated in a viewpoint discriminatory manner “even if [doing so] is
7 reasonably related to pedagogical concerns.” Peck, 426 F.3d at 633. We
8 conclude that Collins has failed plausibly to allege that Putt’s actions here
9 constituted viewpoint discrimination. To the contrary, Putt’s deletion of
10 Collins’s post reflected a content-based restriction that the Supreme Court has
11 instructed us to tolerate in the school setting. As Hazelwood itself affirms:
12 “educators do not offend the First Amendment by exercising editorial control
13 over the style and content of student speech in school-sponsored expressive
14 activities.” 484 U.S. at 273. Likewise, where, as here, the school-sponsored
15 expressive activity is a class assignment, an educator does not offend the First
4
A student’s posting of material not responsive to a class assignment—whether on a
classroom bulletin board or an electronic message board—may be sufficiently
disruptive to classwork to allow its removal even under the Tinker standard, but we
need not here conclusively decide whether the challenged removal satisfies Tinker
as well as Hazelwood.
13
1 Amendment by limiting the content of posted student speech to that which
2 reasonably responds to the assignment (whatever its viewpoint) and by
3 excluding speech that opts instead to criticize the assignment (whatever its
4 viewpoint).
5 As Collins accepts, Putt explained to him that his blog post was deleted
6 because its content was unresponsive to the class assignment. In an email to
7 Collins, Putt described the blog post as a “rant” targeted at the adequacy of
8 the “classroom materials” rather than the assigned evaluation of the
9 perceptions of the video’s characters. App’x 29. Collins appears to have
10 acknowledged as much. For example, in his second amended complaint, he
11 alleges that “the true reason” for Putt’s challenged actions was to “censor[]”
12 Collins’s “‘ranting’ about the classroom materials.” App’x 32. Further, he
13 admits that his blog post “might reasonably [have been] called a critique of
14 the assignment and the materials themselves.” App’x 26. And Collins’s blog
15 post itself stated that he was “digress[ing].” App’x 41. Thus, we can
16 conclude as a matter of law that, as Collins himself has acknowledged, Putt’s
17 challenged actions were based on the content and style of his blog post, which
14
1 failed to respond to the class assignment, and not on the particular viewpoint
2 expressed therein.
3 It is true that even content- and style-based restrictions on speech must
4 be imposed evenhandedly, without regard to viewpoint. See Peck, 426 F.3d at
5 631–33. Collins submits that a plausible claim of viewpoint discrimination is
6 indicated here by the fact that Putt did not remove other posts that expressed
7 negative views of the portrayal of the disabled person in the assigned video.
8 See App’x 27. But Collins also alleges that these other posts contained “more
9 guarded appraisals” than his. App’x 27. That Putt did not delete the “more
10 guarded” student posts belies Collins’s claim that he was discriminated
11 against for a viewpoint expressed in his post rather than for the manner in
12 which he expressed himself. Indeed, Collins acknowledged at oral argument
13 that other posts’ criticisms focused on the perceptions of the video’s
14 characters and were thus reasonably responsive to the assignment. See Oral
15 Argument, at 11:44–13:24 Collins v. Putt (No. 19-1169-cv),
16 http://www.ca2.uscourts.gov/decisions. By contrast, the point of Collins’s
17 statements was not to perform the assignment but, rather, to emphasize that
18 the “materials did not adequately express the course intent.” Id. An
15
1 instructor does not engage in viewpoint discrimination when she permits
2 student speech that endeavors to perform an assignment, whatever its
3 viewpoint, but deletes speech that predominantly criticizes the assignment.
4 In summary, this is a case in which an assignment posed open-ended
5 questions about certain characters’ perceptions and those perceptions’ effect
6 on their conversation. The Plaintiff, rather than respond to the assignment,
7 ranted about the inadequacy of the materials as a vehicle for teaching
8 communications, thereby addressing a subject entirely outside the scope of
9 the assignment and distracting from the lesson’s pedagogical purpose. Thus,
10 in this context of an online message board for completing course assignments,
11 we conclude that Collins was not subjected to viewpoint discrimination when
12 his post criticizing rather than performing the assignment was deleted. Putt’s
13 deletion resulted from the off topic “general subject matter” of Collins’s post,
14 not a ‘‘prohibited perspective.” Bronx Household of Faith v. Bd. of Educ. of
15 City of N.Y., 650 F.3d 30, 39 (2d Cir. 2011) (quotation marks omitted).
16
1 IV
2 Collins separately argues that the Defendants failed to follow certain
3 internal policies that related to addressing student misconduct, in violation of
4 his due process rights under the Fourteenth Amendment. We disagree.
5 Two days after the removal of his blog post, Collins contacted the
6 provost of Charter Oak State College to complain. After receiving Collins’s
7 complaint, the provost exchanged emails with Collins and offered to fully
8 refund Collins’s tuition. We conclude that Collins was thus afforded a full
9 opportunity to be heard and received sufficient process. See Goss v. Lopez,
10 419 U.S. 565, 584 (1975) (students suspended from school were afforded
11 sufficient process when provided opportunity for “informal give-and-take”
12 allowing them “to characterize [their] conduct and put it in what [they]
13 deem[] the proper context”); Rosenfeld v. Ketter, 820 F.2d 38, 40 (2d Cir. 1987)
14 (student’s two discussions with university administrators afforded him “the
15 opportunity required by Goss to characterize his conduct, put it in the proper
16 context and urge that [u]niversity rules not be enforced against him”). Collins
17 had no constitutionally protected liberty or property interest in the
18 Defendants’ adherence to their own code of conduct. See Holcomb v. Lykens,
17
1 337 F.3d 217, 224 (2d Cir. 2003) (“Although state laws may in certain
2 circumstances create a constitutionally protected entitlement to substantive
3 liberty interests, state statutes do not create federally protected due process
4 entitlements to specific state-mandated procedures.”).
5 To the extent Collins’s pro se complaint can be liberally construed to
6 raise a substantive due process claim based on an alleged violation of his right
7 to free speech, that claim is subsumed in his First Amendment claim. We
8 have held that “where a specific constitutional provision prohibits
9 government action, plaintiffs seeking redress for that prohibited conduct in a
10 § 1983 suit cannot make reference to the broad notion of substantive due
11 process.” Velez v. Levy, 401 F.3d 75, 94 (2d Cir. 2005). Under such
12 circumstances, a “plaintiff’s substantive due process claim is either subsumed
13 in [his] more particularized allegations, or must fail.” Id.; see also Kaluczky v.
14 City of White Plains, 57 F.3d 202, 211 (2d Cir. 1995). For that reason, any
15 discernible substantive due process claim in Collins’s complaint fails
16 alongside Collins’s more particularized First Amendment censorship claim.
18
1 CONCLUSION
2 We have considered Collins’s remaining arguments and conclude that
3 they are without merit. For the foregoing reasons, the judgment of the
4 District Court is AFFIRMED.
19
MENASHI, Circuit Judge, concurring in the judgment:
I agree with the court that Collins’s post on the electronic
message board is subject to the Hazelwood standard because it “may
fairly be characterized as part of the school curriculum” and was
“supervised by faculty members.” Peck ex rel. Peck v. Baldwinsville
Cent. Sch. Dist., 426 F.3d 617, 628 (2d Cir. 2005) (quoting Hazelwood
Sch. Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484 U.S. 260, 271 (1988)) (emphasis omitted).
But restrictions on such speech, “even if reasonably related to
legitimate pedagogical interests,” must be viewpoint neutral. Id. at
633. 1
I disagree with the court’s conclusion that Collins has not
plausibly alleged that he was the victim of unconstitutional viewpoint
discrimination. Collins has plausibly alleged such discrimination and
therefore has stated a claim under the First Amendment. I would
nevertheless affirm the district court on the ground that Putt is
entitled to qualified immunity. See Leecan v. Lopes, 893 F.2d 1434, 1439
(2d Cir. 1990) (“[W]e are free to affirm an appealed decision on any
ground which finds support in the record, regardless of the ground
1 The court suggests that even under the standard of Tinker v. Des Moines
Indep. Cmty. Sch. Dist., 393 U.S. 503 (1969), a school might permissibly
censor a “student’s posting of material not responsive to a class
assignment” in an online forum. Ante at 13 n.4. We have said that “student
expression in the context of a class assignment” is subject to the Hazelwood
standard, Peck, 426 F.3d at 627, so I doubt that Tinker would apply to such
circumstances. But if it did, it is difficult to see how a post in an online
forum—such as the one here, which no one was even required to read—
could possibly be said to “materially and substantially disrupt the work
and discipline of the school” simply because a teacher considers it non-
responsive. Tinker, 393 U.S. at 513. Surely censorship requires a more
substantial justification from the government.
1
upon which the trial court relied.”). Accordingly, I concur only in the
judgment.
I
Before turning to the merits, it is worth considering the court’s
discussion of waiver. In a footnote, the court suggests that “Collins
failed to sufficiently develop a viewpoint discrimination argument.”
Ante at 6 n.1. Ordinarily, the court says, it would deem Collins’s
argument waived. But because of the special solicitude afforded to
pro se litigants, the court says it will consider Collins’s viewpoint
discrimination argument.
To conclude that Collins did not sufficiently develop this
argument is to afford him less solicitude than a counseled litigant
would receive. Under any reasonable standard, Collins adequately
raised and developed his argument that Putt engaged in
unconstitutional viewpoint discrimination. In his opening brief,
Collins clearly articulates his position that Putt censored his post
because she was offended by the viewpoint he expressed. Collins
argues that:
• The issue in this case is “[w]hether ... Appellant’s
classroom speech was lawfully censored because it
offended the Appellee.” Brief of Appellant Jeremy
Collins (“Collins Br.”) 4.
• A professor at a public university cannot “censor
student speech because it offends her” or because
it “might offend another student” because such
“classroom speech is protected by the 1st
Amendment.” Id. at 7.
• Putt “freely admitted to censoring [Collins’s]
thread, stating in part that ‘I will be deleting your
2
post so it does not offend others. It offended me.’”
Id.
• Collins “was not accused of doing anything
wrong, [but] merely of expressing the wrong
ideas, the sort apparently worthy of censure by the
government.” Id. (emphasis omitted).
• “There is no right to be ‘unoffended’ by the
opinions of others … government censure to
prevent offense is unconstitutional.” Id. at 8.
• “Appellee’s censorship, undertaken for no other
reason than her own personal offense, was [not] a
‘legitimate pedagogical concern.’” Id. at 10
(quoting Hazelwood, 484 U.S. at 273).
• Putt’s “pearl clutching ... cannot and should not be
regarded as a lawful excuse for government
censorship absent a showing that the Appellant
had violated a law, a rule, or a code of conduct.”
Id.
• Second Circuit precedent “clearly rules out the
feeling of being ‘offended’ as a justifiable reason to
take action to curtail student speech” because
precedent holds that school officials cannot seek to
avoid “[t]he experience of ‘… discomfort and
unpleasantness that always accompany an
unpopular viewpoint.’” Id. at 11 (quoting Cuff ex
rel. B.C. v. Valley Cent. Sch. Dist., 677 F.3d 109, 112-
13 (2d Cir. 2012)).
• His remarks “were protected by the First
Amendment,” which does not allow a
“prohibition against expression of opinion”
without a greater justification than was present in
this case. Id. at 11-12.
3
Collins further explains his theory of viewpoint discrimination in his
reply brief. “The Appellee argues that the actions taken by Appellee
were ‘viewpoint neutral,’ however, the Appellant has clearly shown
they were not,” he writes. Reply Brief of Appellant Jeremy Collins 8.
“Clearly, his viewpoint was the reason for the censorship.” Id. at 9.
The court’s conclusion that Collins failed to develop his
viewpoint discrimination argument is irreconcilable with our
precedent; we have never held that an argument developed at such
length—especially by a pro se litigant—is insufficient to present an
issue for appellate review. Rather, we have regarded an argument as
waived only when the argument appears in passing or not at all. See,
e.g., United States v. Botti, 711 F.3d 299, 313 (2d Cir. 2013) (concluding
that the appellant waived an argument because he presented it only
“[i]n two footnotes in his briefs to this [c]ourt”); Tolbert v. Queens Coll.,
242 F.3d 58, 76 (2d Cir. 2001) (holding an argument was waived
because it “appears ... only in a footnote stating the proposition
conclusorily in a single sentence”); Norton v. Sam’s Club, 145 F.3d 114,
117 (2d Cir. 1998) (“[W]e have concluded that merely incorporating
by reference an argument presented to the district court, stating an
issue without advancing an argument, or raising an issue for the first
time in a reply brief likewise did not suffice.”); Cooper v. Parsky, 140
F.3d 433, 441 (2d Cir. 1998) (“Any contention that that conclusion was
erroneous has been waived on this appeal, for plaintiffs’ only mention
of [the issue] appears in a footnote in their reply brief.”); United States
v. Restrepo, 986 F.2d 1462, 1463 (2d Cir. 1993) (“We do not consider an
argument mentioned only in a footnote to be adequately raised or
preserved for appellate review.”).
The principle running through our waiver precedents is that
we will generally decline “to scour the record, research any legal
theory that comes to mind, and serve generally as an advocate for [an]
4
appellant.” Ernst Haas Studio, Inc. v. Palm Press, Inc., 164 F.3d 110, 113
f(2d Cir. 1999). Collins does not ask us to do that. Instead, he asks only
that we decide the legal issues that he has squarely put before us.
Because Collins has discharged his obligation to state his “contentions
and reasons for them, with citations to the authorities and parts of the
record on which [he] relies,” Fed R. App. P. 28(a)(8)(A), we have an
obligation to consider those arguments.
II
The court commits several errors in its analysis of the First
Amendment issues in this case. First, the court ignores key allegations
in Collins’s complaint; second, the court erroneously concludes that
Collins conceded Putt censored his post for a viewpoint-neutral
reason; and third, the court fails to apply precedent concerning the
viewpoint-discriminatory application of facially neutral rules.
A
In reviewing “a district court’s dismissal of a complaint,” we
must “accept[] all factual allegations in the complaint as true, and
draw[] all reasonable inferences in the plaintiff’s favor.” Chambers v.
Time Warner, Inc., 282 F.3d 147, 152 (2d Cir. 2002). To survive a motion
to dismiss, a “complaint must contain ‘enough facts to state a claim to
relief that is plausible on its face.’” Biro v. Conde Nast, 807 F.3d 541,
544 (2d Cir. 2015) (quoting Bell Atl. Corp. v. Twombly, 550 U.S. 544, 570
(2007)). “A claim has facial plausibility when the plaintiff pleads
factual content that allows the court to draw the reasonable inference
that the defendant is liable for the misconduct alleged.” Ashcroft v.
Iqbal, 556 U.S. 662, 678 (2009).
The Supreme Court has held that government restrictions on
speech constitute unlawful viewpoint discrimination when the
speech’s “opinion or perspective” is “the rationale for the restriction.”
5
Rosenberger v. Rector & Visitors of Univ. of Va., 515 U.S. 819, 829 (1995).
When “construed liberally and interpreted ‘to raise the strongest
arguments that [it] suggest[s],’” Triestman v. Fed. Bureau of Prisons, 470
F.3d 471, 474 (2d Cir. 2006), Collins’s complaint plausibly alleges that
Putt’s rationale for censoring Collins’s post was that the perspective
it advanced was offensive. That is textbook viewpoint discrimination,
and therefore Collins has stated a claim for relief.
Collins’s complaint contains multiple allegations that state a
claim of unconstitutional viewpoint discrimination. Those allegations
include the following. In the first week of September 2017, Collins
authored a post that, while “includ[ing] what might be reasonably
called a critique of the assignment and materials themselves ... was
not off-topic given the assignment instructions.” App’x 26. His post
“clearly fulfilled all the requirements for the assignment.” Id. at 28.
Because “[e]xamining perception was the entire point of the
assignment,” Collins was permitted “to voice his own perceptions
and viewpoints, even if they [were] not in complete accord with [his]
college instructor’s.” Id. at 26. On September 6, 2017, Putt sent Collins
an email in which she explained that she would be deleting his post.
Id. at 29. Putt said she was deleting Collins’s post because it offended
her and would offend other students, and indeed “Putt censored
[Collins] because his viewpoint was contrary to her own.” Id. at 31.
“Putt’s actions were ... designed to ... enforce some sort of orthodoxy,”
one which forces students “to err on the side of pure dogmatic
adherence to ... Putt’s own presumed viewpoint.” Id.
Because these allegations give rise to a reasonable inference
that Putt censored Collins because she found his views offensive,
Collins has stated a claim under the First Amendment. See FCC v.
Pacifica Found., 438 U.S. 726, 745 (1978) (“[T]he fact that society may
find speech offensive is not a sufficient reason for suppressing it.”);
6
Robinson v. Hunt Cty., 921 F.3d 440, 447 (5th Cir. 2019) (“Official
censorship based on a state actor’s subjective judgment that the
content of protected speech is offensive or inappropriate is viewpoint
discrimination.”); Ridley v. Mass. Bay Transp. Auth., 390 F.3d 65, 82 (1st
Cir. 2004) (“The bedrock principle of viewpoint neutrality demands
that the state not suppress speech where the real rationale for the
restriction is disagreement with the ... perspective that the speech
expresses.”).
The court insists that Putt’s “deletion of Collins’s post reflected
a content-based restriction that the Supreme Court has instructed us
to tolerate in the school setting”—namely, a restriction on student
posts that are off-topic. Ante at 13. The court’s principal factual
support for that conclusion is Putt’s email in which she purportedly
characterizes Collins’s post “as a ‘rant’ targeted at the adequacy of the
‘classroom materials’ rather than the assigned evaluation of the
perception of the video’s characters.” Id. at 14. Read as a whole,
however, Putt’s email undermines the court’s conclusion. The email
states:
This class is designed as an entry level course for all
levels of ability. And age. While I don’t mind a bit of
humor here and there, ranting about the classroom
materials in a manner that some might find offensive will
not be tolerated. You are welcome to find a clip that
illustrates ageism, ableism, automatic processing,
heuristics, perception, selective perception, under
certainty reduction and social construction of self. Please
be sure to include self-concept, self monitoring and self
esteem. Perhaps I will use it next semester. That being
said, I worked in an elder care facility for five years. I
have seen conversations that were very similar to this
play out countless times. I will be deleting your post so it
does not offend others. It offended me. You will be given full
7
credit for your response; it just will be copied into a Word
document. In the future, please be more considerate of
your posts. You might be posting in jest, however, not
everyone will take it that way.
App’x 29 (emphasis added). The court contends that, even after
drawing all reasonable inferences in Collins’s favor, this email admits
of no other interpretation than that Putt deleted Collins’s post for a
viewpoint-neutral reason. That is wrong. While Putt wrote that
Collins was “ranting about the classroom materials,” she did not say
that his post would be removed because it was off-topic. She objected
to “ranting about the classroom materials in a manner that some might
find offensive”—in particular, elder members of the class who would
view Collins’s comments as insensitive to the elderly. Putt expressly
stated that she would delete Collins’s post “so it does not offend
others.”
Because censoring the views of some to prevent offense to
others is viewpoint discrimination, Collins has stated a claim. See
Iancu v. Brunetti, 139 S. Ct. 2294, 2301 (2019) (“[A] law disfavoring
‘ideas that offend’ discriminates based on viewpoint, in violation of
the First Amendment.”); Matal v. Tam, 137 S. Ct. 1744, 1763 (2017)
(“[I]n the sense relevant here, that is viewpoint discrimination: Giving
offense is a viewpoint.”).
Moreover, Putt made clear that she herself was “offended” by
Collins’s post, and she said she disagreed with Collins’s viewpoint
because, in her experience, the video was realistic. App’x 29 (“I
worked in an elder care facility for five years. I have seen
conversations that were very similar to this play out countless
times.“). While the court might think that Putt was profoundly
offended by the mere sight of off-topic commentary—rather than by
comments she viewed as offensive to the elderly—that interpretation
8
is inconsistent with the text of the email and with the fact that Putt
gave Collins “full credit for [his] response,” indicating that she
considered it responsive to the assignment. Id. The most natural
reading of the email—and, at a minimum, a permissible one—is that
Putt was “offended” because Collins disagreed with her about the
realism of the materials and advanced a perspective she saw as
insensitive to the elderly. That interpretation is the only one that
makes sense of Putt’s references to her own experience in elder care
facilities, to the presence of students of any “age” in the class, and to
the alleged offensiveness of Collins’s post rather than any statement
that it was off-topic.
The court emphasizes that Putt wrote in her email that the
“manner” of Collins’s expression was offensive, ante at 6 n.1, and it
concludes that Collins “was discriminated against … for the manner
in which he expressed himself” rather than “for a viewpoint
expressed in his post,” id. at 15. But Collins expressed his views in the
same manner as every other student in the class: he wrote a post on
an online message board. When Putt condemned the “manner” of
Collins’s expression, she was objecting not to his mode of
communication but to the substance of his speech: the words he chose
to write and the tone of his comments—that is, his viewpoint. When
courts have upheld the government’s authority to regulate the
“manner” in which individuals speak, that authority has allowed the
government to regulate the method of conveying a message, not the
message itself. See, e.g., Clark v. Cmty. for Creative Non-Violence, 468
U.S. 288, 294 (1984) (holding that a ban on sleeping overnight in a park
was a permissible “limitation on the manner of demonstrating”);
Members of City Council v. Taxpayers for Vincent, 466 U.S. 789, 803 (1984)
(holding that a ban on posting signs on public property could
permissibly prevent speakers “from communicating with the public
9
in a certain manner”); Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U.S. 104, 116
(1972) (explaining that whether a regulation of the manner of
expression is reasonable depends on “whether the manner of
expression,” such as holding a “silent vigil” or making a “speech,” is
“basically incompatible with the normal activity of a particular place
at a particular time”).
The government may sometimes regulate the “manner” of
speech by specifying that certain types of communication must take
place in certain locations. But it would not be a reasonable regulation
of time, place, or manner for the government to prohibit certain words
or to require a certain tone. Yet, in this case, the court holds that the
government may censor speech when it determines the speaker has
communicated in an “offensive” “manner.” Ante at 6 n.1, 15.
That view has no support in precedent. The Supreme Court has
said that a prohibition on offensive speech “is viewpoint
discrimination” because “[g]iving offense is a viewpoint.” Tam, 137
S. Ct. at 1763. “If there is a bedrock principle underlying the First
Amendment, it is that the government may not prohibit the
expression of an idea simply because society finds the idea itself
offensive or disagreeable.” Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397, 414 (1989).
The First Amendment guarantees a “freedom to be intellectually ...
diverse or even contrary” and to express “opinions which are defiant
or contemptuous” regarding matters that “touch the heart of the
existing order,” let alone opinions that are critical of classroom
materials. Id. (quoting Street v. New York, 394 U.S. 576, 593 (1969)).
In this case, a state actor assigned students to read certain
materials, and she censored student speech she deemed insufficiently
respectful of and deferential toward those materials. She did so
because she found such criticism “offensive” and she disagreed with
10
the critique. The court decides that such viewpoint-based censorship
is permissible. Indeed, it decides that such censorship is so obviously
permissible that Collins’s complaint can be dismissed on a threshold
motion under Rule 12(b)(6). That decision conflicts with the First
Amendment’s requirement that “[t]he government must abstain from
regulating speech when the … perspective of the speaker is the
rationale for the restriction.” Rosenberger, 515 U.S. at 829.
When a government official censors speech because of
disagreement with its perspective, that official violates the First
Amendment. In fact, the “principal inquiry” in determining whether
the government has engaged in viewpoint discrimination “is whether
the government has adopted a regulation of speech because of
disagreement with the message it conveys.” Ward v. Rock Against
Racism, 491 U.S. 781, 791 (1989). Because Collins has plausibly alleged
that Putt censored his post because of disagreement with the message
it conveyed, Collins has stated a claim.
B
In addition to ignoring the complaint’s most relevant
allegations, the court insists that Collins effectively conceded that his
post was off-topic and that Putt deleted it for that reason. That is
incorrect. “[F]or a statement to constitute a judicial admission” that is
binding upon a party, “it must not only be a formal statement of fact
but must also be intentional, clear, and unambiguous.” In re Motors
Liquidation Co., 957 F.3d 357, 361 (2d Cir. 2020). That high standard
ought to be particularly exacting when applied to the pleadings of a
pro se litigant. See Traguth v. Zuck, 710 F.2d 90, 95 (2d Cir. 1983)
(stating that, in evaluating a pro se plaintiff’s submissions, we must
“make reasonable allowances to protect pro se litigants from
inadvertent forfeiture of important rights because of their lack of legal
11
training”). Collins did not concede either that his post was off-topic
or that Putt censored it for that reason—and he certainly did not do
so intentionally, clearly, and unambiguously.
The first purported concession the court identifies is that
“Collins himself alleged [that] his post critiqued the assignments and
materials themselves which was not the assignment.” Ante at 11
(internal quotation marks, citation, and alterations omitted) (citing
App’x 26). Here is the full paragraph from which the court selectively
quotes:
Plaintiff made his first post for the aforementioned
assignment on or around the first week of September
2017. Plaintiff’s fi[r]st post was intentionally humorous,
ironic and provocative. It included what might be
reasonably called a critique of the assignment and
materials themselves, however, Plaintiff was not off-topic
given the assignment instructions.
App’x 26 (emphasis added). This paragraph does not constitute an
intentional, clear, and unambiguous admission that Collins’s post
was off-topic or that Putt deleted it for that reason. It is exactly the
opposite. Collins is explaining that his critique of the assignment and
materials did not render the post off-topic. He says so directly: “Plaintiff
was not off-topic given the assignment instructions.” 2 For the court to
2 The court dismisses Collins’s repeated allegations that he was not off-topic
as “conclusory” and therefore not entitled to an assumption of truth. Ante
at 12. Collins’s allegations are not conclusory. An allegation is conclusory
when it is a “bare assertion[]” that “amount[s] to nothing more than a
‘formulaic recitation of the elements’” of a claim divorced from sufficient
“factual content” to “allow[] the court to draw the reasonable inference that
the defendant is liable for the misconduct alleged.” Iqbal, 556 U.S. at 678,
681. Collins’s allegation that his post “was not off-topic given the
assignment instructions” is not this sort of allegation. It is not “a legal
conclusion couched as a factual allegation.” Twombly, 550 U.S. at 555.
12
read this passage to mean the opposite of what it says—and then to
suggest it is an unambiguous and binding admission of the case
against a pro se plaintiff—is perverse. This paragraph provides no
support for the court’s position. 3
The second purported concession is that Collins acknowledged
that his post “was unresponsive to the class assignment” because he
said that Putt’s “true reason” for censoring him was his “ranting
about the classroom materials.” Ante at 14. The court once again
mischaracterizes Collins’s allegations. The full paragraph from which
the court quotes reads as follows:
Defendant Putt’s actions were deliberate, malicious,
obviously unlawful, designed to intimidate and enforce
some sort of orthodoxy, and contained an implied
accusation that Plaintiff was attacking old people or the
disabled in order to distract from the true reason
Defendant Putt censored the Plaintiff, i.e. his “ranting”
about the classroom materials, something other students
were very unlikely to find “offensive.”
Rather, it is a factual allegation about the nature of the assignment and
Collins’s responsive post. And, more importantly, it does not lack factual
support. Collins’s complaint provides the full text of the assignment and of
Collins’s post. It is hard to imagine what more “factual content” Collins
could possibly provide to support an allegation that his post was
responsive to the assignment when he has provided both the post and the
assignment. The court can evaluate the plausibility of Collins’s claim by
examining the well-supported factual allegations in his complaint. It is
obligated to do so rather than to ignore those allegations as “conclusory.”
3 The court relies on this passage a second time to argue that Collins’s
statement that the post “included what might reasonably be called a
critique of the assignment and materials themselves” constitutes a
concession that his post was off-topic. Ante at 14. The court again ignores
the second half of the sentence—let alone Collins’s repeated allegation that
he was on-topic.
13
App’x 31-32. This paragraph is also not an intentional, clear, and
unambiguous concession that Putt censored Collins’s post because it
was off-topic. First, Collins puts the term “ranting” in quotation
marks, indicating that he is repeating Putt’s characterization of his
comments, not adopting that position himself. Second, Collins’s
description of Putt’s motivation is inconsistent with the court’s
interpretation. Far from conceding that Putt censored his post because
it was off-topic, Collins alleges that “Putt’s actions were … designed
to … enforce some sort of orthodoxy,” one in which students were not
at liberty to disagree with Putt’s views. That is the essence of a
viewpoint discrimination claim. It is difficult to imagine language
that would more clearly express Collins’s position that Putt was
motivated by disagreement with Collins’s viewpoint. And yet the
court somehow reads this passage—in which Collins accuses Putt of
enforcing a prescribed “orthodoxy”—as a concession that Putt
deleted his post for a viewpoint-neutral reason.
The third purported concession is that, because Collins used
the common phrase “I digress” in his post, he was conceding that his
post was off-topic. Ante at 14 (citing App’x 41). Here is the prompt to
which Collins responded: “How does this dialogue demonstrate how
personal perceptions can be out of touch with reality? What are some
moments where we hear the characters recognize their flawed
perceptions? How do these two men reach a compromise of
perceptions?” App’x 41. And here is Collins’s answer: 4
This excruciatingly awkward video in which two
complete idiots have a conversation that could only take
place in an alternate reality on a planet far, far away is, I
4 The answer includes parenthetical references to the assigned reading
material. It also includes a link at the end as well as a full reference to the
assigned reading material, both of which are omitted here. See App’x 41.
14
suppose, intended to demonstrate that both parties[’]
expectations (Verderber, pg. 17) are not in line with
reality and that their respective impression formation
(Verderber, pg[.] 25) of facts led them to a dispositional
attribution [of] motives to the other that probably don’t
exist. Both characters acknowledge that they may have
misjudged the other when, for instance, the young
“artist” realizes he did not take into account the
differently abled community when placing his
photographs on the wall and the cranky old man feels
equally validated by the personal story the young artist
tells of being introduced to photography by another
member of the “greatest generation[.]” Once the young
“artist” realizes the cranky, self pitying old man with
nothing better to do than be offended and angry at life is
not going away he agrees to treat him like a little baby
and escort him around the exhibition where he will
receive the personal care and attention he should
probably be getting from his family, friends, or staff had
he not already driven them away with his miserable
griping. But I digress. All kidding aside it is very difficult
to not be distracted by this ridiculous scenario and its
conclusion. It is patently obvious that both of these
people should have ignored each other and gone about
their business instead of attempting to reach some sort of
mystical understanding. Either that or just had a polite,
non-accusatory conversation. A society based on the
modeled behavior of confrontation/resolution is doomed
and brain dead. As for the video I have no idea what it
was trying to prove or what was proved. I focused on the
task and counted 19 exclamation points. What, precisely,
is the hypothesis being tested in this “experiment”? I
would love to know. Also, Bob Dylan did it way, way
better a long, long time ago... Did you notice Allen
Ginsberg in the b.g.? What did Bob Dylan prove with this
experiment?
15
Id. The court’s position is that Collins’s use of the phrase “[b]ut I
digress” constituted an admission that his post was off-topic. But the
court once again misconstrues Collins’s allegations. The most natural
reading of Collins’s remark is that he acknowledged that his single-
sentence comment on the causes of one character’s isolation—that the
old man had driven away his family with his persistent griping—
constituted a digression from his earlier, indisputably topical point:
explaining how the characters “recognize[d] their flawed
perceptions”—the old man by seeing that the artist has respect for the
elderly and the young artist by realizing that he did not properly
appreciate the struggles of being elderly or disabled—and “reach[ed]
a compromise of perceptions” when the young artist escorted the
elderly man around the art gallery. Because Collins’s use of the phrase
“I digress” does not constitute an intentional, clear, and unambiguous
admission of fact, it does not establish that his post was off-topic.
Put simply, the court’s attempt to find a fatal concession in
Collins’s allegations is unavailing. None of the statements is
sufficiently intentional, clear, and unambiguous to constitute a
binding judicial admission. In fact, if one reads the full passages on
which the court relies, it becomes clear that Collins made no such
concession. In any event, our obligation to afford Collins all
reasonable inferences requires us to interpret these allegations to
support his argument. 5
5 I do not believe that whether Collins’s response to the assignment was
“off-topic” is as important to the resolution of this case as the court
evidently does. As I explain in Part II.C., the government may not
discriminate on the basis of viewpoint even if that viewpoint is “off-topic.”
Still, Collins’s allegation that his post was responsive to the assignment is
plausible. The assignment asks, “How does this dialogue demonstrate how
personal perceptions can be out of touch with reality?” A student might
reasonably respond, as Collins did, by saying that the dialogue attempted
16
C
There is an even more fundamental—and worrying—flaw in
the court’s analysis. The court appears to assume that the
responsiveness of Collins’s post to the assignment is dispositive of his
viewpoint discrimination claim. In other words, the court suggests
that if Collins’s post were off-topic, the government would be free to
censor it. That premise is inconsistent with Supreme Court and
Second Circuit precedent.
We have recognized that a public official engages in viewpoint
discrimination when that official applies a facially viewpoint-neutral
rule in a viewpoint-discriminatory way. See Peck, 426 F.3d at 632-33.
We have also said that a plaintiff states a claim for viewpoint
discrimination when he or she plausibly alleges that the official was
“particularly disposed to censor” the plaintiff’s speech for viewpoint-
discriminatory reasons even if the official invoked a viewpoint-
neutral rationale. Id. at 631. The Supreme Court has made clear that
actions motivated by impermissible viewpoint considerations do not
become lawful simply because those actions might be justified on
some other viewpoint-neutral ground. See Cornelius v. NAACP Legal
Def. & Educ. Fund, 473 U.S. 788, 811 (1985) (explaining that “[t]he
existence of reasonable grounds” for a regulation of speech “will not
save a regulation that is in reality a facade for viewpoint-based
to illustrate a certain lesson regarding personal perceptions but the attempt
was undermined by the dialogue’s lack of realism. The conclusion that his
post was on-topic finds further support in the facts that Collins received
“full credit” for his response, App’x 29, and that other students, according
to the court, also “expressed negative views of the portrayal” of the
dialogue, ante at 15. On a motion to dismiss, the court should not construe
the assignment instructions to render the plaintiff’s response “off-topic”
when the facts could reasonably be construed to reach the opposite
conclusion.
17
discrimination”); see also Turning Point USA v. Rhodes, 973 F.3d 868,
881 (8th Cir. 2020) (Loken, J., concurring) (“In the modern university,
it is all too common for petits fonctionnaires, arbitrarily enforcing broad
rules and policies, to take action that may be politically correct but is
not viewpoint neutral. When such actions trample a student’s
constitutionally protected right of free speech, those responsible
should be held accountable.”).
Though the court acknowledges these principles by remarking
that “[i]t is true that even content- and style-based restrictions on
speech must be imposed evenhandedly, without regard to
viewpoint,” ante at 15, the court makes no serious attempt to explain
why Collins has not plausibly alleged that Putt was “particularly
disposed” to censor posts she found offensive. In an oblique reference
to the issue, the court argues that, because Collins conceded that other
posts that critiqued the assignment were not deleted, he cannot
plausibly allege that it was his critique—as opposed to concerns about
responsiveness—that motivated Putt’s deletion of his post.
Here, the court impermissibly makes factual inferences that
favor the defendants. Earlier in its opinion, the court dismisses as
“conclusory” all of Collins’s allegations about his post being
responsive to the assignment—even though Collins’s factual
allegations included the full text of his post and of the assignment. See
supra note 2. But in this part of its opinion, the court latches onto an
allegation that indicates that other students’ posts also critiqued the
classroom materials. Even though there are no copies of these posts
in the record—and we therefore do not know what the posts said or
how the posts compare to Collins’s—the court regards this allegation
18
as decisive. 6 It does not believe the lack of “factual content” renders
this allegation conclusory because it is willing to infer facts not
alleged or otherwise in the record. But see Iqbal, 556 U.S. at 678.
Yet given that the actual posts are not in the record, we have
only Collins’s allegation. According to his allegation, the other
students’ posts expressed a different viewpoint than his. Here is the
relevant paragraph of Collins’s complaint:
Plaintiff specifically took issue with the stereotypical
portrayal of a disabled character in the video and by
means of an expository backstory attempted to frame the
disabled character’s noxious personality as independent
of his disability and not caused by it. Plaintiff’s rhetorical
device ascribed to the fictional character, a fictional
explanation for his otherwise inexplicably rude,
thoughtless and stupid behavior towards the other
character. By doing so Plaintiff intended to draw
attention to the fact that there was an implicit expectation
to perceive the disabled character’s rude, obnoxious
behavior as unquestionably acceptable merely because
he is disabled. Many other student’s responses included
similar though more guarded appraisals of the disabled
character.
App’x 27 (italics omitted and emphasis added). Collins is apparently
“sensitive” to “stereotypical depictions of disabled people” because
he suffers from “health issues” that include “very limited mobility.”
Id. (Compl. ¶ 20). Whatever his motivation, Collins’s allegation
6See ante at 15 (noting that “Putt did not remove other posts that expressed
negative views of the portrayal of the disabled person in the assigned
video” and concluding “That Putt did not delete the ‘more guarded’
student posts belies Collins’s claim that he was discriminated against for a
viewpoint expressed in his post rather than for the manner in which he
expressed himself”).
19
explained that while other students appeared to sympathize with his
perspective—as least as it pertained to the depiction of the disabled
character—their posts were substantively different. Collins
elaborated at oral argument: “I think my comment was targeted
because I went into more depth and made more arguments than other
students did. They made passing comments about it and I actually
took up the idea that these materials did not adequately express the
course intent or the course topics and concepts.” 7 In other words, he
alleges that he directly expressed a viewpoint to which Putt objected
while other students made only passing comments.
The court reads Collins’s allegation to mean the opposite of
what it says. Whereas he distinguished the viewpoint of his post from
those of other students in the class, the court concludes that those
other posts must have expressed the same viewpoint. How does the
court know this? It is pure conjecture, given that the posts are not
alleged in the complaint or otherwise in the record. Nevertheless, the
court regards this imaginary evidence as so compelling that it allows
Collins’s complaint to be rejected on a motion to dismiss. The “other
posts’ criticisms,” the court explains, describing evidence it has never
seen, “focused on the perceptions of the video’s characters and were
thus reasonably responsive to the assignment.” Ante at 15. This
hypothetical evidence, the court imagines, shows that the school’s
censorship really was about responsiveness rather than viewpoint.
It should go without saying that, on a motion to dismiss—of a
pro se plaintiff’s complaint, no less—the court should not make
inferences about the plaintiff’s factual allegations that favor the
defendants. Yet that is exactly what the court does in this case. Collins
alleges that other students wrote posts that were notably different than
7 Oral Argument Audio Recording at 13:08 to 13:25.
20
his own, and the court takes that allegation to mean that Collins’s
viewpoint was shared and expressed by other students not subject to
censorship. There are no allegations or evidence before the court—
aside from the court’s own speculation—to suggest this.
Besides its incompatibility with Rule 12(b)(6), there are at least
three other flaws in the court’s analysis worthy of note. First, if other
students responded to the assignment with a critique of the classroom
materials, then it is harder to assume without any analysis—as the
court does—that Collins’s post was non-responsive simply because it
included such a critique. Why was his critique singled out as non-
responsive? If the other students’ critiques were materially different
than Collins’s so that he could be singled out, then the court cannot
say that the lack of censorship of those critiques belies Collins’s
allegations of viewpoint discrimination.
Second, even if Collins’s viewpoint about “the portrayal of the
disabled person in the assigned video” were widely expressed across
student posts—which I doubt—it would not undermine Collins’s
central allegations of viewpoint discrimination. Ante at 15. In her
email explaining her censorship of Collins’s post, Putt did not refer to
the disabled character but said she was censoring the post because she
believed it was offensive to the elderly and because she disagreed
with Collins’s argument that the classroom materials were unrealistic.
Third, nothing in our precedents requires that a plaintiff
demonstrate that the government availed itself of every opportunity
to engage in unconstitutional censorship. The court appears to
assume that if other posts expressed views similar to Collins’s and
were not censored, that would doom Collins’s complaint. But it is just
as unconstitutional to discriminate against one speaker’s views as it
is to discriminate against the views of multiple speakers. And it is
21
possible plausibly to allege that the government discriminated on the
basis of viewpoint against one plaintiff even if the government could
have but did not discriminate against others as well.
On a motion to dismiss, the court should not make inferences
in the defendants’ favor. We must construe Collins’s complaint
liberally and afford him the benefit of factual inferences. Applying
that standard, I would conclude that Collins plausibly alleges that
Putt treated his post differently from other students’ posts because
she thought Collins’s post was offensive and expressed a view with
which she disagreed.
D
“At a time when free speech is under attack, it is especially
important for this Court to remain firm on the principle that the First
Amendment does not tolerate viewpoint discrimination.” Iancu, 139
S. Ct. at 2302-03 (Alito, J., concurring). “[U]nder our Constitution the
public expression of ideas may not be prohibited merely because the
ideas are themselves offensive to some of their hearers.” Street, 394
U.S. at 592. By persistently mischaracterizing Collins’s complaint, by
making factual inferences that favor the government, and by failing
rigorously to adhere to our precedent, the court does a disservice to
the important First Amendment principles at stake. For those reasons,
I do not join its opinion.
III
In addition to his First Amendment claim, Collins alleges that
the defendants violated his right to due process under the Fourteenth
Amendment. To state a claim under the Due Process Clause, a
plaintiff must allege that the government deprived the plaintiff of “a
protected liberty or property interest” without adequate process.
Sealed v. Sealed, 332 F.3d 51, 55 (2d Cir. 2003).
22
Collins argues that Putt’s censorship of his post “was based on
the imposition of a vague, inarticulable standard explained only as
that which personally offended her and might offend others.” Collins
Br. 12 (emphasis omitted). He further notes that his being censored
without being afforded due process “is cognizable under 42 U.S.C.
§ 1983 as a substantive violation of Due Process that impinges on
fundamental liberty” because his “right to free speech, established
and codified in the First Amendment, was subjected to an unfair and
arbitrary act of government power without Due Process” by the
defendants. Id.
In other words, Collins argues that the defendants violated his
rights to procedural and substantive due process by violating his First
Amendment right to free speech without following a proper standard
to justify the invasion of his right and, ultimately, while lacking a
sufficient justification. Because Collins’s asserted liberty interest is the
right to free speech guaranteed by the First Amendment, his due
process claim should be assessed according to the standards
applicable to government regulation of speech. See Bauer v.
Montgomery, 215 F.3d 656, 661-62 (6th Cir. 2000) (noting that the
viability of a due process claim premised on the denial of First
Amendment interests depends on whether the plaintiff “has stated a
First Amendment claim”); see also United States v. Lanier, 520 U.S. 259,
272 n.7 (1997) (“[I]f a constitutional claim is covered by a specific
constitutional provision ... the claim must be analyzed under the
standard appropriate to that specific provision, not under the rubric
of substantive due process.”); Southerland v. City of New York, 680 F.3d
127, 142-43 (2d Cir. 2012) (“Where another provision of the
Constitution provides an explicit textual source of constitutional
protection, a court must assess a plaintiff’s claims under that explicit
provision and not the more generalized notion of substantive due
23
process.”) (quoting Kia P. v. McIntyre, 235 F.3d 749, 757-58 (2d Cir.
2000)).
In this case, therefore, Collins’s due process allegations “are
subsumed by [his] more particular allegations” of a violation of the
First Amendment. Hu v. City of New York, 927 F.3d 81, 104 (2d Cir.
2019); accord Velez v. Levy, 401 F.3d 75, 94 (2d Cir. 2005) (noting that a
“plaintiff’s substantive due process claim is either subsumed in her
more particularized allegations, or must fail”). When a due process
claim is “duplicative” of a more specific constitutional claim, our
court’s practice is to dismiss the due process claim. Terminate Control
Corp. v. Horowitz, 28 F.3d 1335, 1351 n.8 (2d Cir. 1994); accord Hu, 927
F.3d at 104; Velez, 401 F.3d at 94; Kaluczky v. City of White Plains, 57
F.3d 202, 211 (2d Cir. 1995). 8 Accordingly, I would “affirm the
[d]istrict [c]ourt’s dismissal of the [due process] claim on different
grounds, concluding that this claim must be analyzed under the [First
Amendment].” Hu, 927 F.3d at 104.
8Prior cases have focused on claims of substantive due process. Collins does
not clearly distinguish between the substantive and procedural
components of his claim. Yet to the extent Collins alleges procedural aspects
of a due process violation, such as Putt’s reliance on a vague standard of
offensiveness, those allegations also duplicate his First Amendment claim
because the First Amendment more specifically prohibits state actors from
censoring speech based on a standard of offensiveness. See, e.g., Tam, 137
S. Ct. at 1763. Collins also suggests that, apart from his First Amendment
interest in free speech, he had a cognizable liberty or property interest in
the school’s use of the processes enumerated in its code of conduct. Yet
“[p]rocess is not an end in itself. Its constitutional purpose is to protect a
substantive interest to which the individual has a legitimate claim of
entitlement.” Olim v. Wakinekona, 461 U.S. 238, 250 (1983). Accordingly, we
have held that “the fact that a state has established procedures to be
followed does not mean it has created a protectable liberty interest” in those
procedures. Rodriguez v. McLoughlin, 214 F.3d 328, 339 (2d Cir. 2000).
24
IV
Despite my disagreement with the court about the plausibility
of Collins’s claim of viewpoint discrimination, I ultimately agree that
Collins’s suit should be dismissed. A defendant is subject to suit
under 42 U.S.C. § 1983 only when that defendant has violated a right
so clearly established that every “reasonable official would
understand that what he is doing violates that right.” Anderson v.
Creighton, 483 U.S. 635, 640 (1987). Although Collins is not required to
provide “a case directly on point, existing precedent must have
placed the … constitutional question beyond debate” and not have
done so at too “high [a] level of generality.” Ashcroft v. al-Kidd, 563
U.S. 731, 741-42 (2011); see also Walczyk v. Rio, 496 F.3d 139, 154 (2d
Cir. 2007) (“[A]n officer is still entitled to qualified immunity if
‘officers of reasonable competence could disagree’ on the legality of
the action at issue in its particular factual context.”). Here, reasonable
state actors could disagree about the legality of Putt’s actions because
Collins’s expression occurred in a forum that is materially different
from those at issue in prior cases.
The forum here differs from those in prior cases because of its
inward-facing and interactive nature. Hazelwood concerned a
newspaper that was widely distributed; “[m]ore than 4,500 copies of
the newspaper were distributed during that year to students, school
personnel, and members of the community.” 484 U.S. at 262. In Peck,
the school censored a poster which was to be “displayed at [an]
assembly” to which “parents of the students were invited.” 426 F.3d
at 621. Here, by contrast, the discussion board was meant only for an
in-class audience. And unlike Hazelwood and Peck—in which those
exposed to the censored material could ignore it—here Collins’s
audience of fellow students was expected to comment on the posts,
though not necessarily on his. See App’x 25-26. These facts suggest
25
that a professor might have reasonably believed that online posts
were a continuation of classroom lectures and discussion that the
professor could regulate more than student expression in a more
traditional forum in which speech is directed to an outside audience.
Because the forum at issue here differs from those in past
viewpoint discrimination cases in this circuit, I would hold that Putt
is entitled to qualified immunity and affirm the judgment of the
district court.
CONCLUSION
In sum, the court’s opinion misapplies precedent concerning
the interpretation of pro se complaints, the judicial admission
doctrine, and First Amendment principles prohibiting viewpoint
discrimination by state actors. For these reasons, I decline to join the
court’s opinion. But because Putt is entitled to qualified immunity, I
concur in the judgment.
26