City of Biddeford Ex Rel. Board of Education v. Biddeford Teachers Ass'n

WERNICK, Justice

(Agreeing in part and disagreeing in part with the opinion of WEATHERBEE, J.).

I concur in the conclusions reached in Part One of the opinion of Mr. Justice Weatherbee.

I disagree, however, with Part Two and its conclusion that the statutory provisions for binding arbitration must be nullified as an unconstitutional delegation of powers legislative in nature. My opinion is that the legislature has constitutionally utilized arbitration, and judicial interference with the legislative program is unwarranted.

“Unconstitutional delegation of legislative powers” connotes that in a given instance the legislature has transferred a portion of its legislative power to another body in contravention of principles derived from constitutional vesting and separation of the three polar categories of sovereign power: legislative, judicial and executive.

For one hundred fifty years the “unconstitutional delegation” doctrine has been developed largely in relation to the sovereign’s exercise of “police power” externally to control and regulate private personal and property rights.

In the instant statute sovereignty appears in a different role. Here, its concerns are directed fundamentally inward to meet internal problems arising from governmental functioning as an “employer” of “employees” in the “business” of providing essential services to the public.

In this domain there is a paucity of judicial authority on “delegation” questions. Since the decision of the instant case thus entails a large measure of pioneering, analysis should not assume that principles of “delegation” formulated relative to “police power” problems are automatically applica*404ble at all, or with full scope, to the present issues. Inquiry should probe deeply to assess whether, and the extent to which, “delegation” principles affecting the exercise of the police powers of government should be transposed into the separate realm of sovereignty’s internal “employer-employee” relationships in the rendering of essential public services, both as a general matter and as specifically crystallized in the particular statutory program now under scrutiny.

I

Before American life had been substantially affected by the political, social and economic complexities of the industrial revolution, the constitutional vesting of the “law-making” power of sovereignty in a specific body, designated the “legislature”, was conceived to reflect, literally, the dogma of John Locke:

“The Legislature neither must nor can transfer the power of making laws to anybody else, or pass it but where the people have.”

Soon, the burgeoning needs and exigencies of the latter part of the nineteenth century caused enormous extension of the scope of governmental police power regulation and necessitated that broad discretionary authority be granted- to bodies other than the legislature. In the face of this development, adherence to the Locke dogma created a dilemma which, at first, the courts sought to resolve by giving lip-service to the dogma while escaping its practical strictures with the rationalization that to delegate to another body only a power to “fill in details” or “find facts” is not really to transfer “legislative” power. Illustrative of this earlier approach are cases such as Locke’s Appeal, 72 Pa. 491 (1873); Field v. Clark, 143 U.S. 649, 12 S.Ct. 495, 36 L.Ed. 294 (1892); and in Maine, State v. Butler, 105 Me. 91, 73 A. 560 (1909).

As twentieth century pressures became heavier, the courts were ultimately driven to the recognition that under the fiction that only “facts were being found” or “details being filled in”, they had been sustaining, with increasing frequency, expansive grants of power unquestionably “legislative” in character.

It became apparent that fiction must be discarded to avoid confusion and error. A new approach was necessary by which twentieth century needs could be met realistically but yet consistently with preservation of the essential spirit of the constitutional vesting and separation of the polar categories of sovereign power.

Interestingly, in the mid-nineteenth century a State Court, with remarkably prophetic insight, had provided the root concept for such undertaking. In People v. Reynolds, 10 Ill. 1 (1848) the Illinois Court had observed:

“ . . . few will be found to insist, that whatever the legislature may do, it shall do, or else it shall go undone. . it may still authorize others to do those things which it might properly, yet can not understandingly or advantageously do itself. Without this power legislation would become oppressive, and imbecile. . . . but in doing this it [the legislature] does not divest itself of any of its original powers. It still possesses all the authority it ever had.” (pp. 13, 20 and 21)

Seventy years later, the message, more frequently heard, was amplified — and by another State Court. In State v. Whitman, 196 Wis. 472, 220 N.W. 929 (1928) the Wisconsin Court perceived that (1) necessity had required “delegation”, and “cross-delegation”, of the powers of government; (2) to accomplish it the courts, by “one pretext or another”, had been upholding extensive delegations of legislative power; (3) avoidance of “confusion and error”, and a “logical and symmetrical development” of administrative law, demanded that a new approach be adopted, abandoning the pretense of “finding facts” and filling in “details” and acknowledging that legislative power, as such, is constitution*405ally permissible of delegation under appropriate limitations to check against abuse— the most potent of which is the legislature’s retention of power to revise or withdraw the power granted; (4) if a prospective legislative “standard” is to be used as a device to confine administrative authority, the subject-matter under regulation will often allow as feasible only a generalized “standard”; and (5) the “standard” need not be expressly stated but may be implicit in the overall statutory context.1

In the development of its rationale Whitman relied substantially upon a course being chartered almost simultaneously by the Supreme Court of the United States in Hampton & Co. v. United States, 276 U.S. 394, 48 S.Ct. 348, 72 L.Ed. 624 (1928) — -a decision itself bringing to fruition the seeds of a newer federal approach' to the problems of “delegation” germinated in 1924 in Mahler v. Eby, 264 U.S. 32, 40, 44 S.Ct. 283, 68 L.Ed. 549 (1924).

In Mahler v. Eby the Supreme Court of the United States, taking its clues from leads in Buttfield v. Stranaham, 192 U.S. 470, 24 S.Ct. 349, 48 L.Ed. 525 (1904), had begun to talk explicitly of the constitutional permissibility of delegation of powers avowedly “legislative” so long as consent of the governed is channeled through the legislature to be a continuing indirect source of control over the actions of a body not immediately responsible to the people. The mechanism conceived to serve this “conduit” function was the prospective prescription by the legislature, as the peo-pie’s delegate, of a “primary standard” to confine the legislature’s delegate.

Hampton & Co. v. United States developed this into the full-blown principle:

“If Congress shall lay down by legislative act an intelligible principle to which the person or body authorized to . "[act] is directed to conform, such legislative action is not a forbidden delegation of legislative power.” (276 U.S. p. 409, 48 S.Ct. p. 352) (emphasis supplied)

Thus, the Court in Hampton & Co. recognized that the transfer of legislative power will not, as Such, produce constitutional infirmity; it is rather the manner of the transfer — whether it places unbridled legislative authority in a body not responsible to the electorate and thus precipitates the potential for an absolutism of power (the primary evil apprehended by Montesquieu and Locke to require the protections embodied in the concepts of “separation” and “checks and balances).”

In Panama Refining Co. v. Ryan, 293 U.S. 388, 55 S.Ct. 241, 79 L.Ed. 446 (1935) and Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States, 295 U.S. 495, 55 S.Ct. 837, 79 L.Ed. 1570 (1935), and even though these decisions represented the solitary instances in which the Supreme Court of the United States had struck down congressional “delegation”, the Court reaffirmed the “intelligible principle” approach — with the further development that the “principle” need not be expressly stated by the legislature but might be regarded as legislatively implied.2

*406Subsequent evaluations in the federal Courts saw the most general of “standards” relied upon to sustain the constitutionality of large delegations of legislative power. As shown by Yakus v. United States, 321 U.S. 414, 64 S.Ct. 660, 88 L.Ed. 834 (1944) and American Power & Light Company v. Securities and Exchange Commission, 329 U.S. 90, 67 S.Ct. 133, 91 L.Ed. 103 (1946), the focus was upon whether the legislature had imposed, explicitly or implicitly, a check on absolutism by an “intelligible principle” by which the delegated power

“is . . . canalized within banks that keep it from overflowing.” Cardozo, J., concurring, in Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States, 295 U.S. 495, 551, 55 S.Ct. 837, 852, 79 L.Ed. 1570 (1935)

To the objection raised in American Power & Light Company that Congress had, in effect, because of vagueness and generality, allowed “unlimited whim” and “unfettered discretion” to the Securities and Exchange Commission

“to decide whose property shall be taken or destroyed and to what extent” (329 U.S. p. 104, 67 S.Ct. p. 142),

the Supreme Court of the United States answered that (1) in other contexts “standards” as broad and indefinite as “public interest,” “just and reasonable rates,” “unfair methods of competition” or even “relevant factors” had been approved as adequate limitations upon the exercise of arbitrary power (p. 105, 67 S.Ct. 133); (2) the judicial approval accorded these broad standards reflected a “necessity”, imposed by complex economic and social problems, which

“ . . . fixes [that] ... it . . . becomes constitutionally sufficient if Congress clearly delineates the general policy, the . . . agency which is to apply it, and the boundaries of this delegated authority” (p. 105, 67 S.Ct. p. 142)

—the protection of private rights being left, primarily, to judicial review

“to test the application of the policy in the light of these legislative declarations” (p. 105, 67 S.Ct. p. 142);

and (3) permissible sources to derive and provide meaning for the concepts interpretable as the boundaries are

“the purpose of the Act, its factual background and the statutory context.” (p. 104, 67 S.Ct. p. 142)

In the state courts a similar trend was plainly discernible, notwithstanding that state courts tended to be more prone than the federal to nullify delegations — often revealing strange internal inconsistencies within a given body of decisions.3

*407In Maine, illustrative is the contrast between Butler, supra, in 1909 and the decision in 1961 in Kovack v. City of Waterville, 157 Me. 411, 173 A.2d 554 (1961). In Kovack, following strong intimations already contained in McGary et al v. Barrows et al., 156 Me. 250, 163 A.2d 747 (1960) (which dealt specifically with “delegation” in the field of education), this Court' basically discarded its earlier conception that law-making powers and authority may not at all be delegated by the legislature to another body and that administrative tribunals may be permitted only to “find facts” or “fill in details.” Frankly acknowledging that:

“There are many instances where the Legislature has delegated to an administrative body authority to use its discretion and judgment” (157 Me. p. 417, 173 A.2d p. 557),

this Court concluded that it must be held justifiable in principle because

“ [administrative bodies are functionally necessary in the process of government”,

and

“There must be that delegation of power sufficient to the end that a proper, . administration may occur.” (p. 416, 173 A.2d p. 556)

The approach of Kovack was to test the validity of the delegation of legislative power in the terms that (1)

“it is important that there exists in the statute adequate procedural safeguards”,

and (2) the

“Legislature sets the standard.” (p. 416, 173 A.2d p. 557)

Cf. also: Smith v. Speers, Me., 253 A.2d 701 (1969) dealing with delegation of the power of eminent domain.

In a dissenting opinion in Arizona v. California, 373 U.S. 546, 83 S.Ct. 1468, 10 L.Ed.2d 542 (1963) Justice Harlan, joined by Justices Douglas and Stewart, incisively summarized the rationale by which the “intelligible principle”, or “primary standard”, mechanism for the delegation of substantial legislative power to a body not directly responsible to the electorate may be deemed to fulfill the essential spirit of the constitutional provisions concerning the vesting and separation of the polar powers of sovereignty to achieve “checks and balances.” Justice Harlan said:

“The principle that authority granted by the legislature must be limited by adequate standards serves two primary functions vital to preserving the separation of powers required by the Constitution. First, it insures that the fundamental policy decisions in our society will be made ... by the body immediately responsible to the people. Second, it prevents judicial review from becoming merely an exercise at large by providing the courts with some measure against which to judge the official action that has been challenged.” (p. 626, 83 S.Ct. p. 1511)

Tn a leading decision, Ward v. Scott, 11 N.J. 117, 93 A .2d 385 (1952), the Supreme Court of New Jersey (likewise conceiving the same two constitutional objectives to be fulfilled by a prospectively prescribed legislative “primary standard” to control broad discretion reposed in bodies not immediately answerable to the people) offered the following specifications for a sound “standards” approach in the exercise of the police power.

(1) “It is settled that the Legislature may not vest unbridled or arbitrary power in the administrative agency ...” (p. 388) ;
*408(2) hence, the legislature must give the administrative agency "a reasonably adequate standard to guide it” (p. 388) ;
(3) “ . . . the exigencies of modern government have increasingly dictated the use of general rather than minutely detailed standards in regulatory enactments under the police power” (p. 388);

(4)expansive latitude for discretion and judgment under a generalized standard is the more readily tolerable, in police power regulation of private rights, when procedural safeguards are afforded as an additional check upon the danger of unwarranted or arbitrary administrative action (p. 389); and

(5)“it is elementary that we
must examine the entire act in the light of its surroundings and objectives. . . . Nor are we restricted to the ascertainment of standards in express terms if they may be reasonably implied from the entire act. ‘. . . That which is clearly implied is as much a part of the law as that which is expressed.’ ” (p. 387)

II

In the present situation, then, attention must be concentrated upon the extent to which the above delineated general, and specific, concepts (as developed in the realm of the police power control and regulation of private rights) have reasonable applicability to government when it is acting as an “employer” of “employees” engaged in the “business” of providing essential services to the public — this being an area in which the police power regulation of private rights is not an inherently prominent factor.

Initially, assessment must be made of whether the powers here granted to “ad * hoc” arbitrators operate in a domain so attenuated in its relationship to “law-making” activity — and, therefore, outside areas likely to precipitate the kinds of value judgments which demand channeling the consent of the governed through the legislature as a continuingly operative control —that insistence upon a “primary standard” or “intelligible principle” becomes realistically unnecessary.

As clarified in Part One of the opinion of Mr. Justice Weatherbee, when the focus is strictly upon the internalities of sovereignty separately and independently of extrapolations affecting the rights of the general citizenry, the sovereign (acting through the legislature) is free to adopt a policy by which it gives an advance consent that its own “employer-employee” disputes be resolved by the binding determinations of persons serving only “ad hoc”; and who, precisely for this reason that they are not continuing governmental officials, are capable of being regarded by the employees of sovereignty as free of its direct, or indirect, pressures or controls.

To the extent, therefore, that sovereignty, as one party, and its “employees” as the other party, both freely consent to submit to “ad hoc” binding arbitration areas of controversy lacking significant spill-over into other spheres in which it is thought necessary to preserve the consent of the governed as an indirect monitor of the exercise of legislative power by a body not elected by the people, an approach which demands a legislatively prescribed “primary standard” might be dispensed with— reliance to be placed, instead, upon a totality of procedural safeguards and adequate techniques of judicial review to prevent irresponsible, arbitrary or capricious determinations.

In the present situation, however, and even though we are in the area of internal governmental employer-employee relationships, factors are present which could develop potential constitutional infirmities were we to forego reliance upon the combination of a before-the-fact legislative “primary standard”, or “intelligible princi-*409pie”, and adequate controls against irresponsible arbitrary action through procedural safeguards and opportunity for effective judicial review.

First, notwithstanding that sovereignty has here provided its own advance consent to binding arbitration should the teacher employees request it, sovereignty has not made choice by the teachers the sole determinant. 26 M.R.S.A. § 965, subd. 4 provides that “either party” may bring about “binding arbitration”; and if arbitration is requested by the public employer, a refusal of the teachers to participate is an unfair labor practice under the combined effects of Sections 964 and 965.

Because the statute empowers the public employer to force binding arbitration against the will of the teachers, it is, in this respect, a “police power” law-making control at least of the teachers-, and this involvement with the exercise of police power might generate need for a decision as to whether unconstitutionality results from the absence of a legislatively prescribed “intelligible principle”, or “primary standard”, to allow a channeling of the consent of the governed and also to enable judicial review to be more effective in detecting and exposing irresponsible arbitra-tional conduct.

Further, there are carry-over effects upon the citizenry generally.

It may be true that (1) in the statutory scheme before us “salaries, pensions and insurance”, as well as “educational policies”, have been removed from the scope of binding arbitration; and (2) thereby, the legislature has taken from the determinative control of the arbitrators areas having the most direct and substantial impact upon the interests of the citizenry not only directly in the field of education but also in the quantity and quality of all other essential public services; and (3) hence, it might be thought that the consent of the governed, as expressed through policy determinations made by the persons whom they elect as their representatives, need not enter as a significant factor to require a prospective legislative “intelligible principle” or “primary standard” to afford a pipeline of control from the people to the arbitrators.

Nevertheless, even as thus carefully limited, the area of “working conditions” which is subject to binding arbitration can involve sufficient overlap with the sphere of “educational policies” (see infra, pp. 413, 414) to precipitate for decision questions as to the statute’s constitutionality should the consent of the governed not be transmitted to the arbitrators by a “primary standard” or “intelligible principle” prospectively prescribed by the legislature. In addition, insofar as “working conditions” (other than “salaries, pensions and insurance”) can entail financial costs, they generate overtones which beat upon general fiscal policy and which, therefore, affect the personal and property rights of the citizenry (1) in the availability, as well as the quantity and quality, of all essential public services and (2) in the taxes which the citizenry will be called upon to pay to provide the services.

Notwithstanding, therefore, that binding arbitration is here restricted to a narrowed domain encompassing only those “working conditions” from which matters of “educational policies” as well as “salaries, pensions and insurance” have been excluded, there yet remains a sufficient connection with “law-making”, at least in the sense of important value choices, to induce search for a legislatively prescribed “primary standard” or “intelligible principle” through which is effected, at least indirectly, a control by the electorate as the ultimate source of fundamental value judgments — and the presence of which will avoid need for a decision concerning potential issues of constitutionality which might be thought to arise were such intelligible principle lacking.4

*410In the assessment of whether the legislature has provided such “primary standard” or “intelligible principle” the criteria for judgment, as above delineated, are that (1) the “standard” or “intelligible principle” need not be expressly stated by the legislature but may be found implicit in the totality of the statutory provisions reasonably *411construed in relation to surroundings and objectives and (2) large latitude for exercise of discretion and judgment by the arbitrators under a “standard” highly generalized becomes the more readily tolerable (a) when the nature of the subject-matter makes such breadth and generality necessary or desirable and (b) ample procedural safeguards are afforded as additional checks to narrow the likelihood of otherwise undetectable irresponsibility, arbitrariness or invidious discrimination.

At the outset of the “Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law”, the legislature expressly declares the fundamental public policy upon which it has settled. In purpose the policy is “to promote the improvement of the relationship between public employers and their employees.” As pragmatic implementation of the purpose, the policy is to achieve it by the specific “uniform” processes that (1) public employees shall have full rights “to join labor organizations of their own choosing” and (2) such labor organizations are “legally recognized” as the representatives of the employees to engage in mandatory “collective bargaining” ultimately to achieve “terms and conditions of employment” to be embodied in contracts. (Section 961) The details of implementation are elaborated in various other provisions of the statute proclaiming the protection of the right of the public employees to join labor organizations (Section 963), defining unfair labor practices (Section 964) and delineating with the greatest of care the details comprehended within the generalized concept of the “obligation ... to bargain collectively.” (Section 965)

Most importantly, the legislature unequivocally clarifies that the obligation to bargain collectively embraces, specially, that the parties (1) submit in good faith to binding arbitration, as provided in Section 965, subd. 4, concerning the area of “working conditions”- — exclusive of “salaries, pensions and insurance” and, additionally, specifically as to teachers, “educational policies” (Section 965, subd. 1, par. C)— and (2)

“ . . . enter an agreement or take other action . . . appropriate to carry out and effectuate such binding determinations”

of the arbitrators. (Section 965, subd. 4)

Thus, the legislature’s policy is clearly and expressly that there be an improvement of the relationship between public employers and their public employees by the mechanism that disputes unresolved by negotiations between the parties shall not continue to fester but shall be forced, at least in part, toward termination, upon the request of either party, by the binding arbitration of such “working conditions” as are not “salaries, pensions and insurance” or significant aspects of “educational policies.” The binding arbitration is to follow after the parties themselves have established the framework within which the controversy is confined not only (1) by virtue of their discharge of their obligation to “confer and negotiate in good faith” but also (2) through the highly probable, if not mandated,5 resort to fact-findings and recommendations developed by an independent panel.

With arbitrational authority placed within these explicitly stated contours, the omission of the statute to delineate additional express criteria by which the arbitrators are to make their selections among “working conditions” creates no fatal deficiency. By what is said expressly, con*412joined with what may be ascertained implicitly, the statute has prescribed an adequate “standard” and “intelligible principle” to contain, and guide, the arbitrators and to allow effective scope to judicial review as a further check upon arbitrariness.

The statute plainly contemplates that the arbitrators shall act reasonably and fairly to resolve the dispute in terms of the respective positions which have been (1) developed by the parties in negotiations, including independent fact-finding, (2) represented by the parties in the issues presented to the arbitrators for decision, and (3) further supported by evidence taken out during the hearing — the statute making abundantly clear that the entire hearing procedure and the statutory specifications regarding the taking of evidence are calculated to achieve relevance “to the issues represented to . [the arbitrators] for determination.” (Section 965, subd. 4)

Unless we would destroy all significance in the expressed legislative policy that binding arbitration is an implementing method “to promote the improvement of the relationship between public employers and their employees”, it must be held an implicit minimal injunction of the statute that the arbitrators act reasonably and fairly to effect accommodation within the bounds developed by the parties and the positions asserted by them. Surely, unless arbitrators act responsibly and with fairness and reasonableness to accommodate the interests of the parties, crystallized in the issues presented for determination and as buttressed by the positions asserted by the parties concerning the issues, and as the parties will themselves have sharpened them through the negotiating process and fact-finding, the arbitrators would frustrate, rather than achieve, the promotion of “the improvement of the relationship between public employers and employees.”

The foregoing analysis could suffice, without more, to sustain the binding arbitration provisions here involved. The legislatively prescribed “standard” or “intelligible principle” — that the arbitrators shall act with reasonableness and fairness to resolve the issues in a manner tending to promote improvement of relationships — is adequate. The conclusion is a fortiori when we observe, further, that there are ample procedural safeguards concerning the conduct of the hearing and provisions for judicial review by which the Court

“may, . . . affirm, reverse or modify any . . . binding determination or decision based upon an erroneous ruling or finding of law.” (Section 972)

Precisely this generalized justification has been approved in an approach taken by the Pennsylvania Súpreme Court — and as to a scope of subject-matter including “salaries, pensions and insurance” and thus having far more direct and extensive impact upon the general citizenry (in terms of their potential tax burdens and the order of the priorities governmental public service provided them) than we presently confront. In Harney v. Russo, 435 Pa. 183, 255 A.2d 560 (1969), and independently of the consideration that constitutional amendment had made a “standards” analysis unnecessary, the Pennsylvania Court chose to deal with the “delegation” issue before it on an assumption that adequate limiting standards were necessary to avoid an unconstitutional delegation of legislative power. Sustaining as sufficient the standard that the arbitrators shall act reasonably to accomplish labor peace between the public employer and its employees in the rendering of essential public services, the Court said:

“To require to a more explicit statement of legislative policy in a statute calling for labor arbitration would be sheer folly. The great advantage of arbitration is, after all, the ability of the arbitrators to deal with each case on its own merits in order to arrive at a compromise which is fair to both parties. The arbitrators’ services are particularly valuable where, as the legislative scheme here requires, *413the parties have been unable to reach an agreement through collective bargaining. Certainly that is what the Legislature envisioned in its attempt to insure labor peace in this critical public area, and this is adequate . . ..” (p. 563)

As to the statute presently before us, we may observe that it goes further to furnish, as reasonably implicit in its overall context, additional subsidiary “intelligible principles” to guide the arbitrators in the discharge of their functions as well as the courts in exercising judicial review.

In the total statutory context the limitations upon the jurisdiction of the arbitrators to make binding determinations elucidate not only the drawing of a jurisdictional line but also “intelligible principles” to guide the exercise of judgmental selectivity within the areas jurisdictionally covered.

It is to be emphasized that the arbitrators are not denied all authority to deal with “salaries, pensions and insurance.” They are responsible to “recommend terms of settlement”, and they “may make findings of fact” thereon, “such recommendations and findings . . . [to] be advisory only.” There is thus crystallized not merely an express differentiation of function but also an implicit message as to the reason for the differentiation. Obviously because they have direct and enormous impact, in terms of costs, not only upon the ordering of priorities within the particular sphere of public services affected by the controversy before the arbitrators but also upon the public employer’s general fiscal budgeting and appropriations for all public services, and the tax burdens consequently imposed upon the citizenry, “salaries, pensions and insurance” are withheld from binding determination by persons who are not directly responsible to the electorate.

Since the legislature has thus manifested an overriding concern with the impact of monetary costs upon the ordering of priorities not only within one sphere of essential public services but as to all public services which the public employer must provide, as well as upon the ultimate burden of taxation, this legislative concern transposes to become one factor which the arbitrators must consider in arriving at determinative decisions concerning any “working conditions” which involve monetary costs.

Legislative intention that the arbitrators take into account the impact of the money costs of those “working conditions” which are to be settled upon for contractual incorporation is further manifested by the express legislative mandate that not only as to “wages” or “rates of pay” but also “any other matter requiring appropriation of money by any municipality” (emphasis supplied), it is a pre-condition of the subject-matter’s being eligible for collective bargaining that

“the bargaining agent . . . serve written notice of request for collective bargaining on the public employer at least 120 days before the conclusion of the current fiscal operating budget.” (Section 965, subd. 1)

Similarly, the exclusion of “educational policies” from the jurisdictional scope of binding arbitration, in the case of teachers, operates with carry-over effect to provide additional subsidiary “intelligible principles” to guide discretional selectivity by the arbitrators within the domain of the “working conditions” which may be bind-ingly determined.

The concepts of “working conditions” and “educational policies” yield a significantly clear core of meaning when they are regarded as the opposite poles of a continuum toward the center of which there will be large degrees of intermixture. Whether a datum is analytically classifiable as “working conditions” rather than “educational policy”, or vice-versa, will depend, therefore, on (1) the decision made as to the legislature’s intended direction of emphasis and (2) recognition that notwithstanding the ultimate theoretical classification decided upon, the substantive reality *414retains those features of the opposed classification which inhered in it as a fact before the theoretical classification process was undertaken.

Hence, as a glass containing water to the halfway point may be said to be “half empty” or “half full”, dependent upon the direction of emphasis and, in addition, no matter what the theoretical designation chosen, the reality continues to remain both “half full” and “half empty”, so will the appropriate classification of a given subject-matter as “working conditions” or “educational policy” be controlled by the presumed legislative emphasis; and the substantive reality after classification will retain in fact the features of both categories.

Thus, the process by which the arbitrators decide their jurisdiction to make binding determinations simultaneously provides them with an “intelligible principle” to guide their selection (from among the totality of “working conditions” subject to their jurisdiction) of those which shall be contractually incorporated. The arbitrators will be obliged to bear in mind that (1) the legislature deemed “educational policies” to involve value choices so fundamental that binding decisions concerning them should be made essentially unilaterally and by persons directly responsible to the people and (2) for this reason, even though the arbitrators might reasonably believe a concrete item to embody a sufficient measure of the features of “working conditions” to overbalance an admixture of “educational policy”- — thereby warranting a conclusion that the subject-matter is to be classified as “working conditions” and, as such, subject to binding arbitrational determinations by them — the arbitrators must acknowledge the continuing importance of such generalized interests of the citizenry in the overall domain of education as might be relevantly in play. The arbitrators must balance the impacts of such “educational policy” overlays as inhere in fact (even though they might not have been sufficient to require that the subject-matter be classified as “educational policies” thereby to be totally excluded from collective bargaining and binding arbitration) against the weight of the “working conditions” interests of the teachers (e.g., their comfort and their ability to perform and work with efficiency, effectiveness, enjoyment and satisfaction). Into this assessment will enter, also, the consideration that arbitration is offered, policy-wise, as a partial substitute for the denial to the teachers of a right to strike and, hence, counterbalancing evaluation must be made in arbitration of what the teachers might be capable of winning were they allowed resort to the economic force of a right to strike.

In light of the foregoing discussion disclosing the existence of “standards” or “intelligible principles” by which, expressly and implicitly, the authority of the arbitrators is legislatively contained, a point cogently made by Professor Louis L. Jaffe and based upon the premise that

“Delegation of power to administration is the dynamo of the modern social service state” (p. 85)

must be stressed.

“If, . . ., the legislature has seen fit to create an organism for the transaction of public business, its validity should be sustained if one among competing logical implications reasonably supports it. At such points the theory of separation is logically too infirm to condemn any sensible or covenient arrangement. We should in sum keep in mind that the great end of the theory is, by dispersing in some measure the centers of authority, to prevent absolutism.” Jaffe, Judicial Control of Administrative Action (p. 32)

Thus, in the final analysis the potency of the presumption favoring constitutionality of legislative action becomes determinative. As this Court stressed in Crommett et al v. City of Portland, 150 Me. 217, 107 A.2d *415841 (1954) quoting Laughlin v. City of Portland, 111 Me. 486, 90 A. 318 (1914):

‘The Court is bound to assume that, in the passage of any law, the Legislature acted with full knowledge of all constitutional restrictions and intelligently, honestly and discriminatingly decided that they were acting within their constitutional limits and powers. That determination is not to be lightly set aside. It is not enough that the court be of the opinion that had the question been originally submitted to it for decision it might have held the contrary view. The question has been submitted in the first instance to the tribunal designated by the Constitution, the Legislature, and its decision is not to be overturned by the court unless no room is left for rational doubt. All honest and reasonable doubts are to be resolved in favor of the constitutionality of the act. This healthy doctrine is recognized as the settled policy of this court.’ ” (150 Me. pp. 231, 232, 107 A.2d p. 850)

The attack upon the binding arbitration provisions of the Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law, as an unconstitutional delegation of legislative powers, fails. In this respect, the statute is constitutionally valid and must be judicially sustained.

Ill

Since this opinion upholds the legislative scheme of binding arbitration, the additional issues are reached of asserted invalidity by virtue of improprieties in the conduct of the arbitration and claimed “erroneous . . . finding[s] of law” in the decision.

III-A

The conduct of the arbitration is attacked on two grounds: (1) bias and prejudice of the neutral arbitrator as manifested by language contained in the arbitration decision, and (2) disqualification of the person appointed to the arbitration panel by the Biddeford Teachers Association because he had been

“ . . . employed full time by the Maine Teachers Association with which the Biddeford Teachers Association is affiliated and participated as advisor . at various times in the bargaining process prior to the arbitration.”

Both grounds fail.

Notwithstanding that the arbitration decision sharply rebukes counsel for the Biddeford Board of Education and persistently points up his lack of cooperation to assist in the accomplishment of the purposes of the proceeding, the totality of the record — including, specifically, the cogent point that all three arbitrators signed the arbitration decision — shows an absence of bias or prejudice attributable to the neutral arbitrator and likely to affect or in fact tainting his conscientiousness, impartiality and fairness.

Similarly, no fatal infirmity was caused either in the composition, or the decision, of the arbitration panel because the person designated by the Biddeford Teachers Association might be regarded as “interested” in the subject-matter or parties — as an employee of the Maine Teachers Association who had participated in the prior proceedings leading to the arbitration.

The statutory design for the selection of a tripartite arbitrational panel reveals that the legislature was unconcerned with the “interests”, pecuniary or otherwise, of the two arbitrators to be designated by the parties. Only as to the third arbitrator— to be appointed by the two arbitrators selected by the parties or, upon their failure to agree, by the American Arbitration Association, — is there a statutory sepcification of qualifications. The third arbitrator shall be (1) “neutral” and (2)

“ . . . not, without the consent of both parties, . . . the same person selected as mediator pursuant to subsection 2 nor any member of the *416fact-finding board selected pursuant to subsection 3.”

This omission of the statute to state qualifications for the party-designated arbitrators, and the implications flowing negatively from the inclusion of restrictive qualifications for the third arbitrator, establish that the two party-appointed arbitrators are neither imcompetent nor disqualified because they might have interests concerned with the subject-matter of the arbitration, or the parties, or which arise by virtue of participation in processes prior to arbitration.

The type of arbitration here involved— so-called “interests” arbitration to establish particular terms and conditions of a contract (as distinguished from “grievance” arbitration by which the terms of an existing contract are interpreted or applied)-— suggests a sound policy reason for favoring, rather than prohibiting, the designation by the parties of “interested” arbitrators. In “interests” arbitration the function of the arbitrators is to make a contract for the parties which they were unable to make for themselves. It is, therefore, desirable that a degree of “bargaining” be part of the arbitration process itself — to assist in the ultimate settlement of contract terms and conditions. Such continuance of bargaining into the arbitrational process, including the reaching of accommodations usually necessary if the arbitration is to result in an improvement of the relationships between the contesting parties, is effectively achieved if the arbitrators appointed by the parties, precisely because they are allowed to have “interests”, may function as “advocates” along the way to becoming, ultimately, decison-makers.

III-B

Particular aspects of the arbitration decision attacked as “erroneous finding[s] of law” must now be evaluated.

III-B-1

Claim is made that the arbitrators’ approval of the contractual clause:

“Except as otherwise specifically provided in this Agreement or otherwise specifically agreed to in writing between the parties . . . ”,

to operate as a limitation upon the further contractual language:

“the determination of educational policy, the operation and management of the schools and the control, supervision and direction of the certificated staff are vested exclusively in the Board”,

contravenes independent statutory mandates.

The argument is that the reference to “certificated staff” comprehends all full-time principals, all substitute teachers and all part-time teachers (because of the provisions of 20 M.R.S.A. § 1751) — with the consequence that the above stated language of exception, it is said, effectively subjects full-time principals, substitute teachers and part-time teachers to the collective bargaining process as well as to coverage under a collective bargaining contract — in direct violation of the exclusions of 26 M.R. S.A. § 962, subd. 6.

The argument misconceives the purport of the excepting clause under consideration. In itself the clause is without operative effect to delineate an appropriate bargaining unit or to bring any persons within the coverage of the contract. Some separate and independent provision of the contract is requisite for such purpose. Were the present contract to contain such separate independent provision, subjecting to contractual coverage persons excluded by Section 962, subd. 6, it would be that separate and independent provision which should be attacked as invalid — not the excepting clause under scrutiny. Yet, the Biddeford Board of Education has pointed to no such separate independent contractual provision. It is, therefore, specious for the Board to assail the instant general language of exception, more particularly since this language performs the important, and valid, function of ciar-*417ifying that various portions of the collective bargaining agreement — pursuant to changes of prior law introduced by the Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law — have limiting effect upon what (otherwise) would be unilaterally exclusive powers of superintending school boards or committees.

Assault is made upon the arbitrators’ approval of a contractual clause establishing a “sick-leave bank.” The “sick-leave bank” provision authorizes each teacher, who is independently contractually granted 20 days annual sick leave with unlimited accumulation, voluntarily to become a member of the “bank” by a contribution, from his own allowable sick leave days, of one day — the total of contributions to create a maximum of 180 “banked” days. Any member of the “bank” may draw from it to a maximum of 30 days in any one school year to cover absence because of illness for a period in excess of said teacher’s own total “sick-leave” authorization. When the number of days in the “bank” is reduced to a minimum of 30, the “bank” members are to contribute another one day each to re-establish the 180 days “bank” maximum.

Contention is made that the arbitrational approval of such “sick-leave bank” is error of law because (1) 20 M.R.S.A. § 1951 must be interpreted to prohibit the pooling, or transfer, of sick-leave days6 and (2) in any event, the “sick-leave bank” is “effectively” a subject-matter relating to “salary” and, hence, must be held legally excluded from the scope of binding arbitration. Both points are without merit.

By its literal language 20 M.R.S.A. § 1951 aims only to guarantee minimal annual sick-leave and accumulativeness. Solely for this purpose, the statute speaks, as it must to establish a unit of reference for computation of the minimum, of a relationship to each individual teacher. There is, however, an absence of language having reasonable tendency to show legislative insistence upon the entirely different concept that sick-leave days must be personal to each teacher and personally utilized, thereby to prohibit pooling or transfer of sick-leave days. Neither does the manifest statutory purpose to mandate a minimum amount of sick-leave days and accumulations suggest that the statute is violated in spirit by recognition of the propriety of pooling or transfer — whether of the statutory minimum or of contractual allowances in excess of the statutory minimum.

The argument that in making binding determinations for contractual inclusion of a “sick-leave bank”, the arbitrators exceeded their jurisdiction because the “sick-leave bank” is really a form of “salary” (concerning which arbitrators are authorized to act only advisorily) is likewise fallacious for error in its premise.

“Salary”, as ordinarily conceived, reasonably connotes an actual, affirmative regular payment of benefits (usually in monetary form) in exchange for work or services. Measured by such concept the “sick-leave bank” does not lend itself, reasonably, to a classification as “salary.”

Independently of the “bank” plan, the public employer is contractually committed to “sick-leave” to a theoretical maximum for each teacher of 20 days and unlimited accumulativeness. By the “bank” arrangement any individual teacher “member” derives opportunity for sick-leave enjoyments *418in excess of said teacher’s otherwise allowable maximum. And it is true that such “benefit” to individual teachers is achieved through the device of limited pooling and transfer arrangements among teachers from the aggregate of sick-leave days authorized for all teachers without causing need that this aggregate maximum be exceeded.

Yet, it must be recognized that the aggregate maximum sick-leave days theoretically authorized for all teachers, in the absence of a sick-leave bank and should each teacher be permitted sick-leave days only on a personal basis without pooling and transferability, are not usually totally claimed in practice. Thus, without the “sick-leave bank” the public employer would ordinarily have the “benefit” that of the total sick-days authorized for all teachers a residual number remain unused. This “benefit” to the public employer is impaired by operation of the sick-leave “bank” insofar as transfers from the “bank” among individual teachers, even though within the aggregated maximum allowed for all teachers, tends to reduce the number of ultimately unclaimed sick-leave days; and this reduction is to be regarded as an economic “cost” to the public employer.

To categorize such “economic benefit” to any individual teacher and “economic cost” to the public employer as “salary” to the teacher “paid” by the public employer, however, would be to pervert the ordinary, plain meaning of “salary.” It would be to transform the ordinary connotations of “salary”- — directness, regularity and actuality of payment — into that which is indirect, sporadic and fortuitous. No sound reason appears suggesting that the legislature intended that “salary”, as used in the Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law, should carry such artificial and distorted meaning.

The provisions for “sick-leave bank” are thus not reasonably to be regarded as a form of “salary.” The arbitrators acted within their jurisdiction when they bind-ingly determined that the “sick-leave bank” should be incorporated as a term of the contract.

III-B-2

Attacks upon other facets of the arbitra-tional decision are comprehended within the generalized claim that they are errors of law because the arbitrators exceeded their jurisdiction by purporting to make binding contractual determinations on specific matters of “educational policies.”

Since the exclusionary concept of “educational policies”, and its specific relationships to “working conditions” as the inclu-sionary statutory concept for collective bargaining and binding arbitration, will provide the foundation for subsequent analysis, a preliminary exposition of general guidelines will be helpful.

As already observed (ante at p. 413), “educational policies” and “working conditions” may be reasonably conceived as categories defining areas with essential purity at the extremities but with intermediate zones of substantial intermixture. Thus, in the controversies between teachers and their public employers (currently prevalent throughout the country), even if some of the concrete items in dispute may be readily classifiable at the pure extremes of “policies” or “working conditions”, it is undeniable that by far the major portion lie in the intermediate areas with substantial intermix-ings.

How, then, is exclusionary and inclusion-ary classification under the Maine statute rationally to proceed? Again, as already discussed (ante, at p. 413), the key is found in ascertainment of the legislatively prescribed direction of emphasis by which particular features of one classification must be considered legislatively subordinated to factors of the opposed classification.,

The legislative language on its face sufficiently offers an answer for these purposes. The crucial words appear in Section 965, subd. 1, par. C. After first clari*419fying that the obligation to bargain includes the duty .

“To confer and negotiate in good faith with respect to wages, hours, working conditions and contract grievance arbitration . . .”,

the statute immediately thereafter specifies, in particular relationship to the public employers of teachers, the exception that

“public employers of teachers shall meet and consult but not negotiate with respect to educational policies . . . .”

Had the legislature seen fit to end its recitation at this point, it might be held a reasonable conclusion that the concept of “educational policies” was legislatively intended broadly to mandate continuance of the unilaterally exclusive powers of school boards to “supervise” and “manage” the public schools- — as such powers had been traditionally conferred by statute prior to the enactment of the Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law; and that, therefore, any concrete item tending to impinge upon any area ordinarily conceived as “supervision” or “management” must be excluded as an appropriate subject of mandatory collective bargaining regardless of its concomitant relationships to the “working conditions” of teachers.

It is of extreme significance, therefore, that in Section 965, subd. 1, par. C the legislature revealed that it was not content to leave the language as above set forth— thereby to open the door to the extreme “exclusive-management-prerogatives” interpretation above indicated. On the contrary, the legislature was careful, explicitly and definitively, to insert additional language having strong tendency to show that “educational policies” was legislatively intended to be restrictively, not broadly, conceived — specifically that “for the purpose of this paragraph” the calculated meaning is that

“educational policies shall not include wages, hours, working conditions or contract grievance arbitration.”

Such double emphasis by the legislature upon the overriding importance of the concept of “working conditions” in relation to the collective bargaining process, — first, that by affirmative definition teacher “working conditions” are explicitly included within mandatory collective bargaining and, second, that by negative exclusion “working conditions” are eliminated from the limitational effects of “educational policies” — signifies, most clearly in my view, a legislative design that the general doctrine of “unilaterally exclusive managerial prerogatives” must not be permitted to operate as an instrumentality by which all practical substance may be scooped out of the concept of teacher “working conditions”, to transform teacher collective bargaining — in marked contradistinction to the collective bargaining of all other public employees — into a litany noble in sound but hollow in reality.

More particularly, I interpret such double legislative emphasis upon the “working conditions” of teachers to mean that the legislature intended that teacher “working conditions” shall be bilaterally negotiable in collective bargaining and subject to binding arbitration (except for “salaries, pensions and insurance”) notwithstanding that they touch upon one specific “managerial” function with which, as a practical matter the “working conditions” of teachers are almost invariably interconnected — i. e., the organization, supervision, direction and distribution of working personnel. Since decisions concerning almost every “working condition” of teachers will tend to encroach upon the “managerial” organization, supervision, direction or distribution of the working personnel, were this single facet of “managerial” functioning to be permitted to accomplish, under the category “educational policies”, a per se automatic exclusion of teacher “working conditions” from the collective bargaining process, there would result precisely that emasculation of “working conditions” as a mandatory subject of collective bargaining and of binding arbitration which, as above indi*420cated, the legislature — by its specially reiterated emphasis upon “working conditions” —must reasonably be interpreted to have sought to prevent.

Thus, (1) negatively, not only must impact upon the organization, supervision, direction and distribution of personnel be held insufficient, per se, to exclude items related to teacher “working conditions” as proper matters of collective bargaining and binding arbitration but also, (2) affirmatively, the reasonably manifest legislative intention must be held to be that other contacts of such items with other functions generally cognizable as “managerial” and “policy-making” can subordinate the “working conditions” features, and accomplish an exclusion from negotiability and binding arbitration, only if, on balance, their quantitátive number or qualitative importance, or both, are found significantly substantial to override the prima facie eligibility for collective bargaining and binding arbitration established by the presence of reasonable relationships to “working conditions.”

"Class Sise”

By such general approach to the application of the “working conditions” — “educational policies” dichotomy, and as an initial illustration of the techinque in operation, I conclude that the concrete item of “class size” lies within “educational policies” — excluded from collective bargaining and binding arbitration.

Although the size of a class to be taught by a given teacher plainly and seriously affects teacher “working conditions”, the impacts of “class size” overlap into a number of “managerial” and “policy” areas which are of substantial qualitative importance. “Class size” requirements directly involve considerations not merely of organization, supervision, direction and distribution of personnel but also of the needs for additional school building construction or other types of capital outlays, the current population trends, the appropriate use of technological developments (such as television or other electronic teaching aids) and the swings in educational philosophies and theories and the manner of their implementation.

Here, then, (1) “working conditions” features are so intimately entwined with an abundant plurality of important “managerial” and pure “policy” elements that “class size” must be deemed to be an integral complex of “educational policies” and “working conditions” — incapable of separation to allow the “working conditions” factors to be negotiated in isolation and (2) with “class size” thus treated as an inseparable unit, it cannot, as a unit, qualify for collective bargaining and binding arbitration because the weight of the “educational policies” factors contained in it are sufficiently heavy to override the impacts upon the “working conditions” of teachers.

The arbitrators exceeded their jurisdiction in making binding determinations as to “class size.”

“Length of a Teacher’s Working Day"

Similarly, the length of the school day in terms of the number of hours the teacher will be required to teach or be in attendance at school, is a matter concerning which the “working conditions” interests of teachers are fundamentally inseparable from a plurality of non-teacher considerations involving important “managerial” and “policy” areas.

While it is clear that the number of hours which any individual teacher shall be required to work in a given day need not coincide with the number of hours the students are obliged to be in attendance at school, this fact by itself fails to establish that the length of the teacher’s school day may be isolated as a proper subject of mandatory collective bargaining. Closer scrutiny reveals that were the length of the teacher’s school day negotiable in collective bargaining and in a given situation were economic conditions to preclude the hiring of additional teaching personnel, negotia*421tions aimed at shortening the work-day of teachers would necessarily become directed toward seeking alternatives to the hiring of additional personnel. There would thus eventuate an exploration into such areas as the utilization of newer educational techniques by which a teacher’s actual presence or participation is rendered unnecessary— e. g., electronic aids, open class rooms, team teaching programs and subject-matter restrictions or modifications. In this manner, significantly more substantial intrusions into “policy” areas,- — over and above encroachment simply upon the “managerial” supervision, organization, direction and distribution of personnel — become involved.

Thus, the length of the teacher’s working day is closely and heavily interwoven with judgments bearing upon the welfare of the students,' — as reflected in the ultimate quality of their education and the extent to which it may be improved or weakened by use of various types of substitutes, technological or otherwise, for the living presence and active participation of teachers. Such foundational educational value judgments cannot reasonably be subordinated to the overlay of teacher “working conditions”, and for this reason, the length of the teacher’s working day must be held, fundamentally, that kind of “educational policies” subject-matter which was legislatively intended to remain outside the scope of mandatory collective bargaining and, therefore, of binding arbitration.

The arbitrators exceeded their jurisdiction in making binding determinations concerning the length of the teacher working day.

“Scheduling and Length of School Vacations and of the Commencement and Ending of the School Year”

On similar reasoning,} questions concerned with the scheduling and length of school vacations and the commencement and ending of the school year (insofar as such calendar aspects, respectively, are directed at teacher attendance at school) must be held matters of “educational policies” and, as such, non-negotiable and beyond the scope of binding arbitration.

Here, again, the “educational policies” predominance arises not merely because of an impingement upon the “managerial” function of organizing, supervising, directing and distributing personnel but mainly because of a substantial intermixing of judgments transcending teacher interests and embracing important interests of the general citizenry. Since the teaching staff is reasonably to be required to be at school, minimally, whenever the students must attend, the commencement and termination of at least such minimum school year for the teachers, and the scheduling and length of intermediate vacations, will be settled by such calendar arrangements as are to be fixed for student attendance.

Into the calendar arrangements for students enter considerations and decisions involving the plans and interests of families, the need to arrange for the presence of all non-teaching personnel who function while students are in attendance at school and the interests and concerns of all other parts of the community related to, or affected by, the times when students will be in attendance at school or on vacation.

Thus, the commencement and termination of the school year and the scheduling and length of intermediate vacations during the school year, at least insofar as students and teachers are congruently involved, must be held matters of “educational policies” bearing too substantially upon too many and important non-teacher interests to be settled by collective bargaining or binding arbitration.

The arbitrators exceeded their jurisdiction in purporting to make binding determinations concerning this subject-matter.

“Pre- and post-school Day Hours and pre- and post-school Year Days for Teacher Attendance at School”

On the other hand, questions relating to the attendance of teachers at school at times other than when the students will be *422in attendance are to be regarded as “working conditions” of teachers lacking significant relationships to non-teacher interests of a quantitive and qualitative magnitude sufficient to negate collective bargaining or binding arbitration. The negotiation or arbitration of questions related to whether and when teachers shall be at school, even though the students are not in attendance, impinge only upon that “managerial” function concerned with the organization, supervision, direction and distribution of personnel. As above emphasized, this single “managerial” factor must be regarded as insufficient per se to establish the kind of involvement with “educational policies” requisite, statutorily, to remove an item substantially related to teacher “working conditions” from the sphere of mandatory collective bargaining or of determination by binding arbitration.

The arbitrators acted properly within their jurisdiction in making binding determinations concerning pre- and post-school day hours and pre- and post-school year days for teacher attendance at school (at times other than when the students would be in attendance).

“Teacher Aides for non-teaching ‘Housekeeping’ Functions”

By the same analysis the issue of the use of teacher aides to monitor play grounds, supervise lunch periods, load and unload buses and other non-teaching types of activities must be held a subject proper for collective bargaining and within the scope of binding arbitration.

Unquestionably bearing heavily upon the work load of teachers, the issue of teacher aides for various “housekeeping” functions touches upon other areas ordinarily deemed to affect “policy” — over and above a narrow impingement upon “managerial” organization, supervision, direction and distribution of personnel — only in terms of the monetary costs of hiring the additional non-professional personnel. That money costs may become involved — -with potential for impact upon not only the ordering of educational priorities but the overall budgeting appropriations and tax rate of the public employer — does not suffice, ipso facto, to exclude from negotiability or binding arbitration any concrete item substantially related to “working conditions.” (See ante, p. 413) Rather, these monetary costs of various “working conditions” are operative as one consideration providing guidance to the arbitrators as they engage in the balancing of facts leading to the accommodations they make when they select the particular terms to be fixed as contractually binding.

The subject-matter of teacher aides for non-teaching “household” tasks is negotiable and subj ect to binding arbitration.

In making binding determinations of the issues, the arbitrators acted within their jurisdiction.

“Specialist Teachers for Specific Types of Subject-matter Taught or Services Offered”

Analysis discloses that the question of the employment of “specialist” teachers for particular subjects being taught or services being offered students is a matter bilaterally negotiable in collective bargaining and included within the sphere of binding arbitration.

The issue, here, is posited not as requiring decision whether a particular subject, such as art, music or remedial reading is to be taught as part of the curriculum or whether a special type of “service” (such as guidance counseling, remedial reading or library) is to be offered. The assumption is that it has been settled that art, music, remedial reading, guidance counseling and library services are to be taught as subjects or offered as services.

The question is, rather, who, shall do such teaching or provide such services — • specifically, whether it shall be an additional ancillary task to be borne by regular class-room teachers who have other pri*423mary teaching and class-room responsibilities or whether it shall be made the primary responsibility of teachers who are fundamentally free of generalized regular teaching obligations and who are to concentrate as specialists in a subject-matter which involves special skills or knowledge.

Clearly, to the extent that art, music, remedial reading, guidance and counseling or acting as a librarian do involve special types of skills and knowledge, to have regular teachers assume the additional ancillary responsibility for such specialities not only increases the work load of the regular teachers, as such, but also tends, indirectly, to cause them additional difficulties; it tends to introduce a potential for frustrations and dissatisfactions should regular teachers be unable to develop the special skills, or competencies, for which they are thus given ancillary responsibility.

To have these “working conditions” aspects determined by bilateral negotiation and ultimately (should it be necessary) by binding arbitration, as with the issues of teacher aides for “household” tasks, impinges upon “managerial” and “policy” areas — over and above an involvement with the organization, direction and distribution of personnel — basically only in terms of the additional monetary expenditures which might be required to arrange for such “specialist” teachers.

Hence, as with teacher aides for “housekeeping” tasks, the contacts with the “managerial” and “policy” realm must be held insufficient to override the prima facie eligibility for negotiation and binding arbitration established by the important “working conditions” factors present. That money expenditures might be involved does not preclude bilateral negotiation or binding arbitration but rather is only one of a plurality of considerations which enter into the ultimate determination by the arbitrators of whether, and to what extent, “specialist” personnel for the above designated “special” subjects or services shall be used rather than to have these “special” subjects or services (art, music, guidance counseling, remedial reading and library) be taken on as additional ancillary responsibilities of regular teachers who have other primary teaching tasks to perform.

The arbitrators acted within their jurisdiction in making binding determinations concerning these questions of “specialists” for “special” subjects or services.

III-B-3

The Biddeford Board of Education has levelled a wide ranging onslaught against all of the determinations in the arbitrational decision the implementation of which entails monetary expenditures. The argument is that since the monies for the conduct of the public schools come from the municipal legislative body empowered to make appropriations, the arbitration panel had lawful jurisdiction to settle issues requiring money expenditures for their implementation not bindingly but subject only to a contingency that adequate funds will be provided by appropriations.

The argument is unacceptable. It is fundamentally at odds with the basic pattern and objectives of the Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law.

As fully explained (ante at p. 413), “working conditions” which are other than “salaries, pensions and insurance” are placed within the jurisdiction of arbitrators to settle as the terms and conditions of contracts which are to have fully binding legal effect, notwithstanding that they can, or will, require expenditures of money. This is the only meaning reasonably attributable to the explicit provisions of Section 965:

“. . . with respect to a controversy over subjects other than salaries, pensions and insurance, the arbitrators shall make determinations . . . and if made by a majority . . . such determinations will be binding on both parties and the parties will enter an agreement or take whatever other action that *424may be appropriate to carry out and effectuate such binding determinations

The position being asserted by the Bidde-ford Board of Education is contrary to this plain statutory language.

Moreover, the position is irreconcilable with the full implications of the legislature’s carefully stated differentiation between the function of the arbitrators (1)

. . with respect to a controversy over . . . salaries, pensions and insurance . . .”,

that the arbitrators in such controversy

“. . . will recommend terms of settlement and may make findings of fact; such recommendations and findings . . . [to be] advisory only . . . ”

(Section 965) but (2) otherwise,

“. . . with respect to a controversy over subjects other than salaries, pensions and insurance . . .”

shall, by majority,

“. . . make determinations . binding on both parties . .

and to be embodied in an “agreement” to be entered into by the parties.

This legislative concern to point up such differences in arbitrational functioning, dependent upon whether “salaries, pensions and insurance” are involved, emphasizes precisely that (1) only as to the major items of money expenditures represented by “salaries, pensions and insurance” is the contingency of the need for appropriations recognized, thereby to require that the arbitrators act only as an advisory body making recommendations but (2) concerning all items negotiable in collective bargaining other than “salaries, pensions and insurance”, and even though such other items can and, will, involve money expenditures when they are to be implemented, the arbitrators are empowered to impose fully binding legal obligations. As to these necessary monetary expenditures resulting from such binding decisions of the arbitrators, it becomes the responsibility of the school board, as well as the appropriate legislative body of the municipality, to make such arrangements as will ensure that these legal obligations will be met. Cf. Providence Teach. U. Local 958 v. School Committee, 108 R.I. 444, 276 A.2d 762 (1971).7

III-B-4

A last issue raised for decision concerns the legal effects under the Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law flowing from the binding determinations of arbitrators acting pursuant to Section 965, subd. 4 — in particular, during the period allowed for instituting review (under Section 972) and, if review has been sought, while it is pending.

By the express language of the statute, when made

“. . . by a majority of the arbitrators . . . determinations will be binding on both parties and the parties will enter an agreement ... to *425carry out and effectuate such binding determinations.”

Hence, that at least two arbitrators have in fact settled upon determinations becomes the controlling factor by which their determinations become binding and which brings into play the legal obligation of the parties to incorporate the determinations into an agreement. The statute omits to establish an automatic suspension of legal consequences because of the potential that the arbitrational decision might embody errors causing them to be reversed or modified on review.

Any such suspension of “bindingness” or of legal obligation is allowed, by the statutory language, to come into play only to the extent that in Section 972 8 the statute prescribes that

“review shall be sought in accordance with Rule 80B of the Rules of Civil Procedure”

and that

“an appeal [from the Superior Court’s review] may be taken to the law court as in any civil action.”

As to any review “in accordance with Rule 80B . . .,” the Rule plainly provides :

“Except as otherwise provided by statute, the filing of the complaint does not stay any action of which review is sought, but the court may .order a stay upon such terms as it deems proper.”

The present statute fails to provide otherwise and, on the contrary, tends clearly to indicate that until a Court ordered stay is accomplished pursuant to Rule 80B, the ar-bitrational determinations are immediately and continuingly binding and the parties are under immediate and continuing legal duty to enter an agreement which incorporates them.

Accordingly, regardless of whether it is, or will be, claimed that determinations of arbitrators contain an “erroneous ruling or finding of law” subjecting the determinations to potential reversal or modification upon review, the determinations are, and remain, binding in their legal effect and the parties are, and remain, under the legal duty to incorporate them in a signed agreement until the party asserting a right of review achieves the intervention of judicial action in the form of such “stay” as the Superior Court sees fit to order in the circumstances.

CONCLUSION

I would remand the cases to the Superi- or Court for action, as follows:

(1) In Docket No. 2688-71, City of Biddeford by its Board of Education v. Biddeford Teachers Association, et als, the decision of the arbitration panel of November 17, 1971 is to be modified by striking therefrom the determinations concerning “Class Size”, “Length of a Teacher’s Working Day” and “Scheduling and Length of School Vacations and of the Commencement and Ending of the School Year.”

After such modification has been effected, the Superior Court should enter

Judgment affirming the decision of the arbitrational panel (as modified).

(2) In Docket No. 2690-71, Biddeford Teachers Association v. Board of Educa*426tion of City of Biddeford, et als, the case, as remanded, is to await the entry of judgment in case No. 2688-71 aforesaid. Thereafter, the Superior Court shall proceed in such manner as the subsequent conduct of the parties might make necessary or appropriate — all in accordance with the principles enunciated in this opinion.

. As to the specific subject-matter before it the 'Whitman Court observed: “While the statute does not in terms provide that the commissioner of insurance shall exercise a sound and reasonable discretion in the disapproval of proposed rules and regulations, that condition is necessarily implied. As has been said many times, in many cases administrative officers or bodies must act, not only within the field of their statutory powers, but in a reasonable and orderly manner. . The rule of reasonableness inheres in every law, and the action of those charged with its enforcement must in the nature of things be subject to the test of reasonableness.” (pp. 942, 943)

. The language of Chief Justice Hughes, writing for the majority in Panama Refining Co. v. Ryan, was: “We examine the context to ascertain if it furnishes a declaration of policy or a standard of action, which can be deemed to imply what is not there expressed.” (293 U.S. p. 416, 55 S.Ct. p. 246) In dissent Justice Cardozo explicitly added: “I concede that to uphold the delegation there is need to discover in the terms of the act a standard reasonably clear *406whereby discretion must be governed. I deny that such a standard is lacking . . . when the act with all its reasonable implications is considered as a whole.” (p. 434, 55 S.Ct. p. 25.4)

Reiterating the clear permissibility of finding standards implicit, Justice Cardozo said: “The prevailing opinion concedes that a standard will be as effective if imported ... by reasonable implication as if put there in so many words.” (p. 435, 55 S.Ct. p. 254)

. A partial explanation might be that the specific subject-matter which most frequently comes before state tribunals involves an overlay of additional and unique problems not entirely answerable by use of the “standards” conception as the sole criterion of valid “delegation” and requiring special emphasis upon prevention of arbitrary and capricious action — as, for example, licensing controls over the right of a person to earn a living in a profession, trade or business (in which one’s peers often sit on the administrative tribunal having the licensing, or revocation, power — thus giving rise to likelihood of the influence of friendship or self-interest) ; or situations involving zoning boards of appeals and their authority to decide exceptions or variances (and in which inheres the potential for favoritism and discrimination resulting from the influence of small pressure groups or other aspects of local politics). These unique features create special danger of invidious discrimination in the exercise of power — • the worse because it might be undetectable *407and therefore, unexposable by judicial review if the power is not adequately contained ; and the dangers are aggravated because in these types of proceedings there is generally an absence of evidentiary hearings conducted with reasonable procedural controls. See: Waterville Hotel Corp. v. Board of Zoning Appeals, Me., 241 A.2d 50 (1968) ; Small v. Maine Board of Registration and Examination in Optometry, Me., 293 A.2d 786 (1972).

. This approach has been taken in the present context with full awareness that much respectable current scholarship advocates (1) abandonment, even in the *410area of police power regulation and control of private rights, of the methodology which insists upon adequate “primary standards”, legislatively prescribed, ns an absolute precondition of the validity of legislative delegation and (2) reliance, rather, upon a total conglomerate of safeguards against irresponsible, arbitrary or capricious action by administrative bodies in which before-the-fact statutory standards may be a helpful, but not an indispensable, factor. Illustrative of this attitude are the following comments by Professor Kenneth Culp Davis:

“The non-delegation doctrine can and should be altered to turn it into an effective and useful judicial tool. Its purpose should no longer be either to prevent delegation of legislative power or to require meaningful statutory standards; its purpose should be the much deeper one of protecting against unnecessary and uncontrolled discretionary power. The focus should no longer be exclusively on standards; it should be on the totality of protections against arbitrariness, including both safeguards and standards.” Davis, Administrative Law Treatise (1970 Supplement, p. 40)

Compare, however, the resurgence of the directly opposite philosophy as recently advanced by Judge J. Shelly Wright in his book, review of Professor Davis’ book Discretionary Justice: A Preliminary Inquiry.

Judge Wright maintains in Beyond Discretionary Justice, 81 Yale Law Journal 575 (January, 1972):

“There must be some limit on the extent to which Congress can transfer its own powers to other bodies without guidance as to how these powers should be exercised.” (p. 582) “I think the delegation doctrine retains an important potential as a check on the exercise of unbounded, standardless discretion by administrative agencies. At its core, the doctrine is based on the notion that agency action must occur within the context of a rule of law previously formulated by a legislative body. That concept is as important now as it was a century and a half ago when it was first propounded.” (pp. 583, 584)
“Delegation is, after all, a matter of degree, and the amount of power which it is permissible to delegate to an agency varies with the problem involved. ... It will be necessary to do some systematic thinking about the degree to which various categories of problems are subject to prospective [legislative] control. We need, in short, some standards for when we should require standards. . . . [the legislature] should channel its delegations of power with prospective guidelines and standards to the greatest extent possible. But ironically, the courts may have to work out the precise contours of the requirement of prospective standards on an empirical, case-by-case basis, . . . .” (p. 587)

Finally, and to be regarded, probably, as a position mediating between the two extremes, is a recent analysis by Professor Abraham D. Sofaer in his December, 1972 Columbia Law Review article, Judicial Control of Informal Discretionary Adjudication and Enforcement, 72 Col.L.Rev. 1293.

Professor Sofaer injects a new dimension into the “standards” controversy by observations which concentrate upon the opportunity for benefits deriving from “individualized” rather than “standardized” approach. Professor Sofaer says (1):

“Even if it were reasonable to expect the courts to insist on better legislative standards, one cannot be confident that the results of such action would be salutary” (p. 1307);

and (2), in respect to Professor Davis’ position that the concern should be not so much with prospective legislative standards as with administrative rule-making,

“The current focus on rulemaking as a means of limiting and controlling discretion distracts needed attention from the use of adjudication for such purposes. A decision is a standard, at least potentially. If the relevant facts are included along with the conclusion in a statement made available to interested persons, then a decision will give guidance. . . . Decisions can narrow or control discretion just as effectively as regulations: they can turn on the special circumstances of a particular case; they can set forth principles applicable to many cases; and they can even specify the presence of a single factor as controlling.” (pp. 1314, 1315)

. The language of Section 965, subd. 3, as specifically interrelated with and carried over into Section 965, subd. 4, forcefully suggests that before either party may compel arbitration, such party, as a precondition to arbitration, must have demanded the fact-finding process to have been instituted and completed.

We need not here decide, however, whether fact-finding is a statutory prerequisite to arbitration since it will suffice for present purposes that the fact-finding process has been available and is highly likely to have been invoked.

. 20 M.R.S.A. § 1951 reads: “Each administrative unit operating public schools within the State shall grant all certified teachers, except substitute teachers as defined by the commissioner, a minimum annual sick leave of 10 school days accumulative to a minimum of 90 school days without loss of salary. Each administrative unit employing teachers who have unused sick leave accumulated in their previous positions shall accept up to 20 days of such sick leave to be transferred to the employing administrative unit, said sick leave to be credited and made effective upon achieving continuing contract status in the, new employing unit. Any other plan of sick leave which, in the opinion of the state board, provides at least equal benefits may be approved in lieu thereof. Full-time teachers assistants and teachers aides shall be granted minimum annual sick leave of 10 school days.”

. To assist the public employer (including its school board and legislative body) to deal with the legal obligations which will result if (1) issues as to “salaries, pensions and insurance” are settled by collective bargaining, or (2) any other matters requiring the appropriations of money, are settled by collective bargaining or, if collective bargaining has failed, by the binding determinations of arbitrators, the Municipal Public Employees Labor Relations Law has inserted a special provision affording the public employer the benefit of specific timing for all collective bargaining which involves money expenditures. The statute explicitly provides: “Whenever . . . any matter [s] requiring appropriation of money . are included as a matter of collective bargaining . . . , it is the obligation of the bargaining agent to serve written notice or request for collective bargaining on the public employer at least 120 days before the conclusion of the current fiscal operating budget . . . .”

. By P.L.1970 Chapter 578, § 7, a new section, Section 972, was added to govern the review of binding determinations of arbitrators.

The consolidated matters now before us are governed by these statutory changes effective (by emergency enactment) as of February 9, 1970.

It is to be observed that at the Special Session of the Legislature convened from .Tanuary 24, 1972 to March 10, 1972, other changes were made affecting the remedies for unfair labor practices which could, in future situations, have a relationship to mattex-s arising from binding arbitration and interi'elationslxips between enforcement px'oceedings and the review proceedings pi-ovided by Section 972.